Results for 'James G. Renno'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  18
    Freudenthal H.. Logique mathématique appliquée. Collection de logique mathématique, Série A, no. 14. Gauthier-Villars, Paris, and E. Nauwelaerts, Louvain, 1958, title pages + 59 pp. [REVIEW]James G. Renno - 1959 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 24 (3):256-256.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  6
    Alonzo Church. Vvédénié v matématičéskuú logiku. Russian translation of XXII 286 by V. S. Čérnávskij, edited by V. A. Uspénskij. Izdatél'stvo Inostrannoj Litératury, Moscow1960, 484 pp. [REVIEW]James G. Renno - 1962 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 27 (1):76-76.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  5
    Review: Alonzo Church, Vvedenie v Matematiceskuu Logiku. [REVIEW]James G. Renno - 1962 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 27 (1):76-76.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Review: H. Freudenthal, Logique Mathematique Appliquee. [REVIEW]James G. Renno - 1959 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 24 (3):256-256.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  15
    Aristotle's philosophy of biology: studies in the origins of life science.James G. Lennox - 2000 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    In addition to being one of the world's most influential philosophers, Aristotle can also be credited with the creation of both the science of biology and the philosophy of biology. He was the first thinker to treat the investigations of the living world as a distinct inquiry with its own special concepts and principles. This book focuses on a seminal event in the history of biology - Aristotle's delineation of a special branch of theoretical knowledge devoted to the systematic investigation (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  6. Aristotle’s Philosophy of Biology: Studies in the Origins of Life Science.James G. Lennox - 2001 - Journal of the History of Biology 36 (1):223-224.
  7. Synthesizing activities and interactions in the concept of a mechanism.James G. Tabery - 2004 - Philosophy of Science 71 (1):1-15.
    Stuart Glennan, and the team of Peter Machamer, Lindley Darden, and Carl Craver have recently provided two accounts of the concept of a mechanism. The main difference between these two versions rests on how the behavior of the parts of the mechanism is conceptualized. Glennan considers mechanisms to be an interaction of parts, where the interaction between parts can be characterized by direct, invariant, change-relating generalizations. Machamer, Darden, and Craver criticize traditional conceptualizations of mechanisms which are based solely on parts (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   95 citations  
  8.  12
    Aristotle on Inquiry: Erotetic Frameworks and Domain Specific Norms.James G. Lennox - 2020 - New York, NY, USA: Cambridge University Press.
    Aristotle is a rarity in the history of philosophy and science - he is a towering figure in the history of both disciplines. Moreover, he devoted a great deal of philosophical attention to the nature of scientific knowledge. How then do his philosophical reflections on scientific knowledge impact his actual scientific inquiries? In this book James Lennox sets out to answer this question. He argues that Aristotle has a richly normative view of scientific inquiry, and that those norms are (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  9.  16
    Andrzej Walicki, Legal Philosophies of Russian Liberalism.James G. Colbert - 1998 - Studies in East European Thought 50 (1):69-75.
  10. Darwin was a teleologist.James G. Lennox - 1993 - Biology and Philosophy 8 (4):409-421.
    It is often claimed that one of Darwin''s chief accomplishments was to provide biology with a non-teleological explanation of adaptation. A number of Darwin''s closest associates, however, and Darwin himself, did not see it that way. In order to assess whether Darwin''s version of evolutionary theory does or does not employ teleological explanation, two of his botanical studies are examined. The result of this examination is that Darwin sees selection explanations of adaptations as teleological explanations. The confusion in the nineteenth (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   82 citations  
  11.  48
    Admissible Rules and the Leibniz Hierarchy.James G. Raftery - 2016 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 57 (4):569-606.
    This paper provides a semantic analysis of admissible rules and associated completeness conditions for arbitrary deductive systems, using the framework of abstract algebraic logic. Algebraizability is not assumed, so the meaning and significance of the principal notions vary with the level of the Leibniz hierarchy at which they are presented. As a case study of the resulting theory, the nonalgebraizable fragments of relevance logic are considered.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  12.  26
    Aristotle: On the Parts of Animals.James G. Lennox (ed.) - 2002 - Clarendon Press.
