Results for 'Speaker Responsibilities '

986 found
Order:
  1.  11
    Speaker Responsibility for Synthetic Speech Derived from Neural Activity.Stephen Rainey - 2022 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 47 (4):503-515.
    This article provides analysis of the mechanisms and outputs involved in language-use mediated by a neuroprosthetic device. It is motivated by the thought that users of speech neuroprostheses require sufficient control over what their devices externalize as synthetic speech if they are to be thought of as responsible for it, but that the nature of this control, and so the status of their responsibility, is not clear.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  25
    Response to the Speakers.John Deely - 2005 - American Journal of Semiotics 21 (1-4):43-51.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  34
    Compliment response patterns between younger and older generations of Persian speakers.Mehdi Sarkhosh & Ali Alizadeh - 2017 - Pragmatics and Society 8 (3):421-446.
    The majority of studies on compliment response have investigated CR patterns and norms among different cultural groups and communities. The present study investigated the shifting of CR patterns across generations within the same speech community. To this end, 272 Persian speakers were chosen from among high school students and teachers. A discourse completion task with four complimenting situations was administered. The findings revealed that the new generation of Persian speakers, regardless of their gender, had shifted their CR patterns and overwhelmingly (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4.  8
    A Speaker-Meaning Theory of Moral Responsibility.Michael S. McKenna - 1998 - The Paideia Archive: Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 26:53-59.
    In this paper I attempt to give an account of the moral criticizability of motive by appeal to some insights in semantic theory. I maintain that the actions for which we hold persons responsible cannot strictly be understood as expressive of semantic meaning. However, I argue that morally responsible actions can be understood on analogy with a basic Gricean distinction between speaker's and sentence meaning. The analogy suggests that morally responsible actions require a competent moral agent to operate from (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  9
    Different Neural Responses for Unfinished Sentence as a Conventional Indirect Refusal Between Native and Non-native Speakers: An Event-Related Potential Study.Min Wang, Shingo Tokimoto, Ge Song, Takashi Ueno, Masatoshi Koizumi & Sachiko Kiyama - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13.
    Refusal is considered a face-threatening act, since it contradicts the inviter’s expectations. In the case of Japanese, native speakers are known to prefer to leave sentences unfinished for a conventional indirect refusal. Successful comprehension of this indirect refusal depends on whether the addressee is fully conventionalized to the preference for syntactic unfinishedness so that they can identify the true intention of the refusal. Then, non-native speakers who are not fully accustomed to the convention may be confused by the indirect style. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  25
    Moral Foreign Language Effect on Responses to the Trolley Dilemma amongst Native Speakers of Arabic.Gabriel Andrade - 2022 - Journal of Cognition and Culture 22 (3-4):338-351.
    Trolley dilemmas have been tested cross-culturally, but only recently have researchers begun to assess the effect of responding to such dilemmas in a foreign language. Previous studies have found a Moral Foreign Language Effect in trolley dilemmas, whereby subjects who respond to these dilemmas in a foreign language, tend to offer more utilitarian responses. The present study seeks to test whether the MFLE holds amongst native speakers of Arabic. Additionally, the present study seeks to test whether the use of visual (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  21
    Toward a Speaker Meaning Theory of Moral Responsibility.Michael S. McKenna - 2000 - In A. van den Beld (ed.), Moral Responsibility and Ontology. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 247--258.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  12
    The Persian cultural schema of shekasteh-nafsi: A study of compliment responses in Persian and Anglo-Australian speakers.Farzad Sharifian - 2005 - Pragmatics and Cognition 13 (2):337-361.
