Results for 'Porter, Dale'

(not author) ( search as author name )
997 found
Order:
  1.  16
    Readings in Animal Cognition.Dale Jamieson & Marc Bekoff (eds.) - 1996 - MIT Press.
    Table of Contents Perspectives on Animal Cognition Chapter 1 The Myth of Anthropomorphism John Andrew Fisher Chapter 2 Gendered Knowledge? Examining Influences on Scientific and Ethological Inquiries Lori Gruen Chapter 3 Interpretive Cognitive Ethology Hugh Wilder Chapter 4 Concept Attribution in Nonhuman Animals: Theoretical and Methodological Problems in Ascribing Complex Mental Processes Colin Allen and Marc Hauser Cognitive and Evolutionary Explanations Chapter 5 On Aims and Methods of Cognitive Ethology Dale Jamieson and Marc Bekoff Chapter 6 Aspects of the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  2.  8
    Milestones in Microbiology. Thomas Dale Brock.J. R. Porter - 1963 - Isis 54 (1):147-147.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  16
    Milestones in Microbiology by Thomas Dale Brock. [REVIEW]J. Porter - 1963 - Isis 54:147-147.
  4.  11
    Dale H. Porter. The Thames Embankment: Environment, Technology,and Society in Victorian London. xvi + 318 pp., frontis., illus., bibl., index. Akron, Ohio: University of Akron Press, 1998. $49.95 ; $24.95. [REVIEW]Betsy Mendelsohn - 2002 - Isis 93 (4):741-741.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. The Significance of a Life’s Shape.Dale Dorsey - 2015 - Ethics 125 (2):303-330.
    The shape of a life hypothesis holds, very roughly, that lives are better when they have an upward, rather than downward, slope in terms of momentary well-being. This hypothesis is plausible and has been thought to cause problems for traditional principles of prudential value/rationality. In this article, I conduct an inquiry into the shape of a life hypothesis that addresses two crucial questions. The first question is: what is the most plausible underlying explanation of the significance of a life’s shape? (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  6. Subjectivism without Desire.Dale Dorsey - 2012 - Philosophical Review 121 (3):407-442.
    Subjectivism about well-being holds that ϕ is intrinsically good for x if and only if, and to the extent that, ϕ is valued, under the proper conditions, by x. Given this statement of the view, there is room for intramural dissent among subjectivists. One important source of dispute is the phrase “under the proper conditions”: Should the proper conditions of valuing be actual or idealized? What sort of idealization is appropriate? And so forth. Though these concerns are of the first (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  7. The Supererogatory, and How to Accommodate It.Dale Dorsey - 2013 - Utilitas 25 (3):355-382.
    Many find it plausible to posit a category of supererogatory actions. But the supererogatory resists easy analysis. Traditionally, supererogatory actions are characterized as actions that are morally good, but not morally required; actions that go the call of our moral obligations. As I shall argue in this article, however, the traditional analysis can be accepted only by a view with troubling consequences concerning the structure of the moral point of view. I propose a different analysis that is extensionally correct, avoids (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  8. Desire-satisfaction and Welfare as Temporal.Dale Dorsey - 2013 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 16 (1):151-171.
    Welfare is at least occasionally a temporal phenomenon: welfare benefits befall me at certain times. But this fact seems to present a problem for a desire-satisfaction view. Assume that I desire, at 10am, January 12th, 2010, to climb Mount Everest sometime during 2012. Also assume, however, that during 2011, my desires undergo a shift: I no longer desire to climb Mount Everest during 2012. In fact, I develop an aversion to so doing. Imagine, however, that despite my aversion, I am (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  9. Why should Welfare ‘Fit’?Dale Dorsey - 2017 - Philosophical Quarterly 67 (269):685-24.
    One important proposal about the nature of well-being, prudential value or the personal good is that intrinsic values for a person ought to ‘resonate’ with the person for whom they are good. Indeed, virtually everyone agrees that there is something very plausible about this necessary condition on the building blocks of a good life. Given the importance of this constraint, however, it may come as something of a surprise how little reason we actually have to believe it. In this paper, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  10. Idealization and the Heart of Subjectivism.Dale Dorsey - 2017 - Noûs 51 (1):196-217.