    Aristotle is without question the founder of the science of biology. In his treatise On the Parts of Animals, he develops his systematic principles for biological investigation, and explanation, and applies those principles to explain why the different animal kinds have the different parts that they do. It is one of the greatest achievements in the history of science. This new translation from the Greek aims to reflect the subtlety and detail of Aristotle's reasoning. The commentary provides help in understanding (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  13.  69
    Order algebraizable logics.James G. Raftery - 2013 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 164 (3):251-283.
    This paper develops an order-theoretic generalization of Blok and Pigozziʼs notion of an algebraizable logic. Unavoidably, the ordered model class of a logic, when it exists, is not unique. For uniqueness, the definition must be relativized, either syntactically or semantically. In sentential systems, for instance, the order algebraization process may be required to respect a given but arbitrary polarity on the signature. With every deductive filter of an algebra of the pertinent type, the polarity associates a reflexive and transitive relation (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  14. Aristotelian Problems.James G. Lennox - 1994 - Ancient Philosophy 14 (S1):53-77.
  15.  87
    Natural selection and the struggle for existence.James G. Lennox & Bradley E. Wilson - 1994 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 25 (1):65-80.
  16.  25
    Rhythmic (hierarchical) versus serial structure in speech and other behavior.James G. Martin - 1972 - Psychological Review 79 (6):487-509.
  17.  46
    History and philosophy of science: A phylogenetic approach.James G. Lennox - unknown
    Kuhn closed the Introduction to The Structure of Scientific Revolutions with what was clearly intended as a rhetorical question: How could history of science fail to be a source of phenomena to which theories about knowledge may legitimately be asked to apply? (Kuhn 1970, 9) This paper argues that there is a more fruitful way of conceiving the relationship between a historical and philosophical study of science, which is dubbed the 'phylogenetic' approach. I sketch an example of this approach, and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  18.  88
    The darwin/gray correspondence 1857–1869: An intelligent discussion about chance and design.James G. Lennox - 2010 - Perspectives on Science 18 (4):456-479.
    This essay outlines one aspect of a larger collaboration with John Beatty and Alan Love.2 The project’s focus is philosophical, but for reasons that will become clear momentarily, the method of approach is historical. All three of us share the conviction that philosophical issues concerning the foundations of the sciences are often illuminated by investigating their history. It is my hope that this paper both provides support for that thesis, and illustrates it. The focal philosophical issue can be stated in (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  19. Between data and demonstration: The Analytics and the Historia Animalium.James G. Lennox - 1991 - In Alan C. Bowen (ed.), Science and Philosophy in Classical Greece. Garland. pp. 2--61.
  20.  31
    Gibson's affordances.James G. Greeno - 1994 - Psychological Review 101 (2):336-342.
  21.  21
    Inconsistency lemmas in algebraic logic.James G. Raftery - 2013 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 59 (6):393-406.
  22. Health as an objective value.James G. Lennox - 1995 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 20 (5):499-511.
    Variants on two approaches to the concept of health have dominated the philosophy of medicine, here referred to as ‘reductionist’ and ‘relativis’. These two approaches share the basic assumption that the concept of health cannot be both based on an empirical biological foundation and be evaluative, and thus adopt either the view that it is ‘objective’ or evaluative. It is here argued that there are a subset of value concepts that are formed in recognition of certain fundamental facts about living (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  23.  17
    Learning to be risk averse.James G. March - 1996 - Psychological Review 103 (2):309-319.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  24. Aristotle: On the Parts of Animals.James G. Lennox - 2003 - Philosophical Quarterly 53 (213):607-609.
    Aristotle is without question the founder of the science of biology. In his treatise On the Parts of Animals, he develops his systematic principles for biological investigation, and explanation, and applies those principles to explain why the different animal kinds have the different parts that they do. It is one of the greatest achievements in the history of science. This new translation from the Greek aims to reflect the subtlety and detail of Aristotle's reasoning. The commentary provides help in understanding (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  25.  32
    Evolution and Ethics: T.H. Huxley's Evolution and Ethics with New Essays on its Victorian and Sociobiological Context.James G. Paradis & George Christopher Williams - 1989 - Princeton University Press.