    This study is as an attempt to explicate the Persian cultural schema of shekasteh-nafsi `modesty'. The schema motivates the speakers to downplay their talents, skills, achievements, etc. while praising a similar trait in their interlocutors. The schema also encourages the speakers to reassign the compliment to the giver of the compliment, a family member, a friend, or another associate. This paper explicates the schema in an ethnographic fashion and also makes use of empirical data to further explore how the schema (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  9.  26
    The Persian cultural schema of "shekasteh-nafsi": a study of compliment responses in Persian and Anglo-Australian speakers.Farzad Sharifian - 2005 - Pragmatics and Cognition 13 (2):337-362.
    This study is as an attempt to explicate the Persian cultural schema of shekasteh-nafsi ¿modesty¿. The schema motivates the speakers to downplay their talents, skills, achievements, etc. while praising a similar trait in their interlocutors. The schema also encourages the speakers to reassign the compliment to the giver of the compliment, a family member, a friend, or another associate. This paper explicates the schema in an ethnographic fashion and also makes use of empirical data to further explore how the schema (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  10. Group Speakers.Grace Paterson - 2020 - Language & Communication 70:59-66.
    This paper examines group speech acts to argue against the view, here called speaker intentionalism, that one is a speaker behind a speech act in virtue of having the relevant communicative illocutionary intention. An alternative view is presented called speaker responsibilism according to which one is a speaker in virtue of having certain responsibilities. Complexities are considered which arise from the kinds of responsibilities the speaker has and the specific ways in which they (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  11.  88
    What speakers do and what addressees look at.Marianne Gullberg & Kenneth Holmqvist - 2006 - Pragmatics and Cognition 14 (1):53-82.
    This study investigates whether addressees visually attend to speakers’ gestures in interaction and whether attention is modulated by changes in social setting and display size. We compare a live face-to-face setting to two video conditions. In all conditions, the face dominates as a fixation target and only a minority of gestures draw fixations. The social and size parameters affect gaze mainly when combined and in the opposite direction from the predicted with fewer gestures fixated on video than live. Gestural holds (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  12.  61
    Smart Speaker Recommendations: Impact of Gender Congruence and Amount of Information on Users' Engagement and Choice.Jaime Romero, Daniel Ruiz-Equihua, Sandra Maria Correia Loureiro & Luis V. Casaló - 2021 - Frontiers in Psychology 12.
    The relevance of smart speakers is steadily increasing, allowing users perform several daily tasks. From a commercial perspective, smart speakers also provide recommendations of products and services that may influence the consumer decision-making process. However, previous studies have mainly focused on the adoption of smart speakers, but there is a lack of proper guidelines that help design the way these devices should offer their consumption recommendations. Based on a stimulus-organism-response approach, we analyze how two features of smart speakers' recommendations influence (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. Metalinguistic Negotiation and Speaker Error.David Plunkett & Tim Sundell - 2021 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 64 (1-2):142-167.
    In recent work, we have argued that a number of disputes of interest to philosophers – including some disputes amongst philosophers themselves – are metalinguistic negotiations. Prima facie, many of these disputes seem to concern worldly, non-linguistic issues directly. However, on our view, they in fact concern, in the first instance, normative questions about the use of linguistic expressions. This will strike many ordinary speakers as counterintuitive. In many of the disputes that we analyze as metalinguistic negotiations, speakers might quite (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  14. Assertoric content, responsibility, and metasemantics.Andrew Peet - 2021 - Mind and Language 37 (5):914-932.
    I argue that assertoric content functions as a means for us to track the responsibilities undertaken by communicators, and that distinctively assertoric commitments are distinguished by being generated directly in virtue of the words the speaker uses. This raises two questions: (a) Why are speakers responsible for the content thus generated? (b) Why is it important for us to distinguish between commitments in terms of their manner of generation? I answer the first question by developing a novel responsibility (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  15.  23
    SILENCING AND SPEAKER VULNERABILITY: undoing an oppressive form of (wilful) ignorance.Nicholas Bunnin & Pamela Sue Anderson - 2020 - Angelaki 25 (1-2):36-45.
