Results for 'patient‘s duties'

998 found
Order:
  1.  57
    The patient's duty to adhere to prescribed treatment: An ethical analysis.David B. Resnik - 2005 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 30 (2):167 – 188.
    This article examines the ethical basis for the patient's duty to adhere to the physician's treatment prescriptions. The article argues that patients have a moral duty to adhere to the physician's treatment prescriptions, once they have accepted treatment. Since patients still retain the right to refuse medical treatment, their duty to adhere to treatment prescriptions is a prima facie duty, which can be overridden by their other ethical duties. However, patients do not have the right to refuse to adhere (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  2.  32
    Can “Giving Preference to My Patients” be Explained as a Role Related Duty in Public Health Care Systems?Søren Holm - 2011 - Health Care Analysis 19 (1):89-97.
    Most of us have two strong intuitions (or sets of intuitions) in relation to fairness in health care systems that are funded by public money, whether through taxation or compulsory insurance. The first intuition is that such a system has to treat patients (and other users) fairly, equitably, impartially, justly and without discrimination. The second intuition is that doctors, nurses and other health care professionals are allowed to, and may even in some cases be obligated to give preference to the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  3.  18
    Do not resuscitate decisions: discussions with patients.S. G. Schade & H. Muslin - 1989 - Journal of Medical Ethics 15 (4):186-190.
    The problem of psychological pain caused by discussions of do not resuscitate status with patients is addressed. Case histories of patients with such distress are given. We propose that not all patients should be informed of their do not resuscitate status, that the information about such status be given incrementally, and that the giving of further information be guided by the patient's reaction to earlier information. While some affirm the duty of the physician always to inform the patient about his (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  4.  87
    Exercising restraint: autonomy, welfare and elderly patients.S. Dodds - 1996 - Journal of Medical Ethics 22 (3):160-163.
    Despite moves to enhance the autonomy of clients of health care services, the use of a variety of physical restraints on the freedom of movement of frail, elderly patients continues in nursing homes. This paper confronts the use of restraints on two grounds. First, it challenges the assumption that use of restraints is necessary to protect the welfare of frail, elderly patients by drawing on a range of data indicating the limited efficacy of restraints. Secondly, it argues that the duty (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  5.  30
    Medical Futility and Physician Assisted Death.Nancy S. Jecker - 2015 - In Michael Cholbi & Jukka Varelius (eds.), New Directions in the Ethics of Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia. Cham: Springer Verlag. pp. 203-223.
    This chapter addresses the close association between withholding and withdrawing futile life-sustaining medical treatments and assisting patients with hastening ending their lives. Section 12.2 sets forth a definition of medical futility and places this concept in the broader context of bioethical principles of autonomy, beneficence, nonmaleficence and justice. Section 12.3 draws out futility’s ethical implications and considers the view that physicians are ethically permitted to refrain from medically futile treatments, should be encouraged to refrain, or have a duty to refrain. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  44
    Familial genetic risks: how can we better navigate patient confidentiality and appropriate risk disclosure to relatives?Edward S. Dove, Vicky Chico, Michael Fay, Graeme Laurie, Anneke M. Lucassen & Emily Postan - 2019 - Journal of Medical Ethics 45 (8):504-507.
    This article investigates a high-profile and ongoing dilemma for healthcare professionals, namely whether the existence of a duty of care to genetic relatives of a patient is a help or a hindrance in deciding what to do in cases where a patient’s genetic information may have relevance to the health of the patient’s family members. The English case ABC v St George’s Healthcare NHS Trust and others considered if a duty of confidentiality owed to the patient and a putative duty (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  7.  53
    The Gettier Problem in informed consent.S. Cohen - 2011 - Journal of Medical Ethics 37 (11):642-645.