    T. H. Huxley (1825-1895) was not only an active protagonist in the religious and scientific upheaval that followed the publication of Darwin's theory of evolution but also a harbinger of the sociobiological debates about the implications of evolution that are now going on. His seminal lecture Evolution and Ethics, reprinted here with its introductory Prolegomena, argues that the human psyche is at war with itself, that humans are alienated in a cosmos that has no special reference to their needs, and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  26.  17
    Introduction.James G. Lennox & Mary Louise Gill - 2017 - In Mary Louise Gill & James G. Lennox (eds.), Self-Motion: From Aristotle to Newton. Princeton University Press.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  27.  53
    Evaluation of statistical hypotheses using information transmitted.James G. Greeno - 1970 - Philosophy of Science 37 (2):279-294.
    The main argument of this paper is that an evaluation of the overall explanatory power of a theory is less problematic and more relevant as an assessment of the state of knowledge than evaluation of statistical explanations of single occurrences in terms of likelihoods that are assigned to explananda.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  28.  5
    A Topological Account of the Space Occupied by Physical Objects.James G. Schmolze - 1996 - The Monist 79 (1):128-140.
    While physical objects exist, they occupy space. We have developed a representation for the spaces that objects can occupy that meets the following criteria.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  29.  7
    Aristotle: On the Parts of Animals.James G. Lennox (ed.) - 2002 - Clarendon Press.
    Aristotle is without question the founder of the science of biology. In his treatise On the Parts of Animals, he develops his systematic principles for biological investigation, and explanation, and applies those principles to explain why the different animal kinds have the different parts that they do. It is one of the greatest achievements in the history of science. This new translation from the Greek aims to reflect the subtlety and detail of Aristotle's reasoning. The commentary provides help in understanding (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  30. Teleology, chance, and Aristotle's theory of spontaneous generation.James G. Lennox - 1982 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 20 (3):219-238.
  31. An Aristotelian Philosophy of Biology: Form, Function and Development.James G. Lennox - 2017 - Acta Philosophica 26 (1):33-52.
    In metaphysics and philosophy of science, a significant movement is making inroads, under the banner of ‘neo-Aristotelianism’. This movement has so far been focused primarily on the physical sciences; but given that Aristotle the natural scientist was above all a biologist, it is worth asking what a neo-Aristotelian philosophy of biology would look like? In this paper, I begin a discussion on precisely that question. One interesting result is that the fact that biology is now permeated by evolutionary ways of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  32.  76
    Aristotle on genera, species, and?the more and the less?James G. Lennox - 1980 - Journal of the History of Biology 13 (2):321-346.
  33.  18
    Getting a Science Going: Aristotle on Entry Level Kinds'.James G. Lennox - 2005 - In Gereon Wolters & Martin Carrier (eds.), Homo Sapiens und Homo Faber: epistemische und technische Rationalität in Antike und Gegenwart ; Festschrift für Jürgen Mittelstrass. Berlin/New York: de Gruyter. pp. 87.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  34.  18
    Emerging Legal Threats to the Public's Health.James G. Hodge, Sarah A. Wetter, Leila Barraza, Madeline Morcelle, Danielle Chronister, Alexandra Hess, Jennifer Piatt & Walter Johnson - 2018 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 46 (2):547-551.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  35. Aristotle on the Emergence of Material Complexity: Meteorology IV and Aristotle’s Biology.James G. Lennox - 2014 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 4 (2):272-305.