    The French feminist philosopher Michèle Le Doeuff has taught us something about “the collectivity,” which she discovers in women’s struggle for access to the philosophical, but also about “the unknown” and “the unthought.” It is the unthought which will matter most to what I intend to say today about a fundamental ignorance on which speaker vulnerability is built. On International Women’s Day, it seems appropriate to speak about – or, at least, to evoke – the silencing which has been (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  16.  67
    Responsibility for Silence.Saray Ayala & Nadya Vasilyeva - 2016 - Journal of Social Philosophy 47 (3):256-272.
    This paper builds upon Mary Kate McGowan’s analysis of the mechanisms of harm in conversations (McGowan 2004; 2009). McGowan describes how a speaker’s intervention might constitute harm by enacting what is permissible to do in the conversation thereafter. We expand McGowan’s analysis in two ways: first, we use her account to argue for the potential of interlocutor’s silence, not only speaker’s intervention, to enact harm; second, we introduce a new party into the picture: observers of the conversation. We (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  17. Speakers for the dead : digital memory and the construction of identity.Alana M. Vincent - 2018 - In Stefan Helgesson & Jayne Svenungsson (eds.), The Ethos of History: Time and Responsibility. Berghahn Books.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  31
    Conversation and Responsibility.Michael McKenna - 2011 - , US: Oxford University Press USA.
    In this book Michael McKenna advances a new theory of moral responsibility, one that builds upon the work of P. F. Strawson. As McKenna demonstrates, moral responsibility can be explained on analogy with a conversation. The relation between a morally responsible agent and those who hold her morally responsible is similar to the relation between a speaker and her audience. A responsible agent's actions are bearers of meaning--agent meaning--just as a speaker's utterances are bearers of speaker meaning. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   151 citations  
  19.  9
    Utterance content, speaker’s intentions and linguistic liability.Claudia Picazo Jaque - 2017 - Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 32 (3):329-345.
    According to contextualists, communication has to do with pragmatically adjusted content, not with conventional meaning. This pragmatic content is sometimes identified with speaker meaning or with the thought the speaker intends to express. I will argue that given the sociolinguistic role of utterance content—the fact it provides reasons for action, liabilities and entitlements—locutionary content should not be modelled as a variety of speaker meaning.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Conceptual Engineering, Metasemantic Externalism and Speaker-Meaning.Mark Pinder - 2021 - Mind 130 (517):141–163.
    What is the relationship between conceptual engineering and metasemantic externalism? Sally Haslanger has argued that metasemantic externalism justifies the seemingly counterintuitive consequences of her proposed conceptual revisions. But according to Herman Cappelen, metasemantic externalism makes conceptual engineering effectively impossible in practice. After raising objections to Haslanger’s and Cappelen’s views, I argue for a very different picture, on which metasemantic externalism bears very little on conceptual engineering. I argue that, while metasemantic externalism principally operates at the level of semantic-meaning, we should (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  21.  7
    Overt reference to speaker and recipient in Korean.Sun-Young Oh - 2007 - Discourse Studies 9 (4):462-492.
    In Korean, reference forms can be omitted so long as the referent can be understood by the interlocutor; speaker/recipient reference terms are most readily omitted because they are easily retrievable from the physical interactional context. The current study represents the first attempt to examine specifically when and why Korean speakers do use an overt reference form in referring to themselves or their recipients even when reference can be understood without such overt forms. It demonstrates that Korean speakers build their (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  2
    Coordination Between Speakers.Kit Fine - 2007 - In Semantic Relationism. Ames, Iowa, USA: Blackwell. pp. 86–121.
    This chapter contains section titled: Kripke's Puzzle Some Related Puzzles A Response A Solution A Deeper Puzzle A Deeper Solution The Role of Variables in Belief Reports Some Semantical Morals.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Silence and responsibility.Ishani Maitra - 2004 - Philosophical Perspectives 18 (1):189–208.