  11. Three arguments for perfectionism.Dale Dorsey - 2010 - Noûs 44 (1):59-79.
    Perfectionism, or the claim that human well-being consists in the development and exercise of one’s natural or essential capacities, is in growth mode. With its long and distinguished historical pedigree, perfectionism has emerged as a powerful antedote to what are perceived as significant problems in desiderative and hedonist accounts of well-being. However, perfectionism is one among many views that deny the influence of our desires, or that cut the link between well-being and a raw appeal to sensory pleasure. Other views (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  12. Prudence and past selves.Dale Dorsey - 2018 - Philosophical Studies 175 (8):1901-1925.
    An important platitude about prudential rationality is that I should not refuse to sacrifice a smaller amount of present welfare for the sake of larger future benefits. I ought, in other words, to treat my present and future as of equal prudential significance. The demands of prudence are less clear, however, when it comes to one’s past selves. In this paper, I argue that past benefits are possible in two ways, and that this fact cannot be easily accommodated by traditional (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  13. Headaches, Lives and Value.Dale Dorsey - 2009 - Utilitas 21 (1):36.
    University of Alberta Forthcoming in Utilias Consider Lives for Headaches: there is some number of headaches such that the relief of those headaches is sufficient to outweigh the good life of an innocent person. Lives for Headaches is unintuitive, but difficult to deny. The argument leading to Lives for Headaches is valid, and appears to be constructed out of firmly entrenched premises. In this paper, I advocate one way to reject Lives for Headaches; I defend a form of lexical superiority (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  14. Intrinsic value and the supervenience principle.Dale Dorsey - 2012 - Philosophical Studies 157 (2):267-285.
    An important constraint on the nature of intrinsic value---the “Supervenience Principle” (SP)---holds that some object, event, or state of affairs ϕ is intrinsically valuable only if the value of ϕ supervenes entirely on ϕ 's intrinsic properties. In this paper, I argue that SP should be rejected. SP is inordinately restrictive. In particular, I argue that no SP-respecting conception of intrinsic value can accept the importance of psychological resonance, or the positive endorsement of persons, in explaining value.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  15.  8
    The problem of the invariance of dimension in the growth of modern topology, part II.Dale M. Johnson - 1981 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 25 (2-3):85-266.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  16. Preferences and Prudential Reasons.Dale Dorsey - 2019 - Utilitas 31 (2):157-178.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  17. The Hedonist's Dilemma.Dale Dorsey - 2011 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 8 (2):173-196.
    In this paper, I argue that hedonism about well-being faces a powerful dilemma. However, as I shall try to show here, this choice creates a dilemma for hedonism. On a subjective interpretation, hedonism is open to the familiar objection that pleasure is not the only thing desired or the only thing for which we possess a pro-attitude. On an objective interpretation, hedonism lacks an independent rationale. In this paper, I do not claim that hedonism fails once and for all. However, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  18.  83
    Objective Morality, Subjective Morality, and the Explanatory Question.Dale Dorsey - 2012 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 6 (3):1-25.
    A common presupposition in metaethical theory is that moral assessment comes in two flavors, one of which is sensitive to our epistemic circumstances, the second of which is not so sensitive. Though this thought is popular, a number of questions arise. In this paper, I limit my discussion to what I dub the "explanatory question": how one might understand the construction of subjective moral assessment given an explanatorily prior objective assessment. I argue that a proper answer to this question is (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  19. Weak Anti-Rationalism and the Demands of Morality†.Dale Dorsey - 2011 - Noûs 46 (1):1-23.
