Results for 'Virtue jurisprudence'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Virtue jurisprudence a virtue–centred theory of judging.Lawrence B. Solum - 2003 - Metaphilosophy 34 (1/2):178--213.
    Virtue jurisprudence” is a normative and explanatory theory of law that utilises the resources of virtue ethics to answer the central questions of legal theory. The main focus of this essay is the development of a virtue–centred theory of judging. The exposition of the theory begins with exploration of defects in judicial character, such as corruption and incompetence. Next, an account of judicial virtue is introduced. This includes judicial wisdom, a form of phronesis, or sound (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  2.  54
    Virtue jurisprudence.Colin Patrick Farrelly & Lawrence Solum (eds.) - 2008 - New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.
  3.  55
    The Limits of Virtue Jurisprudence.R. A. Duff - 2003 - Metaphilosophy 34 (1-2):214-224.
    In response to Lawrence Solum's advocacy of a ‘virtue–centred theory of judging’, I argue that there is indeed important work to be done in identifying and characterising those qualities of character that constitute judicial virtues – those qualities that a person needs if she is to judge well (though I criticise Solum's account of one of the five pairs of judicial vices and virtues that he identifies – avarice and temperance). However, Solum's more ambitious claims – that a judge's (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  4. Solum, Virtue Jurisprudence: A Virtue-centred Theory of Judging.B. Lawrence - 2003 - Metaphilosophy 34 (1/2).
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  40
    The virtues and vices of virtue jurisprudence.R. A. Duff - 2006 - In Timothy Chappell (ed.), Values and Virtues: Aristotelianism in Contemporary Ethics. Oxford University Press.
  6. The virtues and vices of virtue jurisprudence.Antony Duff - 2006 - In Timothy Chappell (ed.), Values and Virtues: Aristotelianism in Contemporary Ethics. Clarendon Press.
  7.  15
    Law, virtue and justice.Amalia Amaya & Hock Lai Ho (eds.) - 2012 - Portland, Or.: Hart Publishing.
    This book explores the relevance of virtue theory to law from a variety of perspectives. The concept of virtue is central in both contemporary ethics and epistemology. In contrast, in law, there has not been a comparable trend toward explaining normativity on the model of virtue theory. In the last few years, however, there has been an increasing interest in virtue theory among legal scholars. 'Virtue jurisprudence' has emerged as a serious candidate for a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  8.  10
    Virtue and the Normativity of Law.Amalia Amaya - 2022 - Ancient Philosophy Today 4 (Supplement):111-133.
    This paper examines the normativity of law, that is, law’s capacity to guide behavior by generating reasons for action, from the perspective of virtue jurisprudence. It articulates a virtue-based model of law’s normativity according to which the law generates first order reasons for action (that is, loyalty-reasons) that need to be factored in citizens’ and legal officials’ practical reasoning, which consists, primarily, in the search for the best specification of the values involved in light of an account (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  12
    Wealth and Virtue: The Shaping of Political Economy in the Scottish Enlightenment.Istvan Hont & Michael Ignatieff (eds.) - 1986 - Cambridge University Press.
    Wealth and Virtue reassesses the remarkable contribution of the Scottish Enlightenment to the formation of modern economics and to theories of capitalism. Its unique range indicates the scope of the Scottish intellectual achievement of the eighteenth century and explores the process by which the boundaries between economic thought, jurisprudence, moral philosophy and theoretical history came to be established. Dealing not only with major figures like Hume and Smith, there are also studies of lesser known thinkers like Andrew Fletcher, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  10.  32
    The Criterions of the Scientific Character of Jurisprudence in the Modern Legal Philosophy.Saulius Arlauskas - 2009 - Jurisprudencija: Mokslo darbu žurnalas 118 (4):247-264.
    In this article the paradoxical role of legal science in legal practice is discussed. On the one hand, legal scientists do not agree on the criterions of the scientific character of legal science. On the other hand, even in the legal cases that are especially complicated it is possible to arrive at theoretically unquestionable decisions. The author of the article concludes that legal practice is based on fundamental theoretical insights; however, in legal practice these insights are used more intuitively than (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  4
    Law, Virtue, and Public Health Powers.Eric C. Ip - 2021 - Public Health Ethics 14 (2):148-160.
    This article contributes to philosophical reflections on public health law by drawing on virtue jurisprudence, which rests on the straightforward observation that a political community and its laws will inevitably shape the character of its officials and subjects, and that an excellent character is indispensable to fulfilment. Thus, the law is properly set to encourage virtue and discourage vice. This opens a new perspective onto the ultimate purpose of public health law that is human flourishing. The means (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12. Recent Work in Applied Virtue Ethics.Guy Axtell & Philip Olson - 2012 - American Philosophical Quarterly 49 (3):183-204.