    In this article I defend an account of Meteorology IV as providing a material-level causal account of the emergence of uniform materials with a wide range of dispositional properties not found at the level of the four elements—the emergence of material complexity. I then demonstrate that this causal account is used in the Generation of Animals and Parts of Animals as part of the explanation of the generation of the uniform parts (tissues) and of their role in providing nonuniform parts (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  36.  23
    Critical Notice. Rational Starting Points.James G. Edwards - 2001 - Disputatio 1 (11):33-51.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  45
    Pathological Circularity: Deductive Validity and a Contextual Account of the Fallacy of Begging the Question.James G. Edwards - unknown
    The purpose of this study is to provide an account of the fallaciousness of begging the question without thereby indicting as fallacious all otherwise acceptable deductively valid reasoning. The solution that we suggest exploits the intuition that all good arguments are weakly circular. The fallaciousness of begging the question is not that the reasoning is circular simpliciter. Rather, begging the question is a fallacy because the conclusion relies on an undischarged assumption that the audience cannot accept without further argumentation. In (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Sydney Shoemaker, The First Person Perspective and Other Essays Reviewed by.James G. Edwards - 1997 - Philosophy in Review 17 (4):283-285.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. The Theory of Epistemic Rationality, by Richard Foley.James G. Edwards - 2001 - Disputatio.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  78
    Being, Nature, and Life in Aristotle: Essays in Honor of Allan Gotthelf.James G. Lennox & Robert Bolton (eds.) - 2010 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This volume of essays explores major connected themes in Aristotle's metaphysics, philosophy of nature, and ethics, especially themes related to essence, definition, teleology, activity, potentiality, and the highest good. The volume is united by the belief that all aspects of Aristotle's work need to be studied together if any one of the areas of thought is to be fully understood. Many of the papers were contributions to a conference at the University of Pittsburgh entitled 'Being, Nature, and Life in Aristotle', (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  41.  11
    Moral Status and Human Life: The Case for Children's Superiority.James G. Dwyer - 2010 - Cambridge University Press.
    Are children of equal, lesser, or perhaps even greater moral importance than adults? This work of applied moral philosophy develops a comprehensive account of how adults as moral agents ascribe moral status to beings - ourselves and others - and on the basis of that account identifies multiple criteria for having moral status. It argues that proper application of those criteria should lead us to treat children as of greater moral importance than adults. This conclusion presents a basis for critiquing (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  42. Aristotle on Norms of Inquiry.James G. Lennox - 2011 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 1 (1):23-46.
    Where does Aristotle stand in the debate between rationalism and empiricism? The locus classicus on this question, Posterior Analytics II. 19, seems clearly empiricist. Yet many commentators have resisted this conclusion. Here, I review their arguments and conclude that they rest in part on expectations for this text that go unfulfilled. I argue that this is because his views about norms of empirical inquiry are in the rich methodological passages in his scientific treatises. In support of this claim, I explore (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  43.  34
    Variable risk preferences and the focus of attention.James G. March & Zur Shapira - 1992 - Psychological Review 99 (1):172-183.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  44.  6
    War's ends: human rights, international order, and the ethics of peace.James G. Murphy - 2014 - Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.
    Before military action, and even before mobilization, the decision on whether to go to war is debated by politicians, pundits, and the public. As they address the right or wrong of such action, it is also a time when, in the language of the just war tradition, the wise would deeply investigate their true claim to jus ad bellum (“the right of war”). Wars have negative consequences, not the least impinging on human life, and offer infrequent and uncertain benefits, yet (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. What is it with Damaris, Lady Masham?: The historiography of one early modern woman philosopher.James G. Buickerood - 2005 - Locke Studies 5:179-214.
  46.  37
    A Topological Account of the Space Occupied by Physical Objects.James G. Schmolze - 1996 - The Monist 79 (1):128-140.
    While physical objects exist, they occupy space. We have developed a representation for the spaces that objects can occupy that meets the following criteria.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47.  76
    Darwin’s Methodological Evolution.James G. Lennox - 2005 - Journal of the History of Biology 38 (1):85-99.
    A necessary condition for having a revolution named after you is that you are an innovator in your field. I argue that if Charles Darwin meets this condition, it is as a philosopher and methodologist. In 1991, I made the case for Darwin's innovative use of "thought experiment" in the "Origin." Here I place this innovative practice in the context of Darwin's methodological commitments, trace its origins back into Darwin's notebooks, and pursue Darwin's suggestion that it owes its inspiration to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  48. Aristotle on Chance.James G. Lennox - 1984 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 66 (1):52-60.
  49.  25
    Situativity and Symbols: Response to Vera and Simon.James G. Greeno & Joyce L. Moore - 1993 - Cognitive Science 17 (1):49-59.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  50. The Self Across Psychology: Self-Recognition, Self-Awareness, and the Self Concept.James G. Snodgrass & R. L. Thompson (eds.) - 1997 - New York Academy of Sciences.
1 — 50 / 1000