Results for 'fiduciary relationship'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Fiduciary Relationship: An Ethical Approach and a Legal Concept?Margaret Brazier & Mary Lobjoit - 2001 - In Rebecca Bennett & Charles A. Erin (eds.), Hiv and Aids, Testing, Screening, and Confidentiality. Clarendon Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  32
    The Fiduciary Relationship Model for Managing Clinical Genomic “Incidental” Findings.Gabriel Lázaro-Muñoz - 2014 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 42 (4):576-589.
    This paper examines how the application of legal fiduciary principles , can serve as a framework to promote management of clinical genomic “incidental” or secondary target findings that is patient-centered and consistent with recognized patient autonomy rights. The application of fiduciary principles to the clinical genomic testing context gives rise to at least four physician fiduciary duties in conflict with recent recommendations by the American College of Medical Genetics and Genomics . These recommendations have generated much debate (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  3. Trust, Autonomy, and the Fiduciary Relationship.Carolyn McLeod & Emma Ryman - 2020 - In Paul Miller & Matthew Harding (eds.), Fiduciaries and Trust: Ethics, Politics, Economics, and Law. Cambridge, UK: pp. 74-86.
    Some accounts of the fiduciary relationship place trust and autonomy at odds with one another, so that trusting a fiduciary to act on one’s behalf reduces one’s ability to be autonomous. In this chapter, we critique this view of the fiduciary relationship (particularly bilateral instances of this relationship) using contemporary work on autonomy and ‘relational autonomy’. Theories of relational autonomy emphasize the role that interpersonal trust and social relationships play in supporting or hampering one’s (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  4.  31
    The Fiduciary Relationship Model for Managing Clinical Genomic “Incidental” Findings.Gabriel Lázaro-Muñoz - 2014 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 42 (4):576-589.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  5.  11
    Ethics of the fiduciary relationship between patient and physician: the case of informed consent.Sophie Ludewigs, Jonas Narchi, Lukas Kiefer & Eva C. Winkler - forthcoming - Journal of Medical Ethics.
    This paper serves two purposes: first, the proposition of an ethical fiduciary theory that substantiates the often-cited assertion that the patient–physician relationship is fiduciary in nature; and second, the application of this theory to the case of informed consent. Patients’ decision-making preferences vary significantly. While some seek fully autonomous decision-making, others prefer to delegate parts of their decision. Therefore, we propose an ethical fiduciary theory that allows physician and patient to jointly determine the physician’s role on (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6.  11
    Property as a Fiduciary Relationship and the Extension of Economic Democracy.David Casassas & Jordi Mundó - 2022 - Theoria 69 (171):74-96.
    During the last two centuries, property understood as an exclusive and unlimited dominion became common sense. Before, the idea of property as a fiduciary relationship, which is still present in contemporary social constitutionalism, was closely linked to the view that the exercise of freedom entails the capacity to shape those property rights that channel socioeconomic life. Today, new ways to operationalise such an approach must be found. This article explores the scope of ‘direct strategies’ and ‘indirect strategies’ in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  30
    Trust and fiduciary relationships in education: What happens when trust is breached?Elizabeth Mary Grierson - 2018 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 50 (2):203-211.
    This paper examines trust as a fundamental aspect of fiduciary relationships in education. The specific relationship under examination is that of academic employee and university employer. Both have the value of trust assigned to them as an implicit part of their social and professional contract. The setting is Australia, but the principles apply to any democratic jurisdiction and educational level or location, where fiduciary principles are a pre-condition for healthy and trustworthy working relationships. The paper firstly discusses (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  33
    Fashioning legal authority from power: The crown-native fiduciary relationship.Evan Fox-Decent - manuscript
    The prevailing view in Canada of the Crown-Native fiduciary relationship is that it arose as a consequence of the Crown taking on the role of intermediary between First Nations and British settlers eager to acquire Aboriginal lands. First Nations are sometimes deemed to have surrendered their sovereignty in exchange for Crown protection. The author suggests that the sovereignty-for-protection argument does not supply a compelling account of how Aboriginal peoples lost their sovereignty to the Crown. Furthermore, Aboriginal treaties compel (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  6
    Do Researchers and Subjects Have a Fiduciary Relationship?Angela R. Holder - 1982 - IRB: Ethics & Human Research 4 (1):6.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10.  13
    Covert Video Surveillance in Pediatric Care: The Fiduciary Relationship with a Child.Steven R. Leuthner - 2004 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 15 (2):173-175.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  16
    Looking for democracy in fiduciary government. Historical notes on an unsettled relationship.David Guerrero - 2020 - Daimon: Revista Internacional de Filosofía 81:17-32.