    The use of the term "applied ethics" to denote a particular field of moral inquiry (distinct from but related to both normative ethics and meta-ethics) is a relatively new phenomenon. The individuation of applied ethics as a special division of moral investigation gathered momentum in the 1970s and 1980s, largely as a response to early twentieth- century moral philosophy's overwhelming concentration on moral semantics and its apparent inattention to practical moral problems that arose in the wake of significant social and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  35
    Virtue, Vice and the Criminal Law - A Response to Huigens and Yankah.R. A. Duff - 2013 - In H. H. Lai & A. Amaya (eds.), Law, Virtue and Justice. Oxford: Hart Publishing. pp. 195-214.
    First paragraph: It is worth distinguishing two kinds of role that ideas of virtue and vice might play in the criminal law (or in our theoretical understanding of the criminal law). Each kind admits of a range of variations; each can be more or less ambitious in scope and aim: but although there are of course quite close connections between the two kinds, we can usefully sketch them as two different ways of developing a virtue jurisprudence of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  21
    The Virtues of Everyday Talk: The Enduring Significance of John Milton’s Theory of Expressive Liberties.Chloé Bakalar - 2021 - Political Theory 49 (4):584-612.
    The system of free expression John Milton defends in Areopagitica, a pamphlet against prior restraint in publishing, is often characterized as merely a proto-liberal, truth-based marketplace of ideas theory. But this represents a misunderstanding of Milton’s views on the freedoms of conscience, speech, and the press. The tendency in political theory, philosophy, and law to reduce the “free speech Milton” to Areopagitica, and the reduction of that essay to several soundbites, has meant sidelining both the significant exceptions to expressive liberties (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  56
    Introduction to ‘Virtue and Law’ symposium.Amalia Amaya & Claudio Michelon - 2018 - Jurisprudence 9 (1):1-5.
    This short piece is the introduction to the Special Issue on ‘Virtue and the Law’ published by Jurisprudence in March 2019 (vol 9, issue 1). It explains the scope of the project and its place in the unfolding of virtue jurisprudence that has occurred in the past few decades, as well as introducing the topics addressed in the volume. In the first couple of pages the authors/editors outline a very brief genealogy of virtue jurisprudence (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  48
    The virtue of judicial humility.Amalia Amaya - 2018 - Jurisprudence 9 (1):97-107.
    This paper articulates an egalitarian conception of judicial humility and justifies its value on the grounds that it importantly advances the legal and political ideal of fraternity. This account of the content and value of the virtue of humility stands in sharp contrast with the dominant view of judicial humility as deference or judicial restraint. The paper concludes by discussing some ways in which the account of humility and of its value provided in the paper furthers our understanding of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  17.  37
    The Demarcation Problem in Jurisprudence: A New Case for Scepticism.Brian Leiter - 2011 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 31 (4):663-677.
    Legal philosophers have been preoccupied with specifying the differences between two systems of normative guidance that are omnipresent in all modern human societies: law and morality. Positivists propose a solution to this ‘Demarcation Problem’ according to which the legal validity of a norm cannot depend on its being morally valid, either in all or at least some possible legal systems. The proposed analysis purports to specify the essential and necessary features of law in virtue of which this is true. (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  18.  65
    A virtue-centered account of equity and the rule of law.Lawrence B. Solum - 2007 - In Colin Patrick Farrelly & Lawrence Solum (eds.), Virtue jurisprudence. Palgrave-Macmillan.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. On Naturalizing Jurisprudence: Some Comments on Brian Leiter’s View of What Jurisprudence Should Become.Julie Dickson - 2011 - Law and Philosophy 30 (4):477-497.
    In a series of powerful and challenging articles emerging since the mid-1990s, Brian Leiter has argued that certain theoretical strains in contemporary legal philosophy are ‘epistemologically bankrupt’, in virtue of their reliance on misguided argumentative devices: analysing concepts, such as the concepts of law and of authority; and doing so by appealing to intuitions regarding the correct way to understand the concepts in question. In response to this state of affairs, Leiter advocates that jurisprudence ought to attempt to (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  20.  15
    Humility as a necessary virtue in common-law decision making.Katharina Stevens - 2023 - Jurisprudence 14 (4):443-461.
