Results for 'Rights of the Child to know their genetic parents, Misattributed Paternity, Adoption, Donor Offspring, Mandatory DNA Testing'

994 found
Order:
  1.  5
    DNA and Family Matters.Madeline Kilty - 2016 - Germany: LAP Lambert Academic Publishing.
    Under the terms of the UN Convention on the Rights of the Child, which Australia has ratified, children have a right to know who their genetic parents are. As a result, we have a duty to establish these facts and to make this information available for children to access should they wish to know. Introducing mandatory DNA testing of newborns and their alleged genetic parents is one viable option to ensure (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  57
    The Right to Know Your Genetic Parents: From Open-Identity Gamete Donation to Routine Paternity Testing.An Ravelingien & Guido Pennings - 2013 - American Journal of Bioethics 13 (5):33-41.
    Over the years a number of countries have abolished anonymous gamete donation and shifted toward open-identity policies. Donor-conceived children are said to have a fundamental “right to know” the identity of their donor. In this article, we trace the arguments that underlie this claim and question its implications. We argue that, given the status attributed to the right to know one's gamete donor, it would be discriminatory not to extend this right to naturally conceived (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  3.  28
    The Right to Know Your Genetic Parents: From Open-Identity Gamete Donation to Routine Paternity Testing.An Ravelingien & Guido Pennings - 2013 - American Journal of Bioethics 13 (5):33-41.
    Over the years a number of countries have abolished anonymous gamete donation and shifted toward open-identity policies. Donor-conceived children are said to have a fundamental “right to know” the identity of their donor. In this article, we trace the arguments that underlie this claim and question its implications. We argue that, given the status attributed to the right to know one's gamete donor, it would be discriminatory not to extend this right to naturally conceived (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  4. The Right to Know the Identities of Genetic Parents.Madeline Kilty - 2013 - Australian Journal of Adoption 7 (2).
    While in this paper I focus on adoptees, my argument is applicable to donor-conceived children and children of misattributed paternity. I address some of the noted risks of closed adopted and the benefits of open adoption, which is more in keeping with Article 7 of the United Nations Convention on the Rights of the Child (CRC), which provides all children with a right to know about their genetic parents and which the Australian government (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  19
    The making and breaking of paternity secrets in donor insemination.L. Turney - 2010 - Journal of Medical Ethics 36 (7):401-406.
    This paper analyses the complex issues faced by regulators of the infertility treatment industry in response to the social and technological changes that heralded a new openness in knowledge about genetics, paternity and the concomitant need for donor offspring to know their genetic origins. The imperative for full information about their donor and biological father, who contributed to their creation and half of their genome, was an outcome unanticipated by the architects of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  6.  15
    Shifting to a model of donor conception that entails a communication agreement among the parents, donor, and offspring.Iñigo de Miguel Beriain & Tetsuya Ishii - 2022 - BMC Medical Ethics 23 (1):1-11.
    BackgroundSome persons conceived with donor gametes react negatively when they found their birth via donor conception. They request access to information about and seek to communicate with the donor. However, some countries mandate donor anonymity. Other countries allow donor-conceived persons to access donor information, but they can only use this access if their parents have disclosed donor conception to them. We investigated a thorny issue of donor conception: whether donor (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  21
    Significant Interests and the Right to Know.Reuven Brandt - 2023 - International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 16 (1):201-213.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Significant Interests and the Right to KnowReuven Brandt (bio)1. IntroductionDaniel Groll's book Conceiving People (2021) attempts a novel and insightful defence of why individuals ought to choose open over anonymous gamete donation, barring any special circumstances. In broad strokes, the overall argument proceeds by defending three main claims: (1) that failing to disclose to children that they are donor-conceived is morally problematic, (2) that children who are informed (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  18
    Contacting gamete donors to facilitate diagnostic genetic testing for the donor-conceived child: what are the rights and obligations of gamete donors in these cases? A response to Horton et al.Lucy Frith - 2020 - Journal of Medical Ethics 46 (3):220-222.
    In their paper Horton et al argue that it is acceptable to contact an anonymous egg-donor to facilitate diagnostic genetic testing for the donor conceived child, despite the donor, ‘indicating on a historical consent form that she did not wish to take part in future research, and that she did not wish to be informed if she was found to be a carrier of a “harmful inherited condition”’. There are a number of claims (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  9.  21
    Donor Conception and Mandatory Paternity Testing: The Right to Know and the Right to Be Told.Lucy Frith - 2013 - American Journal of Bioethics 13 (5):50-52.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10.  46
    Discovering misattributed paternity in genetic counselling: different ethical perspectives in two countries.M. J. Parker, L. Caenazzo & P. Tozzo - 2014 - Journal of Medical Ethics 40 (3):177-181.