    The demandingness of act consequentialism is well-known and has received much sophisticated treatment.1 Few have been content to defend AC’s demands. Much of the response has been to jettison AC in favor of a similar, though significantly less demanding view.2 The popularity of this response is easy to understand. Excessive demandingness appears to be a strong mark against any moral theory. And if excessive demandingness is a worry of this kind, AC’s goose appears cooked: attempts to show that AC is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  20.  6
    The problem of the invariance of dimension in the growth of modern topology, part I.Dale M. Johnson - 1979 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 20 (2):97-188.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  21. Adaptive Preferences Are a Red Herring.Dale Dorsey - 2017 - Journal of the American Philosophical Association 3 (4):465-484.
    ABSTRACT:Current literature in moral and political philosophy is rife with discussion of adaptive preferences. This is no accident: while preferences are generally thought to play an important role in a number of normative domains, adaptive preferences seem exceptions to this general rule—they seem problematic in a way that preference-respecting theories of these domains cannot adequately capture. Thus, adaptive preferences are often taken to be theoretically explanatory: a reason for adjusting our theories of the relevant normative domains. However, as I shall (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  22. A Perfectionist Humean Constructivism.Dale Dorsey - 2018 - Ethics 128 (3):574-602.
    In this article, I articulate and explore a novel constructivist approach to metanormativity that is inspired by David Hume’s metaesthetics. This view, which I call perfectionist Humean constructivism, rejects the claim that practical reasons are constructed by each individual’s valuing attitudes, holding instead that they are constructed by humanity’s shared evaluative nature. I hold that this approach can plausibly respond to a persistent worry for extant versions of Humean constructivism without embracing the commitments of either a Kantian constructivism or a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  23.  74
    Future-Bias: A (Qualified) Defense.Dale Dorsey - 2016 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 98 (S1):351-373.
    The preferences of ordinary folks typically display a future‐bias. For instance, we care more about pains and pleasures in our future than pains and pleasures in our past. Indeed, this future‐bias is so pervasive, many have taken it for granted that the preferences of rational agents will, or at least can, display this future‐bias to some degree or other. However, the rationality of future‐biased preferences has recently come in for critique. However, in this article, I offer a defense of future‐biased (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  24.  49
    Moral Distinctiveness and Moral Inquiry.Dale Dorsey - 2016 - Ethics 126 (3):747-773.
    Actions can be moral or immoral, surely, but can also be prudent or imprudent, rude or polite, sportsmanlike or unsportsmanlike, and so on. The fact that diverse methods of evaluating action exist seems to give rise to a further question: what distinguishes moral evaluation in particular? In this article, my concern is methodological. I argue that any account of the distinctiveness of morality cannot be prior to substantive inquiry into the content of moral reasons, requirements, and concerns. The genuine distinctiveness (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  25. Equality-tempered prioritarianism.Dale Dorsey - 2014 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 13 (1):45-61.
    In this paper, I present and explore an alternative to a standard prioritarian axiology. Equality-tempered prioritarianism holds that the value of welfare increases should be balanced against the value of equality. However, given that, under prioritarianism, the value of marginal welfare benefits decreases as the welfare of beneficiaries increases, equality-tempered prioritarianism holds that the intrinsic value of equality will be sufficient to alter a prioritarian verdict only in cases in which welfare benefits are granted to the very well-off. I argue (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  26. A Coherence Theory of Truth in Ethics.Dale Dorsey - 2006 - Philosophical Studies 127 (3):493-523.
    Quine argues, in “On the Nature of Moral Values” that a coherence theory of truth is the “lot of ethics”. In this paper, I do a bit of work from within Quinean theory. Specifically, I explore precisely what a coherence theory of truth in ethics might look like and what it might imply for the study of normative value theory generally. The first section of the paper is dedicated to the exposition of a formally correct coherence truth predicate, the possibility (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  27.  37
    History and historiography in process.Anders Schinkel - 2004 - History and Theory 43 (1):39–56.
    Although in philosophical dictionaries and the like, Alfred North Whitehead is often praised as one of the most original thinkers of the twentieth century, his work has been virtually ignored. The articles and books that are concerned with Whitehead’s philosophy, with the exception of the work of Dale H. Porter, hardly ever mention the relevance that it has for the philosophy of history and for historiography. I intend to demonstrate this relevance in this article. For this purpose, I will (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Preferences, welfare, and the status-quo bias.Dale Dorsey - 2010 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 88 (3):535-554.