    Humility holds a modest but important place among the judicial virtues. But in spite of its growing popularity, it does not yet have a place on the ‘central judicial virtues’ lists. This paper provides an argument that judicial humility, especially institutional judicial humility, should be considered a necessary judicial virtue at least in common-law jurisdictions. This is because it is a necessary ingredient in precedent-based decisions that are fully justified from the point of view of the law and of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  32
    Virtue as the end of law: an aretaic theory of legislation.Lawrence B. Solum - 2018 - Jurisprudence 9 (1):6-18.
    ABSTRACTThis article investigates a virtue-centered approach to normative legal theory in the context of legislation. The core idea of such a theory is that the fundamental aim of law should be the promotion of human flourishing, where a flourishing human life is understood as a life of rational and social activities that express the human excellences. Law can promote flourishing in several ways. Because peace and prosperity are conducive to human flourishing, legislation should aim at the establishment and maintenance (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  22.  13
    Virtues and Voices.Lawrence B. Solum - unknown
    This essay explores two ideas that have recently played an important role in discourse about the American constitutional order. The first idea has emerged from the revival of civic republicanism. The republican revival has focused our attention on the classical conception of civic virtue. Our basic social arrangements ought to nourish a citizenry with the characteristics of mind and will that promote human flourishing. The second idea, expressed in critical race theory and feminist jurisprudence, is that we have (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  10
    Harnessing legal structures of virtue for planetary health.Eric C. Ip - 2023 - Journal of Medical Ethics 49 (12):833-837.
    Humans and other species depend on the planet’s well-being to survive and flourish. The health of the planet and its ecosystems is under threat from anthropogenic climate change, pollution and biodiversity loss. The promotion of planetary health against entrenched degradation of nature urgently requires ethical guidance. Using an ecocentric virtue jurisprudence approach, this article argues that the highest end of safeguarding planetary health is to secure the flourishing of the Earth community, of which the flourishing of humanity is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  34
    Leibniz's Universal Jurisprudence: Justice as the Charity of the Wise (review).Susanna Goodin - 1998 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 36 (3):470-471.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Leibniz’s Universal Jurisprudence: Justice as the Charity of the Wise by Patrick RileySusanna GoodinPatrick Riley. Leibniz’s Universal Jurisprudence: Justice as the Charity of the Wise. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1996. Pp. xiii + 338. Cloth, $39.95.Leibniz’s political views are often downplayed, if not simply ignored, by philosophers focusing on his metaphysical accounts of substance and force. That Leibniz himself does not view these two areas as (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Virtue and objectivity in legal reasoning.Amalia Amaya - 2022 - In Gonzalo Villa Rosas & Jorge Luis Fabra-Zamora (eds.), Objectivity in jurisprudence, legal interpretation and practical reasoning. Northampton, MA, USA: Edward Elgar Publishing.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  29
    Common virtue and the perspectival imagination: Adam Smith and common law reasoning.Maksymilian Del Mar - 2018 - Jurisprudence 9 (1):58-70.
    This paper considers the similarities between Adam Smith's device of the impartial spectator and the use of perspectival devices in common law reasoning. The paper adopts a reading of Smith's device as one involving the exercise of imaginative sympathy by an ordinarily virtuous, and culturally and historically situated, spectator who does not have a stake in the outcome of the scene being evaluated. The point here is to show that the impartial spectator is 1) a device of common, ordinary (...) – both in the sense of being located in a culture at a specific point in time, and in the sense of possessing only moderate, achievable virtues ; and 2) a device that enables a focus on a situation, which requires imaginative work, emotional engagement and careful, particularised description. Having so modelled Smith's device, the paper shows the similarities between it and the use of perspectival devices in common law reasoning, specifically here via the ‘right-thinking member of society' test in defamation law. (shrink)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  32
    Reconciling virtues and action-guidance in legal adjudication.José Juan Moreso - 2018 - Jurisprudence 9 (1):88-96.
    In this paper, I intend to articulate an answer to the powerful particularist objection against the notion of moral and legal reasoning based on universal principles. I defend a particular way of specifying and contextualising universal principles. I claim that this account preserves legal and moral justification conceived as subsumption to legal and moral principles. I also try to show how virtues can be reconciled with this account, i.e. what is the right place for virtues in legal adjudication. To carry (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28. Law-Determination as Grounding: A Common Grounding Framework for Jurisprudence.Samuele Chilovi & George Pavlakos - 2019 - Legal Theory 25 (1):53-76.
    Law being a derivative feature of reality, it exists in virtue of more fundamental things, upon which it depends. This raises the question of what is the relation of dependence that holds between law and its more basic determinants. The primary aim of this paper is to argue that grounding is that relation. We first make a positive case for this claim, and then we defend it from the potential objection that the relevant relation is rather rational determination (Greenberg (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  29. Natural justice : an aretaic account of the virtue of lawfulness.Lawrence B. Solum - 2007 - In Colin Patrick Farrelly & Lawrence Solum (eds.), Virtue Jurisprudence. Palgrave-Macmillan.