    Misattributed paternity or ‘false’ paternity is when a man is wrongly thought, by himself and possibly by others, to be the biological father of a child. Nowadays, because of the progression of genetics and genomics the possibility of finding misattributed paternity during familial genetic testing has increased. In contrast to other medical information, which pertains primarily to individuals, information obtained by genetic testing and/or pedigree analysis necessarily has implications for other biologically related members (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  32
    The Ethics of Anonymous Gamete Donation: Is There a Right to Know One's Genetic Origins?.Inmaculada De Melo-Martín - 2014 - Hastings Center Report 44 (2):28-35.
    The vast majority of gamete donations worldwide are made anonymously, and in some countries, including Spain, France, and Denmark, the anonymity of donors is explicitly protected by law. Nonetheless, a growing number of countries have called into question the morality of such practices and are enacting laws allowing children access to identifying information about their gamete donor. A significant reason for the growing legislative support for nonanonymous gamete donations is the belief that donor‐conceived children have a fundamental (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  12.  7
    It Is Just a “Battery”: “Right” to Know in Mitochondrial Replacement.Ilke Turkmendag - 2018 - Science, Technology, and Human Values 43 (1):56-85.
    This article addresses the child’s right to know their genetic origins in mitochondrial donation. It focuses on the UK’s public debate on mitochondrial replacement techniques and examines the claims-making activities that shaped the donor information regulations. During the public consultation, downplaying the significance of the mitochondria helped distinguish mitochondria donors from gamete donors and determine their relational status with the resulting child. As a result, according to the Mitochondrial Donation regulations, mitochondria donors, unlike (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  9
    Research involving the recently deceased: ethics questions that must be answered.Brendan Parent, Olivia S. Kates, Wadih Arap, Arthur Caplan, Brian Childs, Neal W. Dickert, Mary Homan, Kathy Kinlaw, Ayannah Lang, Stephen Latham, Macey L. Levan, Robert D. Truog, Adam Webb, Paul Root Wolpe & Rebecca D. Pentz - forthcoming - Journal of Medical Ethics.
    Research involving recently deceased humans that are physiologically maintained following declaration of death by neurologic criteria—or ‘research involving the recently deceased’—can fill a translational research gap while reducing harm to animals and living human subjects. It also creates new challenges for honouring the donor’s legacy, respecting the rights of donor loved ones, resource allocation and public health. As this research model gains traction, new empirical ethics questions must be answered to preserve public trust in all forms of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  21
    Groll on Bionormativity and the Value of Genetic Knowledge.Bradford Skow - 2023 - International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 16 (1):182-192.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Groll on Bionormativity and the Value of Genetic KnowledgeBradford Skow (bio)1. IntroductionShould people who plan to use donated sperm and/or eggs to conceive a child use an open donor who agrees ahead of time that any resulting children may be told who the donor is? In Conceiving People: Genetic Knowledge and the Ethics of Sperm and Egg Donation (Groll 2021), Daniel Groll answers yes. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  14
    Being the Right Kind of Parent: Conceiving People.Camisha Russell - 2023 - International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 16 (1):193-200.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Being the Right Kind of Parent:Conceiving PeopleCamisha Russell (bio)Daniel Groll's Conceiving People makes one central claim regarding the ethics of using egg or sperm donations to create a child (that one intends to parent): "[P]arents should use an open donor because doing so puts their resulting child in a good position to satisfy the child's likely future interest in having genetic knowledge" (Groll (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  59
    Law, ethics and medicine: The right not to know and preimplantation genetic diagnosis for Huntington’s disease.E. Asscher & B.-J. Koops - 2010 - Journal of Medical Ethics 36 (1):30-33.