    Preferences play a role in well-being that is difficult to escape, but whatever authority one grants to preferences, their malleability seems to cause problems for any theory of well-being that employs them. Most importantly, preferences appear to display a status-quo bias: people come to prefer what they are likely rather than unlikely to get. I try to do two things here. The first is to provide a more precise characterization of the status-quo bias, how it functions, and how it infects (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  29. Consequentialism, Metaphysical Realism and the Argument from Cluelessness.Dale Dorsey - 2012 - Philosophical Quarterly 62 (246):48-70.
    Lenman's ‘argument from cluelessness’ against consequentialism is that a significant percentage of the consequences of our actions are wholly unknowable, so that when it comes to assessing the moral quality of our actions, we are without a clue. I distinguish the argument from cluelessness from traditional epistemic objections to consequentialism. The argument from cluelessness should be no more problematic for consequentialism than the argument from epistemological scepticism should be for metaphysical realism. This puts those who would reject consequentialism on the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  30. Toward a theory of the basic minimum.Dale Dorsey - 2008 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 7 (4):423-445.
    Many have thought that an important feature of any just society is the establishment and maintenance of a suitable basic minimum: some set of welfare achievements, resources, capabilities, and so on that are guaranteed to all. However, if a basic minimum is a plausible requirement of justice, we must have a theory — a theory of what, precisely, the state owes in terms of these basic needs or achievements and what, precisely, is the proper structure of the obligation to provide (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  31. How Not to Argue Against Consequentialism.Dale Dorsey - 2013 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 90 (1):20-48.
  32. Can instrumental value be intrinsic?Dale Dorsey - 2012 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 93 (2):137-157.
    In this article, I critique a common claim that instrumental value is a form of extrinsic value. Instead, I offer an alternative dispositional analysis of instrumental value, which holds that instrumental value can, in certain circumstances, be an example of intrinsic value. It follows, then, that a popular account of the nature of final value – or value as an end – is false: the Moorean identification of final value with intrinsic value cannot properly distinguish between value as an end (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  33. Looking To Understand: The Coupling Between Speakers' and Listeners' Eye Movements and Its Relationship to Discourse Comprehension.Daniel C. Richardson & Rick Dale - 2005 - Cognitive Science 29 (6):1045-1060.
    We investigated the coupling between a speaker's and a listener's eye movements. Some participants talked extemporaneously about a television show whose cast members they were viewing on a screen in front of them. Later, other participants listened to these monologues while viewing the same screen. Eye movements were recorded for all speakers and listeners. According to cross-recurrence analysis, a listener's eye movements most closely matched a speaker's eye movements at a delay of 2 sec. Indeed, the more closely a listener's (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  34.  64
    On fellowship.Dale Dorsey - 2024 - Philosophical Studies 181 (1):133-152.
    This paper explores a form of communion between persons that the philosophy of value has a tendency to ignore. In discussions of interpersonal relationships and experiences, focus is almost always directed to the phenomenon of friendship and family: two or more individuals that share a history, have longstanding relationships of mutual care. Friendship is said, among other things, to be of intrinsic value, to directly benefit the friend, to generate special obligations, and to yield advances in a person’s virtue. But (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. A Good Death.Dale Dorsey - 2017 - Utilitas 29 (2):153-174.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  36.  88
    Respecting the Game: Blame and Practice Failure.Dale Dorsey - 2019 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 101 (3):683-703.
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, EarlyView.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37. Hutcheson’s Deceptive Hedonism.Dale Dorsey - 2010 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 48 (4):445-467.
    Francis Hutcheson’s theory of value is often characterized as a precursor to the qualitative hedonism of John Stuart Mill. The interpretation of Mill as a qualitative hedonist has come under fire recently; some have argued that he is, in fact, a hedonist of no variety at all.1 Others have argued that his hedonism is as non-qualitative as Bentham’s.2 The purpose of this essay is not to critically engage the various interpretations of Mill’s value theory. Rather, I hope to show that (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  38.  88
    The Normative Significance of Self.Dale Dorsey - 2016 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 10 (1):1-25.