    Una perspectiva reciente sobre los fundamentos normativos del derecho público ha propuesto concebir las relaciones entre ciudadanía y Estado como una “relación fiduciaria”, usando deberes fiduciarios del ámbito iusprivado para justificar limitaciones jurídicas y morales al poder del Estado. La gobernanza fiduciaria también ha sido señalada como una característica distintiva del republicanismo y la soberanía popular, ya que sitúa a la comunidad política como fideicomitente y beneficiaria de cualquier acto administrativo. En este artículo se revisan algunas concepciones protomodernas del gobierno (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  37
    The fiduciary constitution of human rights: Evan fox-decent and Evan J. criddle.Evan Fox-Decent - 2009 - Legal Theory 15 (4):301-336.
    We argue that human rights are best conceived as norms arising from a fiduciary relationship that exists between states and the citizens and noncitizens subject to their power. These norms draw on a Kantian conception of moral personhood, protecting agents from instrumentalization and domination. They do not, however, exist in the abstract as timeless natural rights. Instead, they are correlates of the state's fiduciary duty to provide equal security under the rule of law, a duty that flows (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  13. Fiduciary Duties and the Ethics of Public Apology.Alice MacLachlan - 2018 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 35 (2):359-380.
    The practice of official apology has a fairly poor reputation. Dismissed as ‘crocodile tears’ or cheap grace, such apologies are often seen by the public as an easy alternative to more punitive or expensive ways of taking real responsibility. I focus on what I call the role-playing criticism: the argument that someone who offers an apology in public cannot be appropriately apologetic precisely because they are only playing a role. I offer a qualified defence of official apologies against this objection, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  14.  26
    Fiduciary Duties and Moral Blackmail.Simon Keller - 2018 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 35 (3):481-495.
    In meeting legal or professional fiduciary obligations, a fiduciary can sometimes come to share a special moral relationship with her beneficiary. Special moral relationships produce special moral obligations. Sometimes the obligations faced by a fiduciary as a result of her moral relationship with her beneficiary go beyond the obligations involved in the initial fiduciary relationship. How such moral obligations develop is sometimes under the control of the beneficiary, or of an outside party. As (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  12
    Cancelling fiduciary excuses.Robert E. Goodin - forthcoming - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy.
    In trust relationships, one person has a ‘beneficial interest’ in another’s performance. The former not only would but should benefit from the latter’s action, and the latter has a ‘fiduciary duty’ toward the former to so act. But where that act would otherwise be wrong, the first person’s beneficial interest would be providing a pro tanto reason for the second person to do something that is pro tanto wrong. That reason can – and should – be removed by the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  35
    Fiduciary Duties and Moral Blackmail.Simon Keller - 2017 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 34 (2).
    In meeting legal or professional fiduciary obligations, a fiduciary can sometimes come to share a special moral relationship with her beneficiary. Special moral relationships produce special moral obligations. Sometimes the obligations faced by a fiduciary as a result of her moral relationship with her beneficiary go beyond the obligations involved in the initial fiduciary relationship. How such moral obligations develop is sometimes under the control of the beneficiary, or of an outside party. As (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  12
    Fiduciary requirements for virtual assistants.Leonie Koessler - 2024 - Ethics and Information Technology 26 (2):1-18.
    Virtual assistants (VAs), like Amazon’s Alexa, Google’s Assistant, and Apple’s Siri, are on the rise. However, despite allegedly being ‘assistants’ to users, they ultimately help firms to maximise profits. With more and more tasks and leeway bestowed upon VAs, the severity as well as the extent of conflicts of interest between firms and users increase. This article builds on the common law field of fiduciary law to argue why and how regulators should address this phenomenon. First, the functions of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  75
    The fiduciary nature of state legal authority.Evan Fox-Decent - manuscript
    The fundamental interaction that triggers a fiduciary obligation is the exercise by one party of discretionary power of an administrative nature over another party's interests, where the latter party is unable, as a matter of fact or law, to exercise the fiduciary's power. The goal of this paper is to demonstrate that there is something "deeply fiduciary" about the interaction between a state and its subjects. The fiduciary nature of this relationship provides the justification for (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  19.  50
    Fiduciary Obligation in Clinical Research.Paul B. Miller & Charles Weijer - 2006 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 34 (2):424-440.