  30.  43
    Adam Smith and the character of virtue.Ryan Patrick Hanley - 2009 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    The problem : commerce and corruption -- Smith's defense of commercial society -- What is corruption? : political and psychological perspectives -- Smith on corruption : from the citizen to the human being -- The solution : moral philosophy -- Liberal individualism and virtue ethics -- Social science vs. moral philosophy -- Types of moral philosophy : natural jurisprudence vs. ethics -- Types of ethics : utilitarianism, deontology, and virtue ethics -- Virtue ethics : modern, ancient, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  31.  10
    Thomas Aquinas on virtue and human flourishing.Stephen Theron - 2018 - Newcastle upon Tyne, UK: Cambridge Scholars Press.
    Thomas Aquinas offers teleological systematisation of the habits needed for human flourishing. His metaphysical jurisprudence remodels ethics upon this, rather than on a moral precept. 'Eternal law' governing the world determines 'natural law', reflected in human legislation (a variety of the 'anthropic principle'). Finally, law, unwritten, is infused spirit as self-consciousness, 'universal of universals'. Acquired virtues elicit this, become effusion, represented in religion as gifts or graces. But mind's or spirit's omnipresence, necessarily 'closer to me than I am to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  3
    The Simple and Sweet Virtues of Analysis. A Plea for Hart's Metaphilosophy of Law.Pierluigi Chiassoni - 2011 - Problema. Anuario de Filosofía y Teoria Del Derecho 1 (5):53-80.
    Chapter I of The Concept of Law raises a fourth, capital, issue, besides the three well-known ones: i.e., the meta-philosophical issue concerning the point, the matter, and the method of legal theory. The paper purports to present Hart’s philosophy of jurisprudence in its best light, also by referring to some of its theoretical pay-offs, and to defend it, so far as possible, against a few criticisms by supporters of different outlooks (Raz, Leiter, and Dworkin)Resumen:El capítulo 1 de El concepto (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33. Hume, virtue and natural law.Thomas Pink - 2017 - In George Duke & Robert P. George (eds.), The Cambridge companion to natural law jurisprudence. New York: Cambridge University Press.
  34. Virtue, vice, and criminal liability.Antony Duff - 2007 - In Colin Patrick Farrelly & Lawrence Solum (eds.), Virtue jurisprudence. Palgrave-Macmillan.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35. Human Rights and the Forgotten Acts of Meaning in the Social Conventions of Conceptual Jurisprudence.William Conklin - 2014 - Metodo. International Studies in Phenomenology and Philosophy 2 (1):169-199.
    This essay claims that a rupture between two languages permeates human rights discourse in contemporary Anglo-American legal thought. Human rights law is no exception. The one language is written in the sense that a signifying relation inscribed by institutional authors represents concepts. Theories of law have shared such a preoccupation with concepts. Legal rules, doctrines, principles, rights and duties exemplify legal concepts. One is mindful of the dominant tradition of Anglo-American conceptual jurisprudence in this regard. Words have been thought (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  16
    Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment (review).Fred Dycus Miller - 2000 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 38 (3):439-441.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Adam Smith and the Virtues of EnlightenmentFred D. Miller Jr.Charles L. Griswold. Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999. Pp. xiv + 412. Cloth, $59.95.For over a century, scholars have been vexed by the so-called "Adam Smith problem," which concerns the relationship between the two works which Smith published during his lifetime: The Theory of Moral Sentiments (TMS) in 1759, and An Inquiry (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  6
    Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment (review).Fred Dycus Miller - 2000 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 38 (3):439-441.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Adam Smith and the Virtues of EnlightenmentFred D. Miller Jr.Charles L. Griswold. Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999. Pp. xiv + 412. Cloth, $59.95.For over a century, scholars have been vexed by the so-called "Adam Smith problem," which concerns the relationship between the two works which Smith published during his lifetime: The Theory of Moral Sentiments (TMS) in 1759, and An Inquiry (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  47
    ‘Simply in virtue of being human’? A critical appraisal of a human rights commonplace.Raffael N. Fasel - 2018 - Jurisprudence 9 (3):461-485.
    ABSTRACTIt has become a commonplace that human beings possess human rights ‘simply in virtue of being human’. Exactly what this formula entails and whether it is cogent remains largely obscure, however. To remedy this situation, the article distinguishes between an interpretation of the formula according to which ‘being human’ is a practical condition for holding human rights and a reading which takes ‘being human’ to be a moral reason for holding human rights. It argues that only under the second (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  34
    Prudence, benevolence, and negligence : virtue ethics and tort law.Heidi Li Feldman - 2000 - In Colin Patrick Farrelly & Lawrence Solum (eds.), Virtue jurisprudence. Palgrave-Macmillan.