    The right not to know is underappreciated in policy-making. Despite its articulation in medical law and ethics, policy-makers too easily let other concerns override the right not to know. This observation is triggered by a recent decision of the Dutch government on embryo selection for Huntington’s disease. This is a monogenetic debilitating disease without cure, leading to death in early middle age, and thus is a likely candidate for preimplantation genetic diagnosis. People possibly affected with the Huntington (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  17.  18
    Whose Right to Know? The Subjectivity of Mothers in Mandatory Paternity Testing.Erin Heidt-Forsythe & Michelle L. McGowan - 2013 - American Journal of Bioethics 13 (5):42-44.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18.  46
    The Right to Know One's Genetic Origin: Are Gamete Donations and Misattributed Paternity Cases Alike?Daniel Sperling - 2013 - American Journal of Bioethics 13 (5):60-62.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  40
    Is There a Right Time to Know?: The Right Not to Know and Genetic Testing in Children.Pascal Borry, Mahsa Shabani & Heidi Carmen Howard - 2014 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 42 (1):19-27.
    The increasing implementation of next-generation sequencing technologies in the clinical context and the expanding commercial offer of genetic tests directly-toconsumers has increased the availability of previously inaccessible genetic information. A particular concern in both situations is how the volume of novel information will affect the processing of genetic and genomic information from minors. For minors, it is argued that in the provision of genetic testing, their “right not to know” should be respected as (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  20.  14
    Introduction to the Symposium on Daniel Groll’s Conceiving People.Alice MacLachlan - 2023 - International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 16 (1):163-165.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Introduction to the Symposium on Daniel Groll's Conceiving PeopleAlice MacLachlan (bio)The ethics of donor conception is often framed as a straightforward clash of rights: the right of would-be parents to procreate and parent, the right of donor-conceived children to know and be raised by their genetic parents, and the right of gamete (sperm and egg) donors to privacy. But in this thoughtful, wide-ranging (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  21
    ‘We Should View Him as an Individual’: The Role of the Child’s Future Autonomy in Shared Decision-Making About Unsolicited Findings in Pediatric Exome Sequencing.W. Dondorp, I. Bolt, A. Tibben, G. De Wert & M. Van Summeren - 2021 - Health Care Analysis 29 (3):249-261.
    In debates about genetic testing of children, as well as about disclosing unsolicited findings (UFs) of pediatric exome sequencing, respect for future autonomy should be regarded as a prima facie consideration for not taking steps that would entail denying the future adult the opportunity to decide for herself about what to know about her own genome. While the argument can be overridden when other, morally more weighty considerations are at stake, whether this is the case can only (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  78
    Thinking ethically about genetic inheritance: liberal rights, communitarianism and the right to privacy for parents of donor insemination children.J. Burr & P. Reynolds - 2008 - Journal of Medical Ethics 34 (4):281-284.
    The issue of genetic inheritance, and particularly the contradictory rights of donors, recipients and donor offspring as to the disclosure of donor identities, is ethically complicated. Donors, donor offspring and parents of donor offspring may appeal to individual rights for confidentiality or disclosure within legal systems based on liberal rights discourse. This paper explores the ethical issues of non-disclosure of genetic inheritance by contrasting two principle models used to articulate the problem—liberal (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  23.  20
    Double‐donor surrogacy and the intention to parent.Teresa Baron - 2023 - Bioethics.
    Assisted reproduction often involves biological contributions by third parties such as egg/sperm donors, mitochondrial DNA donors, and surrogate mothers. However, these arrangements are also characterised by a biological relationship between the child and at least one intending parent. For example, one or both intending parents might use their own eggs/sperm in surrogacy, or an intending mother might conceive using donor sperm or gestate a donor embryo. What happens when this relationship is absent, as in the case (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  25
    Autonomy, the Right Not to Know, and the Right to Know Personal Research Results: What Rights are There, and Who Should Decide about Exceptions?Gert Helgesson - 2014 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 42 (1):28-37.
    Bioethicists have for quite some time discussed the right to know and the right not to know personal health information, such as genetic information acquired in health care and incidental health-related findings in research. Several international ethical guidelines explicitly defend these rights.My own interest in these matters stems from my participation in ethics-related research tied to a longitudinal screening study on Type I diabetes involving young children. A few of the participating parents did not want to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  25.  16
    The United Nations Convention on the Rights of the Child: Implementation in the 21st Century.C. J. Pawson & R. E. S. Tanner - 2005 - Global Bioethics 18 (1):1-15.
    The ratification of the United Nations Convention on the Rights of the Child (UNCRC) demands that those participating nations, adopt the aims of the convention as state responsibilities toward their child citizens. The central premise of the convention is clear: that it is the right of all children to develop to their full potential. The authors propose six basic interdependent developmental requirements if the child is to reach ‘full potential’. Without prioritising any one need, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  88
    Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis: Choosing the “Good Enough” Child[REVIEW]Helen Watt - 2004 - Health Care Analysis 12 (1):51-60.