    Heated debate surrounds the question whether the relationship between physician-researcher and patient-subject is governed by a duty of care. Miller and Weijer argue that fiduciary law provides a strong legal foundation for this duty, and for articulating the terms of the relationship between physician-researcher and patient-subject.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  20.  23
    Fiduciary Obligation in Clinical Research.Paul B. Miller & Charles Weijer - 2006 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 34 (2):424-440.
    Bioethics is currently witnessing unprecedented debate over the moral and legal norms governing the conduct of clinical research. At the center of this debate is the duty of care in clinical research, and its most widely accepted specification, clinical equipoise. In recent work, we have argued that equipoise and cognate concepts central to the ethics of clinical research have been left unnecessarily vulnerable to criticism. We have suggested that the vulnerability lies in the conspicuous absence of an articulated foundation in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  21.  28
    Digital health fiduciaries: protecting user privacy when sharing health data.Chirag Arora - 2019 - Ethics and Information Technology 21 (3):181-196.
    Wearable self-tracking devices capture multidimensional health data and offer several advantages including new ways of facilitating research. However, they also create a conflict between individual interests of avoiding privacy harms, and collective interests of assembling and using large health data sets for public benefits. While some scholars argue for transparency and accountability mechanisms to resolve this conflict, an average user is not adequately equipped to access and process information relating to the consequences of consenting to further uses of her data. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  28
    Fiduciary Paradox and Psychotherapy.Dennis E. Skocz - 2003 - Philosophy in the Contemporary World 10 (1):69-74.
    In the psychotherapist-patient relationship, the therapist-fiduciary must deal with ambiguity, assume risks, and make decisions without final appeal to psychiatric theory. Ambiguity regarding patient autonomy poses treatment paradoxes. Caregiving that aims at autonomy can end up undermining it. Additionally, pursuit of autonomy can put the patient’s well-being at risk.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  7
    Fiduciary Paradox and Psychotherapy.Dennis E. Skocz - 2003 - Philosophy in the Contemporary World 10 (1):69-74.
    In the psychotherapist-patient relationship, the therapist-fiduciary must deal with ambiguity, assume risks, and make decisions without final appeal to psychiatric theory. Ambiguity regarding patient autonomy poses treatment paradoxes. Caregiving that aims at autonomy can end up undermining it. Additionally, pursuit of autonomy can put the patient’s well-being at risk.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Trust and Fiduciary Law.Matthew Harding - 2013 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 33 (1):81-102.
    How can it be that the fiduciary relationship has trust at its core if trust is neither a necessary nor a sufficient condition for the existence of such a relationship? My aim in this article is to make some arguments that I think might assist in solving that puzzle. First, I argue that fiduciary relationships are likely to be characterized by relatively ‘thick’ interpersonal trust. Secondly, I argue that moral duties referring to trust play a role (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  25.  16
    Trust, Covert Surveillance and Fiduciary Obligations.Wayne Vaught - 2003 - Philosophy in the Contemporary World 10 (1):87-92.
    Health professionals, by agreeing to provide care, accept a fiduciary role that entails an obligation to preserve trust. We trust health professionals to be competent, to promote patient interests, and to properly utilize their discretionary power. While some health professionals argue that such activities as secretly screening for drugs or sexually transmitted diseases are necessary to fulfill their fiduciary obligations, these may actually constitute a breach of trust. In this paper, I argue that, in the specific case of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  41
    Doctors as fiduciaries: do medical professionals have the right not to treat?Edwin C. Hui - 2005 - Poiesis and Praxis 3 (4):256-276.