  40.  78
    Reply: The Nature and Virtue of Law.N. E. Simmonds - 2010 - Jurisprudence 1 (2):277-293.
    The essay replies to comments by Finnis, Gardner and Endicott, on my book, Law as a Moral Idea. It is questioned whether Finnis is right to suggest that governance by law is a requirement of justice. It is suggested that Hart's positivism may have rested upon an unduly private conception of morality. Gardner's suggestion that Law as a Moral Idea falsely manufactures disagreement with Hart is rejected, principally by pointing out that Gardner focuses upon only one issue, where the book (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  41. Weapons Control Laws.in Common-Law Jurisprudence - 1991 - In D. Sank & D. Caplan (eds.), To Be a Victim. Plenum.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  85
    Public Reason, Neutrality and Civic Virtues.Colin Farrelly - 1999 - Ratio Juris 12 (1):11-25.
    In this paper I argue that political liberalism is not the “minimalist liberalism” characterised by Michael Sandel and that it does not support the vision of public life characteristic of the procedural republic. I defend this claim by developing two points. The first concerns Rawls's account of public reason. Drawing from examples in Canadian free speech jurisprudence I show how restrictions on commercial advertising, obscenity and hate propaganda can be justified by political values. Secondly, political liberalism also attends to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  27
    The law of duty and the virtue of justice.Ekow Nyansa Yankah - 2008 - Criminal Justice Ethics 27 (1):67-77.
    In his new book, The Grammar of Criminal Law: American, Comparative, and International, celebrated criminal law theorist George Fletcher excavates criminal law doctrine across a number of countries and cultures to reveal a small number of basic shared structures. Among these structures Fletcher argues that it is a criminal law justified by Kantian legal morality, in contrast to perfectionist or communitarian theories, that is legitimate. Thus, Fletcher proposes, along with legal positivists, that the validity of legal norms does not turn (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  7
    Angel detox: taking your life to a higher level through releasing emotional, physical, and energetic toxins.Doreen Virtue - 2014 - Carlsbad, California: Hay House. Edited by Robert Reeves.
    Work with the Angels to Detox Your Body and Energy Detoxing with the help of your angels is a gentle way to release impurities from your body, fatigue, and addictions. Doreen Virtue and naturopath Robert Reeves teach yousimple steps to increase your energy and mental focus, banish bloating, feel and look more youthful, and regain your sense of personal power. Rid your life of physical toxins, as well as negative emotions and energies. Angel Detox guides you step-by-step on how (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  17
    Nineteenth-Century Perceptions of John Austin: Utilitarianism and the.Jurisprudence Determined - 1991 - Utilitas 3 (2).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  19
    Law’s regret: on moral remainders, (in)commensurability and a virtue-ethical approach to legal decision-making.Iris van Domselaar - 2022 - Jurisprudence 13 (2):220-239.
    In his essay ‘Ethical Consistency’, Bernard Williams famously introduced the concept of a moral remainder, which points to the phenomenon of an in itself defensible decision that may nonetheless re...
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47.  10
    Don't let anything dull your sparkle: how to break free of negativity and drama.Doreen Virtue - 2015 - Carlsbad, California: Hay House.
    Difficult relationships and challenging situations all come down to one thing: drama. In this groundbreaking book, Doreen Virtue guides you through the process of determining what your Drama Quotient is. You will learn how much you are unnecessarily tolerating and absorbing from other people and situations. Doreen highlights the difference between detaching from drama and being compassionate and helpful, and she shows you how to: Deal with relatives, friends, and co-workers who are addicted to drama Assess your own level (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Anne Bottomley and Nathan Moore.on New Model Jurisprudence : The Scholar/Critic As Artisan - 2018 - In Andreas Philippopoulos-Mihalopoulos (ed.), Routledge Handbook of Law and Theory. New York, NY: Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  37
    The aretaic turn in American philosophy of law.Lawrence B. Solum - 2009 - In Francis J. Mootz (ed.), On Philosophy in American Law. Cambridge University Press.
    This essay explores the development of "virtue jurisprudence," a general theory of law that draws on ideas developed in virtue ethics.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  28
    Dependent Rational Animals: Why Human Beings Need the Virtues by Alasdair C. MacIntyre.Patrick Lee - 2000 - American Journal of Jurisprudence 45 (1):133-160.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 1000