    The duty to procure informed consent (IC) from patients before any significant intervention is among the pillars of medical and research ethics. The provision by the doctor of relevant information about treatment and free decision-making by the patient are essential elements of IC. The paper presents cases of IC where the free decision about treatment is not causally related to the information provided, and claims that such cases pose a difficulty parallel to that presented by the Gettier Problem in epistemology. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  8. Medical Futility: The Duty Not to Treat.Nancy S. Jecker & Lawrence J. Schneiderman - 1993 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2 (2):151.
    Partly because physicians can “never say never,” partly because of the seduction of modern technology, and partly out of misplaced fear of litigation, physicians have increasingly shown a tendency to undertake treatments that have no realistic expectation of success. For this reason, we have articulated common sense criteria for medical futility. If a treatment can be shown not to have worked in the last 100 cases, we propose that it be regarded as medically futile. Also, if the treatment fails to (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  9.  39
    Genetic Information, the Principle of Rescue, and Special Obligations.S. Matthew Liao & Jordan MacKenzie - 2018 - Hastings Center Report 48 (3):18-19.
    In “Genetic Privacy, Disease Prevention, and the Principle of Rescue,” Madison Kilbride argues that patients have a duty to warn biological family members about clinically actionable adverse genetic findings. The duty does not stem from the special obligations that we may have to family members, she argues, but rather follows from the principle of rescue, which she understands as the idea that one ought to prevent, reduce, or mitigate the risk of harm to another person when the expected harm is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10.  13
    Pom + ebm = cpd?S. D. Black - 2000 - Journal of Medical Ethics 26 (4):229-230.
    There are many ways of combining three letters out of an alphabet of 26; yet still there are overlaps which can confuse meaning. So the first duty of anyone using an acronym is to say what it denotes. Here, POM is “problem-oriented medicine”, EBM is “evidence-based medicine”, and CPD is “continuous professional development”. These designations, familiar as they are to clinicians, define what is meant by these terms, but fall well short of describing them for the general reader, something which (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  16
    White coat ceremonies--another commentary.S. M. Glick - 2003 - Journal of Medical Ethics 29 (6):367-368.
    I shared Raanan Gillon’s1 surprise at Robert Veatch’s criticism of the white coat ceremonies,2 and I think that the points raised by Veatch were quite adequately countered by Gillon’s response. The provocative points raised by Veatch do stimulate some valuable critical thinking about the process, although I think Veatch was carried away a bit by hyperbole. To label the drama of the ceremony as “ominous” goes a bit far by any criterion.I should like to describe an oath taking initiation ceremony (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  12.  27
    Repetitive foreign body ingestion: ethical considerations.S. Lytle, S. J. Stagno & B. Daly - 2013 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 24 (2):91-97.
    The treatment of persons who frequently present to the healthcare system following repetitive foreign body ingestion has been addressed in the psychiatric literature. However, there has been little exploration of the ethical considerations regarding the treatment of these patients. The complexity of their medical and psychiatric presentation raises fundamental ethical questions regarding the duty to treat, patient autonomy, justice, and futility. Careful ethical analysis is particularly important in this context, since the frustration that medical professionals may feel in response may (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  9
    Navigating Pandemic Moral Distress at Home and at Work: Frontline Workers’ Experiences.S. A. Miner, B. E. Berkman, V. Altiery de Jesus, L. Jamal & C. Grady - 2022 - AJOB Empirical Bioethics 13 (4):215-225.
    Background: During the COVID-19 pandemic, frontline workers faced a series of challenges balancing family and work responsibilities. These challenges included making decisions about how to reduce COVID-19 exposure to their families while still carrying out their employment duties and caring for their children. We sought to understand how frontline workers made these decisions and how these decisions impacted their experiences.Methods: Between October 2020 and May 2021, we conducted 61 semi-structured interviews in English or Spanish, with individuals who continued to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. When Push Comes to Shove—How Should Physicians Respond to Magical Thinking?Søren Holm - 2020 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 31 (1):86-88.