    Preimplantation genetic diagnosis (PGD) raises serious moral questions concerning the parent-child relationship. Good parents accept their children unconditionally: they do not reject/attack them because they do not have the features they want. There is nothing wrong with treating a child as someone who can help promote some other worthwhile end, providing the child is also respected as an end in him or herself. However, if the child's presence is not valued in itself, regardless of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  27.  19
    Parent-initiated posthumous-assisted reproduction revisited in light of the interest in genetic origins.Ya'arit Bokek-Cohen & Vardit Ravitsky - 2023 - Journal of Medical Ethics 49 (5):357-360.
    A rich literature in bioethics argues against the use of anonymous gamete donation in the name of the ‘interest in knowing one’s genetic origins’. This interest stems from medical as well as psychosocial and identity reasons. The term ‘genealogical bewilderment’ has been coined to express the predicament of those deprived of access to information about their origins. Another rich body of literature in bioethics discusses arguments for and against posthumous-assisted reproduction (PAR), with a recent focus on PAR that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Expanding the Child's Range of Open Futures: A Proposed Basis for the Ethical Assessment of Parental Genetic Trait Selections.Eric B. Schmidt - 2004 - Dissertation, University of Washington
    This dissertation considers the bases upon which ethical assessments of parental genetic trait selections for their children can be made. It argues that if parents engage in genetic trait selections, they must act to expand their child's range of open futures, not to constrict their child's range of open futures or to differentially shift their child's range of open futures. It contends that other proposed distinctions, including distinctions between normal and diseased (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  51
    Accepting Adoption’s Uncertainty: The Limited Ethics of Pre-Adoption Genetic Testing.Kimberly J. Leighton - 2014 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 11 (2):245-260.
    An increasing number of children are adopted in the United States from countries where both medical care and environmental conditions are extremely poor. In response to worries about the accuracy of medical histories, prospective adoptive parents increasingly request genetic testing of children prior to adoption. Though a general consensus on the ethics of pre-adoption genetic testing (PAGT) argues against permitting genetic testing on children available for adoption that is not also permitted for children in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  99
    Genetic Dilemmas and the Child's Right to an Open Future.Dena S. Davis - 1997 - Hastings Center Report 27 (2):7-15.
    Although deeply committed to the model of nondirective counseling, most genetic counselors enter the profession with certain assumptions about health and disability—for example, that it is preferable to be a hearing person than a deaf person. Thus, most genetic counselors are deeply troubled when parents with certain disabilities ask for assistance in having a child who shares their disability. This ethical challenge benefits little from viewing it as a conflict between beneficence and autonomy. The challenge is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   79 citations  
  31. Silver spoons and golden genes: Genetic engineering and the egalitarian ethos.Dov Fox - manuscript
    This Article considers the moral and legal status of practices that aim to modify traits in human offspring. As advancements in reproductive biotechnology give parents greater power to shape the genetic constitution of their children, an emerging school of legal scholars has ushered in a privatized paradigm of genetic control. Commentators defend a constitutionally protected right to prenatal engineering by appeal to the significance of procreative liberty and the promise of producing future generations who are more likely (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  32.  21
    Is it acceptable to contact an anonymous egg donor to facilitate diagnostic genetic testing for the donor-conceived child?Rachel Horton, Benjamin Bell, Angela Fenwick & Anneke M. Lucassen - 2019 - Journal of Medical Ethics 45 (6):357-360.
    We discuss a case where medically optimal investigations of health problems in a donor-conceived child would require their egg donor to participate in genetic testing. We argue that it would be justified to contact the egg donor to ask whether she would consider this, despite her indicating on a historical consent form that she did not wish to take part in future research and that she did not wish to be informed if she (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  33. Genetic Enhancement and the Child’s Right to an Open Future.Davide Battisti - 2020 - Phenomenology and Mind 19 (19):212.
    In this paper, I analyze the ethical implications of genetic enhancement within the specific framework of the “child’s right to an open future” argument (CROF). Whilst there is a broad ethical consensus that genetic modifications for eradicating diseases or disabilities are in line with – or do not violate – CROF, there is huge disagreement about how to ethically understand genetic enhancement. Here, I analyze this disagreement and I provide a revised formulation of the argument in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34. The child's right to an open future: is the principle applicable to non-therapeutic circumcision?Robert J. L. Darby - 2013 - Journal of Medical Ethics 39 (7):463-468.