    In this paper, I shall be concerned with the phenomenon that has been labeled silencing in some of the recent philosophical literature. A speaker who is silenced in this sense is unable to make herself understood, even though her audience hears every word she utters. For instance, consider a woman who says “No”, intending to refuse sex. Her audience fails to recognize her intention to refuse, because he thinks that women tend to be insincere, and to not say what (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  24.  16
    “Those are Your Words, Not Mine!” Defence Strategies for Denying Speaker Commitment.Ronny Boogaart, Henrike Jansen & Maarten van Leeuwen - 2020 - Argumentation 35 (2):209-235.
    In response to an accusation of having said something inappropriate, the accused may exploit the difference between the explicit contents of their utterance and its implicatures. Widely discussed in the pragmatics literature are those cases in which arguers accept accountability only for the explicit contents of what they said while denying commitment to the implicature. In this paper, we sketch a fuller picture of commitment denial. We do so, first, by including in our discussion not just denial of implicatures, but (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  25.  16
    Synesthesia, meaning, and multilingual speakers.Fiona N. Newell - 2013 - In Julia Simner & Edward Hubbard (eds.), Oxford Handbook of Synesthesia. Oxford University Press. pp. 181.
    Although several studies have investigated the cognitive nature of the synaesthetic experience, very little is known about the stage in information processing at which the synaesthetic response arises. Specifically, we are still unclear about how much perceptual processing of an inducing stimulus is required before synaesthesia is experienced. Is synaesthesia induced by particular featural properties of a stimulus or might it be driven by a more abstract representation determined by lexical meaning? Or perhaps synaesthesia is triggered by some combination of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  34
    Response to Wang Bo's Paper.Carine Defoort - 1999 - Contemporary Chinese Thought 30 (4):41-43.
    Allow me first to congratulate the speaker for his most interesting talk. His strategy is well taken and convincing: Look at a Zhuangzi chapter that has been largely neglected by philosophers, identify its concerns, and read other Zhuangzi chapters through these concerns, rather than as mere variants of Western "philosophy." The concerns of the chapter "The Human World" lie, first of all, with staying alive when giving political advice or being sent on a diplomatic mission. The art of staying (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  17
    Compliment Response (CR) patterns among English vs. Persian teachers: Cultural transmission of CR behavior?Zahra Jalilzadeh Mohammadi & Karim Sadeghi - 2021 - Lodz Papers in Pragmatics 17 (1-2):153-174.
    The purpose of the present study was to compare differential functioning of Iranian English versus Persian teachers in responding to compliments and to investigate the possibility of sociolinguistic transmission of speech act of responding to compliments from English culture to native Iranian Persian speakers. Following Chen and Yang (2010), we hypothesized that exposure to English would affect the complimenting behavior of Persian speakers, leading to more acceptance of compliments compared to those with little or no exposure to English. Participants of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  22
    Tests of a two-stage "speaker" communication model using induced respone hierarchies.Meyer A. Rothberg - 1970 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 84 (2):204.
  29.  94
    Response to Slavoj Zizek.Claudia Breger - 2001 - Diacritics 31 (1):105-108.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Diacritics 31.1 (2001) 73-90 [Access article in PDF] The Leader's Two BodiesSlavoj Zizek's Postmodern Political Theology Claudia Breger Over the course of the last decade, Slavoj Zizek and his "Slovenian Lacanian school" have gained renown in the Western theory market. Academics are fascinated not only by Zizek's performances as a speaker, his nondogmatic approach to issues of genre and (inter)mediality, 1 and the "literary" character of his theoretical (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Responsibility for Testimonial Belief.Benjamin McMyler - 2012 - Erkenntnis 76 (3):337-352.
    According to so-called “credit views of knowledge,” knowledge is an achievement of an epistemic agent, something for which an agent is creditable or responsible. One influential criticism of the credit view of knowledge holds that the credit view has difficulty making sense of knowledge acquired from testimony. As Jennifer Lackey has argued, in many ordinary cases of the acquisition of testimonial knowledge, if anyone deserves credit for the truth of the audience’s belief it is the testimonial speaker rather than (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  31. Reference and Response.Louis deRosset - 2011 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 89 (1):19-36.