    Should doctors shove their patients to choose in ways that are aligned with the patients’ desired goals, when the patients’ choices go wrong because of magical beliefs? I argue that doctors should not shove their patients in this way, but push them towards better and more reflective decision making. We can do this by nudging techniques or by more direct advice giving. If patients still choose wrongly, it is their choice, and doctors have fulfilled their professional, ethical duties.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Integrating medical ethics with normative theory: Patient advocacy and social responsibility.Nancy S. Jecker - 1990 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 11 (2).
    It is often assumed that the chief responsibility medical professionals bear is patient care and advocacy. The meeting of other duties, such as ensuring a more just distribution of medical resources and promoting the public good, is not considered a legitimate basis for curtailing or slackening beneficial patient services. It is argued that this assumption is often made without sufficient attention to foundational principles of professional ethics; that once core principles are laid bare this assumption is revealed as largely (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  16.  76
    The ethical professional as endangered person: blog notes on doctor-patient relationships.T. Koch & S. Jones - 2010 - Journal of Medical Ethics 36 (6):371-374.
    In theory, physicians subscribe to and in their actions personify a set of virtues whose performance demands personal engagement. At the same time, they are instructed in their professional roles to remain emotionally and personally distant from those they are called to treat. The result, the authors argue, is an ethical conflict whose nature is described through an analysis of two narratives drawn from an online blog for young physicians. Confusion over professional responsibilities and personal roles were found to affect (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  17.  54
    Informed consent: Patient's right or patient's duty?Richard T. Hull - 1985 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 10 (2):183-198.
    The rule that a patient should give a free, fully-informed consent to any therapeutic intervention is traditionally thought to express merely a right of the patient against the physician, and a duty of the physician towards the patient. On this view, the patient may waive that right with impugnity, a fact sometimes expressed in the notion of a right not to know. This paper argues that the rule also expresses a duty of the patient towards the physician and a right (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  18.  10
    Implementation of an Ethics Committee in a University Mental Health Clinic.M. Azcárraga & S. Derive - 2024 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 21 (1):177-184.
    Mental disorders in university students are very frequent, therefore higher education institutions have established in-campus mental healthcare centres. These clinics have particular characteristics that differ from other mental health centres, as they report to and represent an educational institution, while at the same time looking after the interests and well-being of patients requesting assistance, thus generating unique bioethical conflicts. Ethics Committees are useful tools to offer support to mental health professionals in making ethical decisions. In order to respond to these (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  10
    Відмова від лікування і вбивство: Шляхи розрізнення.Kateryna S. Rassudina - 2020 - Вісник Харківського Національного Університету Імені В. Н. Каразіна. Серія «Філософія. Філософські Перипетії» 62:157-164.
    One of the key problems facing bioethics concerns those cases where, due to the limited human and technical resources of medicine, patients are in fact doomed to die. The reason for withdrawing treatment may be the futility of using the available means, as well as the burden of certain procedures. In the contemporary world, euthanasia is offered as an alternative to withdrawing treatment, that is, direct causing the death of a patient, killing. They distinguish these two types of practice by (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  7
    Pandemics and Beyond: Considerations When Personal Risk and Professional Obligations Converge.Douglas S. Diekema, Joan S. Roberts, Mithya Lewis-Newby & Daniel J. Benedetti - 2021 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 32 (1):20-34.
    With each novel infectious disease outbreak, there is scholarly attention to healthcare providers’ obligation to assume personal risk while they care for infected patients. While most agree that healthcare providers have a duty to assume some degree of risk, the extent of this obligation remains uncertain. Furthermore, these analyses rarely examine healthcare institutions’ obligations during these outbreaks. As a result, there is little practical guidance for healthcare institutions that are forced to weigh whether or when to exclude healthcare providers from (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21. Public Health Doctors' Ancillary-Care Obligations.H. S. Richardson - 2010 - Public Health Ethics 3 (1):63-67.