    A number of recent works in the metaethics of practical rationality have suggested that features of a person’s character, commitments, projects, practical identities and social roles have important normative consequences. For instance, I might commit to caring for a loved one, or I might become an artist, or take on the role of father to a child. In each case, it seems right to say that the normative landscape I face has been altered by this new fact – to put (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  39. Aggregation, Partiality, and the Strong Beneficence Principle.Dale Dorsey - 2009 - Philosophical Studies 146 (1):139 - 157.
    Consider the Strong Beneficence Principle (SBP): Persons of affluent means ought to give to those who might fail basic human subsistence until the point at which they must give up something of comparable moral importance. This principle has been the subject of much recent discussion. In this paper, I argue that no coherent interpretation of SBP can be found. SBP faces an interpretive trilemma, each horn of which should be unacceptable to fans of SBP; SBP is either (a) so strong (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  40. The evolution of moral belief: support for the debunker’s causal premise.Michael T. Dale - 2022 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 44 (2):1-18.
    The causal premise of the evolutionary debunking argument contends that human moral beliefs are explained by the process of natural selection. While it is universally acknowledged that such a premise is fundamental to the debunker’s case, the vast majority of philosophers focus instead on the epistemic premise that natural selection does not track moral truth and the resulting skeptical conclusion. Recently, however, some have begun to concentrate on the causal premise. So far, the upshot of this small but growing literature (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  80
    The Cognitive Dynamics of Negated Sentence Verification.Rick Dale & Nicholas D. Duran - 2011 - Cognitive Science 35 (5):983-996.
    We explored the influence of negation on cognitive dynamics, measured using mouse‐movement trajectories, to test the classic notion that negation acts as an operator on linguistic processing. In three experiments, participants verified the truth or falsity of simple statements, and we tracked the computer‐mouse trajectories of their responses. Sentences expressing these facts sometimes contained a negation. Such negated statements could be true (e.g., “elephants are not small”) or false (e.g., “elephants are not large”). In the first experiment, as predicted by (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  42.  50
    The Dynamics of Reference and Shared Visual Attention.Rick Dale, Natasha Z. Kirkham & Daniel C. Richardson - 2011 - Frontiers in Psychology 2.
  43.  25
    Response to Heathwood and Bradley.Dale Dorsey - 2024 - Res Philosophica 101 (1):151-161.
  44.  12
    Geschichte des Mannigfaltigkeitsbegriffs von Riemann bis Poincare. Erhard Scholz.Dale M. Johnson - 1983 - Isis 74 (4):591-592.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  25
    Handbook of the History of General Topology, Volume 1. C. E. Aull, R. Lowen.Dale M. Johnson - 2001 - Isis 92 (3):645-645.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  19
    The Chinese Theatre in Modern Times: From 1840 to the Present Day.Dale R. Johnson & Colin MacKerras - 1979 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 99 (3):492.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  23
    Effect of distance and size of standard object on the development of shape constancy.Dale W. Kaess, S. Dziurawiec Haynes, M. J. Craig, S. C. Pearson & J. Greenwell - 1974 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 102 (1):17.
  48.  16
    Form constancy and the perceptual task: A developmental study.Dale W. Kaess - 1970 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 83 (3p1):465.
  49.  25
    Κισσβιον.A. M. Dale - 1952 - The Classical Review 2 (3-4):129-132.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  50.  58
    Objectivity and Perfection in Hume’s Hedonism.Dale Dorsey - 2015 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 53 (2):245-270.
    In this paper, I investigate David Hume’s theory of well-being or prudential value. That Hume was some sort of hedonist is typically taken for granted in discussions of his value theory, but I argue that Hume was a hedonist of pathbreaking sophistication. His hedonism intriguingly blends traditional hedonism with a form of perfectionism yielding a version of qualitative hedonism that not only solves puzzles surrounding Hume’s moral theory, but is interesting and important in its own right.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
1 — 50 / 997