    A standard view of reference holds that a speaker's use of a name refers to a certain thing in virtue of the speaker's associating a condition with that use that singles the referent out. This view has been criticized by Saul Kripke as empirically inadequate. Recently, however, it has been argued that a version of the standard view, a /response-based theory of reference/, survives the charge of empirical inadequacy by allowing that associated conditions may be largely or even (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  32. Trust, authority and epistemic responsibility.Gloria Origgi - 2008 - Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 23 (1):35-44.
    In this paper I argue that the epistemology of trust and testimony should take into account the pragmatics of communication in order to gain insight about the responsibilities speakers and hearers share in the epistemic access they gain through communication. Communication is a rich process of information exchange in which epistemic standards are negotiated by interlocutors. I discuss examples which show the contextual adjustment of these standards as the conversation goes on. Our sensitivity to the contextual dimension of epistemic (...)
    Direct download (13 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  33.  11
    Re‐Examining the Effect of Top‐Down Linguistic Information on Speaker‐Voice Discrimination.Ashley Quinto, Sandy Abu El Adas & Susannah V. Levi - 2020 - Cognitive Science 44 (10):e12902.
    The current study replicated and extended the results from a study conducted by Narayan, Mak, and Bialystok (2017) that found effects of top‐down linguistic information on a speaker discrimination task by examining four conditions: rhymes (day‐bay), compounds (day‐dream), reverse compounds (dream‐day), and unrelated words (day‐bee). The original study found that participants were more likely to judge two words to be spoken by the same speaker if the words cohered lexically (created lexical compounds such as day‐dream) or were phonologically (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Response to Paul Gross, by William A. Dembski.William Dembski - manuscript
    A few years back, well-known skeptic Michael Shermer and I were speakers at Baylor’s The Nature of Nature conference. During evening refreshments, we discussed how we could generate funds for our respective causes—he to promote skepticism and debunk people like me, and me to promote intelligent design and debunk Darwinism (which underwrites Shermer’s brand of skepticism). We agreed that we should start a highly visible campaign against each other in which we argue the dangers of the other’s position. Having escalated (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  24
    Motion Event Similarity Judgments in One or Two Languages: An Exploration of Monolingual Speakers of English and Chinese vs. L2 Learners of English.Yinglin Ji - 2017 - Frontiers in Psychology 8:246366.
    Languages differ systematically in how to encode a motion event. English characteristically expresses manner in verb root and path in verb particle; in Chinese, varied aspects of motion, such as manner, path and cause, can be simultaneously encoded in a verb compound. This study investigates whether typological differences, as such, influence how first and second language learners conceptualise motion events, as suggested by behavioural evidences. Specifically, the performance of Chinese learners of English, at three proficiencies, was compared to that of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36.  29
    Responses to an opponent’s nonverbal behavior in a televised debate: Audience perceptions of credibility and likeability.Harry Weger Jr, John S. Seiter, Kimberly A. Jacobs & Valerie Akbulut - 2013 - Journal of Argumentation in Context 2 (2):179-203.
    This study examined audience perceptions of a political candidate’s credibility and likeability as a function of varying the candidate’s responses to an opponent’s nonverbal disparagement during a televised debate. 412 participants watched a purported televised debate between candidates for mayor in a small city in Utah. In all six versions, one debater engaged in strong nonverbal disagreement during his opponent’s opening statement. His opponent responded to the nonverbal behavior with one of six decreasingly polite messages. Results indicated that more direct (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  4
    Ambiguity, responsibility and political action in the UK daily COVID-19 briefings.Jamie Williams & David Wright - 2024 - Critical Discourse Studies 21 (1):76-91.