    This comment on the case presented in ‘Cholera and Nothing More’ argues that the physicians at this public-health centre did not have an ordinary clinician's obligations to promote the health of the people who came to them for care, as they were instead set up to serve a laudable and urgent public-health goal, namely, controlling a cholera outbreak. It argues that, nonetheless, these physicians did have some limited moral duties to care for other diseases they encountered—some ancillary-care duties—arising (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  13
    A world away and here at home: a prioritisation framework for US international patient programmes.Emily Berkman, Jonna Clark, Douglas Diekema & Nancy S. Jecker - 2022 - Journal of Medical Ethics 48 (8):557-565.
    Programmes serving international patients are increasingly common throughout the USA. These programmes aim to expand access to resources and clinical expertise not readily available in the requesting patients’ home country. However, they exist within the US healthcare system where domestic healthcare needs are unmet for many children. Focusing our analysis on US children’s hospitals that have a societal mandate to provide medical care to a defined geographic population while simultaneously offering highly specialised healthcare services for the general population, we assume (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  32
    Supererogation and altruism: a comment.R. S. Downie - 2002 - Journal of Medical Ethics 28 (2):75-76.
    Supererogation can be distinguished from altruism, in that the former is located in the category of duty but exceeds the strict requirements of duty, whereas altruism belongs to a different moral category from duty. It follows that doctors do not act altruistically in their professional roles. Individual doctors may sometimes show supererogation, but supererogation is not a necessary feature of the medical profession. The aim of medicine is to act in the best interests of patients. This aim involves neither supererogation (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  24.  11
    “What are my options?”: Physicians as ontological decision architects in surgical informed consent.Stacy S. Chen & Sunit Das - 2022 - Bioethics 36 (9):936-939.
    The aim of a theoretically ideal process of informed consent is to promote the autonomy of the patient and to limit unethical physician paternalism. However, in practice, the nature of the medical profession requires physicians to act as ontological decision architects—based on the medical knowledge that they acquire through their experience and training, physicians ontologically determine a subset of viable courses of action for their patient. What is observed is not an unethical physician limitation or biasing of the patient towards (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  14
    “What are my options?”: Physicians as ontological decision architects in surgical informed consent.Stacy S. Chen & Sunit Das - 2022 - Bioethics 36 (9):936-939.
    The aim of a theoretically ideal process of informed consent is to promote the autonomy of the patient and to limit unethical physician paternalism. However, in practice, the nature of the medical profession requires physicians to act as ontological decision architects—based on the medical knowledge that they acquire through their experience and training, physicians ontologically determine a subset of viable courses of action for their patient. What is observed is not an unethical physician limitation or biasing of the patient towards (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  16
    Characterization of nurses’ duty to care and willingness to report.Charleen McNeill, Danita Alfred, Tracy Nash, Jenifer Chilton & Melvin S. Swanson - 2020 - Nursing Ethics 27 (2):348-359.
    Background:Nurses must balance their perceived duty to care against their perceived risk of harm to determine their willingness to report during disaster events, potentially creating an ethical dilemma and impacting patient care.Research aim:The purpose of this study was to investigate nurses’ perceived duty to care and whether there were differences in willingness to respond during disaster events based on perceived levels of duty to care.Research design:A cross-sectional survey research design was used in this study.Participants and research context:Using a convenience sample (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27. Timothy F. Murphy.A. Patient'S. Right To Know - 1994 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 19 (4-6):553-569.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  15
    The National Commission on AIDS.Donald S. Goldman & Jeff Stryker - 1991 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 1 (4):339-345.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The National Commission on AIDSDonald S. Goldman (bio) and Jeff Stryker (bio)A decade after the first cases were recognized in the United States, AIDS continues to vex policymakers and fascinate the public. It has been said that AIDS acts as a prism, refracting a spectrum of controversial topics. For bioethicists, these topics include: equity in the allocation of resources for treatment and research; forgoing life-sustaining care and proxy decision (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  18
    When is Public Disclosure of HIV Seropositivity Acceptable?Adamson S. Muula & Joseph M. Mfutso-Bengo - 2005 - Nursing Ethics 12 (3):288-295.