    The principle of the child's right to an open future was first proposed by the legal philosopher Joel Feinberg and developed further by bioethicist Dena Davis. The principle holds that children possess a unique class of rights called rights in trust—rights that they cannot yet exercise, but which they will be able to exercise when they reach maturity. Parents should not, therefore, take actions that permanently foreclose on or pre-empt the future options of their children, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  35.  87
    Cloning, parenthood, and genetic relatedness.Robert Sparrow - 2006 - Bioethics 20 (6):308–318.
    In this paper I examine what I take to be the best case for reproductive human cloning, as a medical procedure designed to overcome infertility, and argue that it founders on an irresolvable tension in the attitude towards the importance of being ‘genetically related’ to our children implied in the desire to clone. Except in the case where couples are cloning a child they have previously conceived naturally, cloning is unable to establish the right sort of genetic relation (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  36.  29
    Of Modest Proposals and Non-Identity: A Comment on the Right to Know Your Genetic Parents.I. Glenn Cohen - 2013 - American Journal of Bioethics 13 (5):45-47.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  45
    The Ethics of General Population Preventive Genomic Sequencing: Rights and Social Justice.Clair Morrissey & Rebecca L. Walker - 2018 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 43 (1):22-43.
    Advances in DNA sequencing technology open new possibilities for public health genomics, especially in the form of general population preventive genomic sequencing. Such screening programs would sit at the intersection of public health and preventive health care, and thereby at once invite and resist the use of clinical ethics and public health ethics frameworks. Despite their differences, these ethics frameworks traditionally share a central concern for individual rights. We examine two putative individual rights—the right not to (...), and the child’s right to an open future—frequently invoked in discussions of predictive genetic testing, in order to explore their potential contribution to evaluating this new practice. Ultimately, we conclude that traditional clinical and public health ethics frameworks, and these two rights in particular, should be complemented by a social justice perspective in order adequately to characterize the ethical dimensions of general population PGS programs. (shrink)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  38.  33
    What can we Learn from Patients’ Ethical Thinking about the right ‘not to know’ in Genomics? Lessons from Cancer Genetic Testing for Genetic Counselling.Lorraine Cowley - 2016 - Bioethics 30 (8):628-635.
    This article is based on a qualitative empirical project about a distinct kinship group who were among the first identified internationally as having a genetic susceptibility to cancer. 50 were invited to participate. 15, who had all accepted testing, were interviewed. They form a unique case study. This study aimed to explore interviewees’ experiences of genetic testing and how these influenced their family relationships. A key finding was that participants framed the decision to be tested (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  39.  17
    Part of my story. The meaning and experiences of genes and genetics for sperm donor-conceived offspring.Astrid Indekeu & Kristien Hens - 2019 - New Genetics and Society 38 (1):18-37.
    Existing empirical research often do not explain which concepts about genetics underlie the assumption that genetic information is deemed important for donor-conceived offspring. This study focused on how donor-conceived individuals following anonymous sperm donation give meaning to and make sense of genes and genetics. Analysis is based on focus groups and interviews with adult donor-conceived offspring. Findings suggest that genes are part of their specific context of being donor-conceived but also play a role in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  27
    The ethics of testing and research of manufactured organs on brain-dead/recently deceased subjects.Brendan Parent, Bruce Gelb, Stephen Latham, Ariane Lewis, Laura L. Kimberly & Arthur L. Caplan - 2020 - Journal of Medical Ethics 46 (3):199-204.
    Over 115 000 people are waiting for life-saving organ transplants, of whom a small fraction will receive transplants and many others will die while waiting. Existing efforts to expand the number of available organs, including increasing the number of registered donors and procuring organs in uncontrolled environments, are crucial but unlikely to address the shortage in the near future and will not improve donor/recipient compatibility or organ quality. If successful, organ bioengineering can solve the shortage and improve functional outcomes. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  41.  21
    Beneath the Rhetoric: The Role of Rights in the Practice of Non-Anonymous Gamete Donation.Lucy Frith - 2001 - Bioethics 15 (5-6):473-484.
    The use of rights based arguments to justify claims that donor offspring should have access to information identifying their gamete donor has become increasingly widespread. In this paper, I do not intend to revisit the debate about the validity of such rights. Rather, the purpose is to examine the way that such alleged rights have been implemented by those legislatures that have allowed access to identifying information. I will argue that serious inconsistencies exist between (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  42.  27
    The Right to Know and the Right Not to Know: Genetic Privacy and Responsibility.Ruth Chadwick, Mairi Levitt & Darren Shickle (eds.) - 2014 - Cambridge University Press.