    ABSTRACT This paper investigates how pronouns were used by UK government speakers to allocate responsibility to themselves and others in all 92 daily televised COVID-19 briefings that were held between March and June 2020. We identified the referent for every use of the first-person plural pronoun (1PL) as ‘inclusive’, ‘exclusive’, or 'ambiguous' and analysed the transitivity patterns in which these pronouns act as Participants. We argue that the UK government uses the inherent ambiguity of this pronoun to strategically mitigate their (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  15
    Should we embrace “Big Sister”? Smart speakers as a means to combat intimate partner violence.Robert Sparrow, Mark Andrejevic & Bridget Harris - 2023 - Ethics and Information Technology 25 (4):1-13.
    It is estimated that one in three women experience intimate partner violence (IPV) across the course of their life. The popular uptake of “smart speakers” powered by sophisticated AI means that surveillance of the domestic environment is increasingly possible. Correspondingly, there are various proposals to use smart speakers to detect or report IPV. In this paper, we clarify what might be possible when it comes to combatting IPV using existing or near-term technology and also begin the project of evaluating this (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. Exhaustiveness, normativity, and communicative responsibilities.Miklós Márton & Tibor Bárány - 2022 - In Piotr Stalmaszczyk & Martin Hinton (ed.), Philosophical Approaches to Language and Communication Vol. 2. Peter Lang. pp. 291-312.
    In this paper we analyze and discuss Jennifer Saul’s account of the famous Gricean notions of ‘what is said’ and ‘what is implicated’ and the alleged conflict between them and the so- called Speaker- Meaning Exhaustiveness Thesis (SMET), which is standardly attributed to Grice in the literature. SMET declares that speaker- meaning divides exhaustively into what is said and what is (conventionally or nonconventionally) implicated by the speaker. After a detailed interpretation of Saul’s position, we argue that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  10
    Response to Comments.Konstantin Kolenda - 1956 - Review of Metaphysics 10 (1):118 - 121.
    2. To use the objective form, "X is the case," is to indicate prima facie that the above rules have been observed in making the assertion and that the hearer is expected to take this for granted. Otherwise, special qualifications are normally added which indicate that the speaker knows of special circumstances which may prevent the hearer from believing X or make him for some reason incapable of following the evidence for X.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  36
    Well I May Be Exaggerating But Self-Qualifying Clauses in Negotiation of Opinions Among Japanese Speakers.Junko Mori - 1999 - Human Studies 22 (2-4):447-473.
    The present study investigates the ways in which Japanese speakers negotiate their opinions in conversational interaction. On the one hand, speakers are apt to exaggerate a particular aspect of a given issue in asserting their opinion, on the other hand, they may also incorporate a self-qualification admitting a potential problem in their claim. By expressing their awareness of the problem before it is pointed out by the co-participants, the speakers seem to get license to proffer an exaggerated or overgeneralized claim (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  4
    Variability in L2 Vowel Production: Different Elicitation Methods Affect Individual Speakers Differently.Murray J. Munro - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13.
    Elicitation methods are known to influence second language speech production. For teachers and language assessors, awareness of such effects is essential to accurate interpretations of testing outcomes. For speech researchers, understanding why one method gives better performance than another may yield insights into how second-language phonological knowledge is acquired, stored, and retrieved. Given these concerns, this investigation compared L2 vowel intelligibility on two elicitation tasks and determined the degree to which differences generalized across vowels, vowels in context, lexical items, and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  82
    Response to Professor Chisholm.V. C. Chappell - 1965 - The Monist 49 (1):36-37.
    I do not think it would be fair for me to reply to Professor Spiegelberg’s rejoinder without giving him the chance to reply in turn to my reply. The first speaker in a symposium should always, I believe, have the last word. But by that principle I am entitled to a reply to Professor Chisholm, for whom, in his original paper, I was a primary target.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  1
    Evidentiality and the expression of speaker’s stance in Romance languages and German.Gerda Haßler - 2015 - Discourse Studies 17 (2):182-209.