    HIV/AIDS is a major public health problem in Africa. Stigmatization, discrimination and lack of appropriate health care are among the commonest challenges that HIV infected persons and their families face. It has been suggested that among the tools available in the fight against stigmatization and discrimination is public disclosure of a person’s HIV seropositive status. While public disclosure of HIV status has a place in the fight against HIV and AIDS, especially by resulting in behavioural change among people who know (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  72
    The Immortal Life of Henrietta Lacks, Feminist Themes, and Research Ethics.Lisa S. Parker - 2012 - International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 5 (1):159-165.
    In 1951 Henrietta Lacks felt a lump in her cervix, entered Johns Hopkins Hospital, and was examined in a colored-only exam room by a physician who biopsied the lump. Called back to Hopkins for treatment of diagnosed carcinoma of the cervix, Henrietta signed a one-line “Operation Permit,” and under general anesthesia received her first round of radium treatment. Before sewing a tube of radium into her cervix, the surgeon on duty took samples of tumor and healthy tissue, and as with (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  9
    Distressed Work: Chronic Imperatives and Distress in Covid‐19 Critical Care.Neelima Navuluri, Harris S. Solomon, Charles W. Hargett & Peter S. Kussin - 2023 - Hastings Center Report 53 (1):33-45.
    This ethnographic study introduces the term “distressed work” to describe the emergence of chronic frictions between moral imperatives for health care workers to keep working and the dramatic increase in distress during the Covid‐19 pandemic. Interviews and observant participation conducted in a hospital intensive care unit during the Covid‐19 pandemic reveal how health care workers connected job duties with extraordinary emotional, physical, and moral burdens. We explore tensions between perceived obligations of health care professionals and the structural contexts of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  13
    The Boundaries of “Good Behavior” and Judicial Competence: Exploring Responsibilities and Authority Limitations of Cognitive Specialists in the Regulation of Incapacitated Judges.Brandon Hamm & Bryn S. Esplin - 2018 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 46 (2):514-520.
    Both law and medicine rely on self-regulation and codes of professionalism to ensure duties are performed in a competent, ethical manner. Unlike physicians, however, judges are lawyers themselves, so judicial oversight is also self-regulation. As previous literature has highlighted, the hesitation to report a cognitively-compromised judge has resulted in an “opensecret” amongst lawyers who face numerous conflicts of interest.Through a case study involving a senior judge with severe cognitive impairment, this article considers the unique ethical dilemmas that cognitive specialists (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  36
    Kidney transplant tourism: cases from Canada.L. Wright, J. S. Zaltzman, J. Gill & G. V. R. Prasad - 2013 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 16 (4):921-924.
    Canada has a marked shortfall between the supply and demand for kidneys for transplantation. Median wait times for deceased donor kidney transplantation vary from 5.8 years in British Columbia, 5.2 years in Manitoba and 4.5 years in Ontario to a little over 2 years in Quebec and Nova Scotia. Living donation provides a viable option for some, but not all people. Consequently, a small number of people travel abroad to undergo kidney transplantation by commercial means. The extent to which they (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34.  8
    Staffing crisis capacity: a different approach to healthcare resource allocation for a different type of scarce resource.Catherine R. Butler, Laura B. Webster & Douglas S. Diekema - forthcoming - Journal of Medical Ethics.
    Severe staffing shortages have emerged as a prominent threat to maintaining usual standards of care during the COVID-2019 pandemic. In dire settings of crisis capacity, healthcare systems assume the ethical duty to maximise aggregate population-level benefit of existing resources. To this end, existing plans for rationing mechanical ventilators and intensive care unit beds in crisis capacity focus on selecting individual patients who are most likely to survive and prioritising these patients to receive scarce resources. However, staffing capacity is conceptually different (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  19
    Nurses’ values on medical aid in dying: A qualitative analysis.Judy E. Davidson, Liz Stokes, Marcia S. DeWolf Bosek, Martha Turner, Genesis Bojorquez, Youn-Shin Lee & Michele Upvall - 2022 - Nursing Ethics 29 (3):636-650.