    The privacy concerns discussed in the 1990s in relation to the New Genetics failed to anticipate the relevant issues for individuals, families, geneticists and society. Consumers, for example, can now buy their personal genetic information and share it online. The challenges facing genetic privacy have evolved as new biotechnologies have developed, and personal privacy is increasingly challenged by the irrepressible flow of electronic data between the personal and public spheres and by surveillance for terrorism and security risks. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  43.  25
    The ethics of anonymous gamete donation: is there a right to know one's genetic origins?Inmaculada De Melo-Martín - 2014 - Hastings Center Report 44 (2):28-35.
    A growing number of jurisdictions hold that gamete donors must be identifiable to the children born with their eggs or sperm, on grounds that being able to know about one's genetic origins is a fundamental moral right. But the argument for that belief has not yet been adequately made.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  44.  84
    The parental love argument against 'designing' babies: the harm in knowing that one has been selected or enhanced.Anca Gheaus - 2014 - In Ruth Chadwick, Mairi Levitt & Darren Shickle (eds.), The Right to Know and the Right Not to Know: Genetic Privacy and Responsibility. Cambridge University Press. pp. 151-164.
    In this chapter, I argue that children who were selected for particular traits or genetically enhanced might feel, for this reason, less securely, spontaneously and fairly loved by their parents, which would constitute significant harm. ‘Parents’ refers, throughout this chapter, to the people who perform the social function of rearing children, rather than to procreators. I rely on an understanding of adequate parental love which includes several characteristics: parents should not make children feel they are loved conditionally, for features (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  40
    Implementing Expanded Prenatal Genetic Testing: Should Parents Have Access to Any and All Fetal Genetic Information?Michelle J. Bayefsky & Benjamin E. Berkman - 2022 - American Journal of Bioethics 22 (2):4-22.
    Prenatal genetic testing is becoming available for an increasingly broad set of diseases, and it is only a matter of time before parents can choose to test for hundreds, if not thousands, of genetic conditions in their fetuses. Should access to certain kinds of fetal genetic information be limited, and if so, on what basis? We evaluate a range of considerations including reproductive autonomy, parental rights, disability rights, and the rights and interests (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  46.  13
    Autonomous Choice and the Right to Know One's Genetic Origins.Vardit Ravitsky - 2014 - Hastings Center Report 44 (2):36-37.
    In “The Ethics of Anonymous Gamete Donation: Is There a Right to Know One's Genetic Origins?,” Inmaculada de Melo‐Martín deconstructs the interests the right is supposed to protect. She argues that these interests are not set back or thwarted when one has no access to one's genetic origins. The basis of her argument is that we lack robust empirical evidence that donor‐conceived individuals suffer certain alleged harms, and that even when such harms are present, they do (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  47. Nothing if not family? Genetic ties beyond the parent/child dyad.Daniela Cutas - 2023 - Bioethics (8):763-770.
    Internationally, there is considerable inconsistency in the recognition and regulation of children's genetic connections outside the family. In the context of gamete and embryo donation, challenges for regulation seem endless. In this paper, I review some of the paths that have been taken to manage children' being closely genetically related to people outside their families. I do so against the background of recognising the importance of children's interests as moral status holders. I look at recent qualitative research involving (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48.  62
    Disclosing misattributed paternity.Lainie Friedman Ross - 1996 - Bioethics 10 (2):114–130.
    ABSTRACTIn 1994, the Committee on Assessing Genetic Risks of the Institute of Medicine published their recommendations regarding the ethical issues raised by advances in genetics. One of the Committee's recommendation was to inform women when test results revealed misattributed paternity, but not to disclose this information to the women's partners. The Committee's reason for withholding such information was that “'genetic testing should not be used in ways that disrupt families”. In this paper, I argue that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  49.  11
    Lowering the age limit of access to the identity of the gamete donor by donor offspring: the argument against.Guido Pennings - 2024 - Journal of Medical Ethics 50 (5):292-294.
    Countries that abolished donor anonymity have imposed age limits for access to certain types of information by donor offspring. In the UK and the Netherlands, a debate has started on whether these age limits should be lowered or abolished all together. This article presents some arguments against lowering the age limits as a general rule for all donor children. The focus is on whether one should give a child the right to obtain the identity of the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  7
    The right to know and genetic testing.Mark Sheehan - 2015 - Journal of Medical Ethics 41 (4):287-288.
1 — 50 / 994