    In recent years, the category of evidentiality has also come into use for the description of Romance languages and of German. This has been contingent on a change in its interpretation from a typological category to a semantic-pragmatic category, which allows an application to languages lacking specialised morphemes for the expression of evidentiality. We consider evidentiality to be a structural dimension of grammar, the values of which are expressed by types of constructions that code the source of information which a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45. The evolution of testimony: Receiver vigilance, speaker honesty and the reliability of communication.Kourken Michaelian - 2013 - Episteme 10 (1):37-59.
    Drawing on both empirical evidence and evolutionary considerations, Sperber et al. argue that humans have a suite of evolved mechanisms for . On their view, vigilance plays a crucial role in ensuring the reliability and hence the evolutionary stability of communication. This article responds to their argument for vigilance, drawing on additional empirical evidence (from deception detection research) and evolutionary considerations (from animal signalling research) to defend a more optimistic, quasi-Reidian view of communication. On this alternative view, the lion's share (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  46.  47
    Introduction, Dan Bromley, 2014 Coss Dialogues Invited Speaker.Paul B. Thompson - 2015 - The Pluralist 10 (1):1-5.
    the coss dialogues were initiated in 1995 to foster cross talk between philosophers working in the classical American tradition modeled by C. S. Peirce, William James, John Dewey, Jane Addams, and others, on the one hand, and contemporary representatives from other traditions, especially disciplines other than philosophy, on the other. The format for the Coss Dialogues was originally conceived as a plenary presentation at the annual meeting of the Society for the Advancement of American Philosophy by an invited speaker (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Intuitions: Rijeka Response to Nenad Miščević.Michael Devitt - 2018 - Croatian Journal of Philosophy 18 (2):277-282.
    This paper is a response to Nenad Miščević’s “Reply to Michael Devitt”, the latest in an exchange on the source of linguistic intuitions. Miščević defends a modified version (“MoVoC”) of the received view that these intuitions are the product of a linguistic competence. I have earlier rejected all versions of the received view urging instead that intuitions are, like perceptual judgments, empirical theory-laden central-processor responses to phenomena. (1) I emphasize here, against Miščević, that this claim about a speaker’s intuitions (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  15
    Political Responsibility in Time of Civil War.Jeremy D. Wilkins - 2020 - The Lonergan Review 11:13-35.
    In this article I propose to do five things. First, I describe the present confusion disturbing the tranquility of the American polity. Next, I hypothesize that an important source of civil confusion is that American civildiscourse is generally conducted in two different moral languages. Neither of these is adequate to the reality of the human good, and their speakers are, perhaps increasingly, given to misunderstanding one another. Third, I propose some reasons why not only misunderstanding but even outright hostility seems (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Referential Intentions: A Response to Buchanan and Peet.Elmar Unnsteinsson - 2018 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 96 (3):610-615.
    Buchanan (2014) argues for a Gricean solution to well-known counterexamples to direct reference theories of content. Peet (2016) develops a way to change the counterexample so that it seems to speak against Buchanan’s own proposal. I argue that both theorists fail to notice a significant distinction between the kinds of cases at issue. Those appearing to count against direct reference theory must be described such that speakers have false beliefs about the identity of the object to which they intend to (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  50.  40
    Moral responses and moral theory: Socially-based externalist ethics. [REVIEW]P. S. Greenspan - 1998 - The Journal of Ethics 2 (2):103-122.
    The paper outlines a view called social (or two-level) response-dependency as an addition to standard alternatives in metaethics that allows for a position intermediate between standard versions of internalism and externalism on the question of motivational force. Instead of taking psychological responses as either directly supplying the content of ethics (as on emotivist or sentimentalist accounts) or as irrelevant to its content (as in classical versions of Kantian or utilitarian ethics), the view allows them an indirect role, as motivational props (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
1 — 50 / 986