    Aim: Explore nurses’ values and perceptions regarding the practice of medical aid in dying. Background: Medical aid in dying is becoming increasing legal in the United States. The laws and American Nurses Association documents limit nursing involvement in this practice. Nurses’ values regarding this controversial topic are poorly understood. Methodology: Cross-sectional electronic survey design sent to nurse members of the American Nurses Association. Inductive thematic content analysis was applied to open-ended comments. Ethical Considerations: Approved by the institutional review board (#191046). (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  40
    The cultural context of patient’s autonomy and doctor’s duty: passive euthanasia and advance directives in Germany and Israel. [REVIEW]Silke Schicktanz, Aviad Raz & Carmel Shalev - 2010 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 13 (4):363-369.
    The moral discourse surrounding end-of-life (EoL) decisions is highly complex, and a comparison of Germany and Israel can highlight the impact of cultural factors. The comparison shows interesting differences in how patient’s autonomy and doctor’s duties are morally and legally related to each other with respect to the withholding and withdrawing of medical treatment in EoL situations. Taking the statements of two national expert ethics committees on EoL in Israel and Germany (and their legal outcome) as an example of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  37.  37
    Is the patient's right to die evolving into a duty to die?: Medical decision making and ethical evaluations in health care.Charles L. Sprung, Leonid A. Eidelman & Avraham Steinberg - 1997 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 3 (1):69-75.
  38.  59
    Doctor-cared dying instead of physician-assisted suicide: a perspective from Germany. [REVIEW]Fuat S. Oduncu & Stephan Sahm - 2010 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 13 (4):371-381.
    The current article deals with the ethics and practice of physician-assisted suicide (PAS) and dying. The debate about PAS must take the important legal and ethical context of medical acts at the end of life into consideration, and cannot be examined independently from physicians’ duties with respect to care for the terminally ill and dying. The discussion in Germany about active euthanasia, limiting medical intervention at the end of life, patient autonomy, advanced directives, and PAS is not fundamentally different (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  39.  25
    Personalized medicine, digital technology and trust: a Kantian account.Bjørn K. Myskja & Kristin S. Steinsbekk - 2020 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 23 (4):577-587.
    Trust relations in the health services have changed from asymmetrical paternalism to symmetrical autonomy-based participation, according to a common account. The promises of personalized medicine emphasizing empowerment of the individual through active participation in managing her health, disease and well-being, is characteristic of symmetrical trust. In the influential Kantian account of autonomy, active participation in management of own health is not only an opportunity, but an obligation. Personalized medicine is made possible by the digitalization of medicine with an ensuing increased (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40.  21
    The Physician’s Duty to Treat in Emergencies: Accepting Patients in Transfer.Ellen Fox - 1994 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 5 (1):43-45.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  1
    A Physician’s Duty to Treat MERS-CoV Patients? An Ethical Assessment.Norman K. Swazo - 2014 - Eubios Journal of Asian and International Bioethics 24 (3):81-86.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  1
    The Neonatologist's Duty to Patient and Parents.Carson Strong - 1984 - Hastings Center Report 14 (4):10-16.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  22
    Hospital Consent for Disclosure of Medical Records.Jon F. Merz, Pamela Sankar & Simon S. Yoo - 1998 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 26 (3):241-248.
    Physicians and other health care providers owe ethical and legal duties to patients to maintain the secrecy of the information learned during the course of patient care. This obligation is fulfilled by limiting access to such information to only those involved in the patient's care-that is, to those within the “circle of confidentiality.” As a general rule, providers may only disclose to others with the written prior consent of the patient. Exceptions may be “ethically and legally justified because of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  14
    Hospital Consent for Disclosure of Medical Records.Jon F. Merz, Pamela Sankar & Simon S. Yoo - 1998 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 26 (3):241-248.