    In the first part of the paper, the author discusses the origin and obligation of the medical profession and argues that the duty of fidelity in the context of a patient–professional relationship (PPR) is the central obligation of medical professionals. The duty of fidelity entails seeking the patient’s best interests even at the expense of the professional’s own, and refusing to treat a risk-patient infected by SARS is a breach of fidelity because the medical professional is involved in a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27.  59
    Reason, Rationality, and Fiduciary Duty.Steve Lydenberg - 2014 - Journal of Business Ethics 119 (3):365-380.
    This paper argues that since the last decades of the twentieth century the discipline of modern finance has directed fiduciaries to act "rationally"—that is, in the sole financial interest of their funds--downplaying the effects of their investments on others. This approach has deemphasized a previous, more "reasonable" interpretation of fiduciary duty that drew on a conception of prudence characterized by wisdom, discretion and intelligence—one that accounts to a greater degree for the relationship between one's investments and their effects (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  28.  31
    Guarding the Fiduciary's Conscience—A Justification of a Stringent Profit-stripping Rule.Irit Samet - 2008 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 28 (4):763-781.
    This article argues that considerations of moral psychology support the traditional stringency of the rule according to which fiduciaries who get involved in a potential conflict of interest shall be stripped of all their gains. The application of the rule, regardless of good faith on the part of the fiduciary, is being contested by courts and academia alike. The article is focused on the ‘deterrence’ justification for the rule, and argues that its unusual strictness should be read as a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  29.  8
    An Opportunity to Reconsider Fiduciary Framing in Medicine.Jennifer L. Herbst - 2023 - American Journal of Bioethics 23 (12):46-48.
    In their target article, Doernberg and Truog (2023) correctly recognize that the doctor-patient relationship is considered a “fiduciaryrelationship (i.e., other-regarding rather than self-interes...
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  10
    Philosophical Foundations of Fiduciary Law.Andrew S. Gold & Paul B. Miller (eds.) - 2014 - Oxford University Press.
    Fiduciary law is one of the most important areas of private law, governing a wide range of relationships that affect people in their daily lives. These new and innovative essays explore the foundations of fiduciary relationships and the duties fiduciaries owe to their beneficiaries.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  9
    Philosophical Foundations of Fiduciary Law.Andrew S. Gold & Paul B. Miller (eds.) - 2014 - Oxford University Press UK.
    Fiduciary law is one of the most important areas of law, governing a wide range of relationships that affect people in their daily lives. These new and innovative essays explore the foundations of fiduciary relationships and the duties of loyalty fiduciaries owe to their beneficiaries.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  22
    The Clinical Investigator as Fiduciary: Discarding a Misguided Idea.E. Haavi Morreim - 2005 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 33 (3):586-598.
    One of the most important questions in the ethics of human clinical research asks what obligations investigators owe the people who enroll in their studies. Research differs in many ways from standard care - the added uncertainties, for instance, and the nontherapeutic interventions such as diagnostic tests whose only purpose is to measure the effects of the research intervention. Hence arises the question whether a physician engaged in clinical research has the same obligations toward research subjects that he owes his (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  33.  29
    The Clinical Investigator as Fiduciary: Discarding a Misguided Idea.E. Haavi Morreim - 2005 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 33 (3):586-598.
    One of the most important questions in the ethics of human clinical research asks what obligations investigators owe the people who enroll in their studies. Research differs in many ways from standard care - the added uncertainties, for instance, and the nontherapeutic interventions such as diagnostic tests whose only purpose is to measure the effects of the research intervention. Hence arises the question whether a physician engaged in clinical research has the same obligations toward research subjects that he owes his (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  34.  22
    Sovereignty's Promise: The State as Fiduciary.Evan Fox-Decent - 2011 - Oxford University Press.
    Arguing that the state and its people stand in a fiduciary relationship, Sovereignty's Promise puts forward a bold new account of political authority and its legal limits. In doing so it presents a fresh argument for common law constitutionalism and a novel theoretical framework for understanding the requirements of the rule of law.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  35.  52
    Ethical Standards for Stockbrokers: Fiduciary or Suitability? [REVIEW]James J. Angel & Douglas McCabe - 2013 - Journal of Business Ethics 115 (1):183-193.
    What are the ethical obligations of the sellers of financial products to their customers? Stockbrokers in the U.S. have a legal and ethical requirement to recommend only “suitable” investments to their customers. This is a fairly weak standard. Currently, there are proposals to raise the standard to a fiduciary one in which the recommendations would have to be in the best interests of the clients. Brokers sell solutions to financial problems. Similar to an auto mechanic or a doctor, the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  36.  21
    Theorising the Fiduciary: Ontology and Ethics.Helen J. Mussell - 2023 - Journal of Business Ethics 186 (2):293-307.
    Despite the omnipresence of the fiduciary in business organisations, there is an omission of theorisations of this legal concept within business ethics literature. This is surprising considering its widespread and embedded use, but even more so given that the presence of ethics within the fiduciary is increasingly contested ground. This article addresses both issues by theorising the fiduciary using an ontological analysis—one which subsequently helps identify a suitable ethical framework. The article argues on two grounds that the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Introduction for the Special Issue on Fiduciary Ethics.Robert Paul Churchillstiv Fleishmanjoe Frank Jones Iii - 2003 - Philosophy in the Contemporary World 10 (1):5-10.
    At a minimum, a fiduciary is one who is entrusted to act for the benefit of others. But as the essays in this volume indicate, fiduciary relationships can be conceived or argued to be thicker and/or more robust. In addition to a relation of trust and action on behalf of another, fiduciary relationships are often thought to include some or all of the following additions: asymmetries of power, knowledge, skill or ability; discretion or reasonable judgment on the (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  18
    The Silenced and Unsought Beneficiary: Investigating Epistemic Injustice in the Fiduciary.Helen Mussell - forthcoming - Business Ethics Quarterly:1-23.
    This article uses philosopher Miranda Fricker’s work on epistemic injustice to shed light on the legal concept of the fiduciary, alongside demonstrating the wider contribution Fricker’s work can make to business ethics. Fiduciary, from the Latin fīdūcia, meaning “trust,” plays a fundamental role in all financial and business organisations: it acts as a moral safeguard of the relationship between trustee and beneficiary. The article focuses on the ethics of the fiduciary, but from a unique historical perspective, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  39.  82
    Review of Sovereignty’s Promise: The State as Fiduciary by Evan Fox-Decent. [REVIEW]Matthew Lister - 2012 - Ethics 123 (1):150-4.
    In Sovereignty’s Promise: The State as Fiduciary, Evan Fox-Decent uses the idea of fiduciary relationships to explain the legitimate exercise of governmental authority. He makes use of the idea of the state as a fiduciary for the people to ground an account of the duty to obey the law, to explain the proper relationships between colonial (or “settler”) societies and aboriginal populations, the role of agency discretion and judicial review in the administrative state, the rule of law, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  71
    Reconceptualising the Doctor–Patient Relationship: Recognising the Role of Trust in Contemporary Health Care.Zara J. Bending - 2015 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 12 (2):189-202.
    The conception of the doctor–patient relationship under Australian law has followed British common law tradition whereby the relationship is founded in a contractual exchange. By contrast, this article presents a rationale and framework for an alternative model—a “Trust Model”—for implementation into law to more accurately reflect the contemporary therapeutic dynamic. The framework has four elements: an assumption that professional conflicts with patient safety, motivated by financial or personal interests, should be avoided; an onus on doctors to disclose these (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  41.  22
    The Moral Patient, the Honorable Fiduciary, and a Faltering Liberalism: An Exploration of Professor Bryant's Call to Animal Respect.Iris J. Goodwin - 2013 - Between the Species 16 (1):10.
    Professor Bryant’s article – which seeks to discover whether aspects of an anticruelty statute can be based directly on a call to virtuous conduct – is a provocative piece of scholarship that harbors a much larger question: Can a general principle mandating full respect for animals be developed out of the moral methodology inhering in virtue ethics? Insights garnered in this rejoinder are meant to stand alongside those in Professor Bryant’s article to lend deep moral grounding to animal-respect as well (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  28
    Balancing Rights and Trust: Towards a Fiduciary Common Future.A. T. Nuyen - 2011 - Asian Philosophy 21 (1):83-95.
    If the current trend is any guide, it looks like we are heading towards a future in which relationships are determined and regulated by rights. In addition to the ?universal human rights? declared soon after the Second World War, other ?universal rights? have been declared and added to the list of rights, such as the rights of the child, the rights of indigenous peoples and so on. A question arises as to whether a world in which our relationships are governed (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. Understanding the Relationship Between Autonomy and Informed Consent: A Response to Taylor.Lucie White - 2013 - Journal of Value Inquiry 47 (4):483-491.