    Physicians and other health care providers owe ethical and legal duties to patients to maintain the secrecy of the information learned during the course of patient care. This obligation is fulfilled by limiting access to such information to only those involved in the patient's care-that is, to those within the “circle of confidentiality.” As a general rule, providers may only disclose to others with the written prior consent of the patient. Exceptions may be “ethically and legally justified because of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  35
    Calvin and the Duty to Respect a Patient's Trust.D. T. Ball - 2014 - Christian Bioethics 20 (1):112-122.
    Contemporary bioethical theory relies upon the concept of informed consent to protect against abuses of patient autonomy. Due to the complexity of the informed consent process, however, many patients rely more on their trust in their health care providers than they do upon their own ability to decide whether or not to give informed consent. Reformation theologian John Calvin placed a strong emphasis on the decision-maker's duty to respect the trust that others repose in the decision-maker. In keeping with Calvin's (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  17
    Ethical obligation and legal requirements: On informed consent practices in Bangladesh.Sonia Mannan, Jobair Alam, K. M. Ashbarul Bari, S. M. A. A. Mamun & Rehnuma Mehzabin Orin - 2023 - Developing World Bioethics 23 (3):252-259.
    Informed consent to medical intervention is fundamental in both ethics and law. But in practice it is often not taken seriously in developing countries. This paper provides an appraisal of informed consent practices in Bangladesh. Following a review of the ethical and legal principles of informed consent, it assesses the degree to which doctors adhere to it in Bangladesh. Based on findings of non-compliance, it then investigates the reasons for such non-compliance through an appraisal of informed consent practices in Bangladesh (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  7
    Profits and Professions: Essays in Business and Professional Ethics.Wade L. Robison, Michael S. Pritchard & Joseph Ellin - 1983 - Springer Verlag.
    Suppose an accountant discovers evidence of shady practices while ex amining the books of a client. What should he or she do? Accountants have a professional obligation to respect the confidentiality of their cli ents' accounts. But, as an ordinary citizen, our accountant may feel that the authorities ought to be informed. Suppose a physician discov ers that a patient, a bus driver, has a weak heart. If the patient contin ues bus driving even after being informed of the heart (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48.  12
    Pre-decision regret before transition of dependents with severe dementia to long-term care.Ingrid Hanssen, Flora M. Mkhonto, Hilde Øieren, Malmsey L. M. Sengane, Anne Lene Sørensen & Phuong Thai Minh Tran - 2022 - Nursing Ethics 29 (2):344-355.
    Background: To place a dependent with severe dementia in a nursing home is a painful and difficult decision to make. In collectivistic oriented societies or families, children tend to be socialised to care for ageing parents and to experience guilt and shame if they violate this principle. Leaving the care to professional caregivers does not conform with the cultural expectations of many ethnic groups and becomes a sign of the family’s moral failure. Research design: Qualitative design with individual in-depth interviews (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  22
    Effect of Financial Relationships on the Behaviors of Health Care Professionals: A Review of the Evidence. [REVIEW]Christopher Robertson, Susannah Rose & Aaron S. Kesselheim - 2012 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 40 (3):452-466.
    Physicians, scholars, and policymakers continue to be concerned about conflicts of interests among health care providers. At least two main types of objections to conflicts of interest exist. Conflicts of interests may be intrinsically troublesome if they violate providers’ fiduciary duties to their patients or they contribute to loss of trust in health care professionals and the health care system. Conflicts of interest may also be problematic in practice if they bias the decisions made by providers, adversely impacting patient (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  50.  50
    Medicine's Duty to Treat Pandemic Illness: Solidarity and Vulnerability.Howard Brody & Eric N. Avery - 2009 - Hastings Center Report 39 (1):40-48.
    Most accounts of why physicians have a duty to treat patients during a pandemic look to the special ethical standards of the medical profession. An adequate account must be deeper and broader: it must set the professional duty alongside other individual commitments and broader social values.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
1 — 50 / 998