    Medical ethicists conventionally assume that the requirement to employ informed consent procedures is grounded in autonomy. It seems intuitively plausible that providing information to an agent promotes his autonomy by better allowing him to steer his life. However, James Taylor questions this view, arguing that any notion of autonomy that grounds a requirement to inform agents turns out to be unrealistic and self-defeating. Taylor thus contends that we are mistaken about the real theoretical grounds for informed consent procedures. Through analysing (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44.  37
    The Patient-Physician Relationship and the Allocation of Scarce Resources: A Law and Economics Approach.Maxwell J. Mehlman & Susan R. Massey - 1994 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 4 (4):291-308.
    Patients with insufficient financial resources place physicians in a conflict of interest between the patients' needs and the financial interests of the physician, other patients, and society. Not only must physicians act ethically, but they must avoid liability for violating their legal duties to their patients. The traditional rules of contract and malpractice law that govern the patient-physician relationship do not provide satisfactory guidelines. Better answers are found in the rules of fiduciary law, but only with regard to (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  27
    The doctor-patient relationship and euthanasia.G. E. Jones - 1982 - Journal of Medical Ethics 8 (4):195-198.
    The author offers grounds for preferring a `fiduciary' model of the doctor-patient relationship to either an `authoritative' or a `contractual' model. Within this framework he suggests that certain acts of euthanasia could be accommodated not in any way as duties, but as supererogatory acts of kindness to the patient.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  22
    Effect of Financial Relationships on the Behaviors of Health Care Professionals: A Review of the Evidence. [REVIEW]Christopher Robertson, Susannah Rose & Aaron S. Kesselheim - 2012 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 40 (3):452-466.
    Physicians, scholars, and policymakers continue to be concerned about conflicts of interests among health care providers. At least two main types of objections to conflicts of interest exist. Conflicts of interests may be intrinsically troublesome if they violate providers’ fiduciary duties to their patients or they contribute to loss of trust in health care professionals and the health care system. Conflicts of interest may also be problematic in practice if they bias the decisions made by providers, adversely impacting patient (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  47.  12
    Inserting microethics into paediatric clinical care: A consideration of the models of the doctor-patient relationship.S. Lutchman - 2023 - South African Journal of Bioethics and Law 16 (2):59.
    Microethics is about the ethics of everyday clinical practice. The subtle nuances in communication between doctor and patient (the doctor’s choice of words, tone, body language, gestures, etc.) can influence the exercise of the patient’s autonomy. The four models of the doctor- patient/physician-patient relationship (paternalistic, informative, interpretive, deliberative) weigh respect for autonomy and beneficence in varying proportions. Each model may be appropriate in certain circumstances. This article considers these models from the perspective of microethics and the unique dimensions created (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  14
    Assessing Public Reason Approaches to Conscientious Objection in Healthcare.Doug McConnell - forthcoming - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics:1-11.
    Sometimes healthcare professionals conscientiously refuse to treat patients despite the patient requesting legal, medically indicated treatments within the professionals’ remit. Recently, there has been a proliferation of views using the concept of public reason to specify which conscientious refusals of treatment should be accommodated. Four such views are critically assessed, namely, those of Robert Card, Massimo Reichlin, David Scott, and Doug McConnell. This paper argues that McConnell’s view has advantages over the other approaches because it combines the requirement that healthcare (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  22
    The patient‐worker: A model for human research subjects and gestational surrogates.Emma Ryman & Katy Fulfer - 2017 - Developing World Bioethics 18 (4):310-320.
    We propose the ‘patient-worker’ as a theoretical construct that responds to moral problems that arise with the globalization of healthcare and medical research. The patient-worker model recognizes that some participants in global medical industries are workers and are owed worker's rights. Further, these participants are patient-like insofar as they are beneficiaries of fiduciary relationships with healthcare professionals. We apply the patient-worker model to human subjects research and commercial gestational surrogacy. In human subjects research, subjects are usually characterized as either (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50. An Exploratory Analysis, 1 Geo J.Lawyer Relationships - 1987 - Legal Ethics 15.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000