Results for 'Retinal image'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Retinal Images and Object Files: Towards Empirically Evaluating Philosophical Accounts of Visual Perspective.Assaf Weksler - 2016 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 7 (1):91-103.
    According to an influential philosophical view I call “the relational properties view”, “perspectival” properties, such as the elliptical appearance of a tilted coin, are relational properties of external objects. Philosophers have assessed this view on the basis of phenomenological, epistemological or other purely philosophical considerations. My aim in this paper is to examine whether it is possible to evaluate RPV empirically. In the first, negative part of the paper I consider and reject a certain tempting way of doing so. In (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  2.  26
    Upright Vision and the Retinal Image.George M. Stratton - 1897 - Psychological Review 4 (2):182-187.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  3.  10
    Berkeley and Molyneux on Retinal Images.Colin M. Turbayne - 1955 - Journal of the History of Ideas 16 (1/4):339.
  4. Optical geometry, retinal images and Berkeley's corpuscles.Richard Glauser - 2010 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de L Etranger 135 (2):301-301.
  5.  82
    Monstrous faces and a world transformed: Merleau-Ponty, Dolezal, and the enactive approach on vision without inversion of the retinal image.Susan M. Bredlau - 2011 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 10 (4):481-498.
    The world perceived by a person undergoing vision without inversion of the retinal image has traditionally been described as inverted. Drawing on the philosophical work of Maurice Merleau-Ponty and the empirical research of Hubert Dolezal, I argue that this description is more reflective of a representationist conception of vision than of actual visual experience. The world initially perceived in vision without inversion of the retinal image is better described as lacking in lived significance rather than inverted; (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6.  38
    Vision without inversion of the retinal image.George M. Stratton - 1897 - Psychological Review 4 (4):341-360.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  7.  89
    Vision without inversion of the retinal image.G. M. Stratton - 1897 - Psychological Review 4 (5):463-481.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  8.  62
    Some preliminary experiments on vision without inversion of the retinal image.George M. Stratton - 1896 - Psychological Review 3 (6):611-617.
  9.  20
    Spatial differential and integral operations in human vision: Implications of stabilized retinal image fading.Lawrence E. Arend - 1973 - Psychological Review 80 (5):374-395.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  10.  13
    Foundations of spatial vision: From retinal images to perceived shapes.Joseph S. Lappin & Warren D. Craft - 2000 - Psychological Review 107 (1):6-38.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  11.  12
    Eye-Tracking Reveals that the Strength of the Vertical-Horizontal Illusion Increases as the Retinal Image Becomes More Stable with Fixation.Philippe A. Chouinard, Hayden J. Peel & Oriane Landry - 2017 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 11.
  12.  45
    Reid Versus Berkeley on the Inverted Retinal Image.James Van Cleve - 2003 - Philosophical Topics 31 (1-2):425-455.
  13.  8
    Reid Versus Berkeley on the Inverted Retinal Image.James Van Cleve - 2003 - Philosophical Topics 31 (1-2):425-455.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  19
    The idea that space perception involves more than eye movement signals and the position of the retinal image has come up before.Alexander A. Skavenski - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):331-332.
  15.  30
    Reid Versus Berkeley on the Inverted Retinal Image.Gideon Yaffe - 2003 - Philosophical Topics 31 (1-2):425-455.
  16.  11
    Retinal and assumed size cues as determinants of size and distance perception.J. C. Baird - 1963 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 66 (2):155.
  17.  76
    Seeing and retinal stability: On a sensorimotor argument for the necessity of eye movement for sight.Dan Cavedon-Taylor - 2013 - Philosophical Psychology 26 (2):263 - 266.
    Sensorimotor theorists of perception have argued that eye movement is a necessary condition for seeing on the basis that subjects whose retinal images do not move undergo a form of blindness. I show that the argument does not work.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18.  21
    Retinal Justice: Rats, Maps, and Masks.Peter Goodrich - 2021 - Critical Inquiry 47 (2):241-271.
    A judge springs out of his car on the way to court in downtown Chicago and takes photographs of an inflatable rat. A while later he inserts these photographs into a decision involving another inflatable rodent. Judges now regularly insert pictures in judgments, but there is no study either of the genres or the precedential status of these modern visual emblemata, these pictorial interventions in the record. Using a comparative visual corpus of over three hundred images extracted from diverse common (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  41
    Exploring wavelet transforms for morphological differentiation between functionally different cat retinal ganglion cells.H. F. Jelinek, R. M. Cesar & J. J. G. Leandro - 2003 - Brain and Mind 4 (1):67-90.
    Cognition or higher brain activity is sometimes seen as a phenomenon greater than the sum of its parts. This viewpoint however is largely dependent on the state of the art of experimental techniques that endeavor to characterize morphology and its association to function. Retinal ganglion cells are readily accessible for this work and we discuss recent advances in computational techniques in identifying novel parameters that describe structural attributes possibly associated with specific function. These parameters are based on calculating wavelet (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  50
    Optique géométrique, images rétiniennes et corpuscules chez Berkeley.Richard Glauser - 2010 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 135 (1):7 - 18.
    Dans l'Essai pour une nouvelle théorie de la vision (1709) Berkeley critique un usage illégitime de l'optique géométrique dans l'explication de la perception des qualités spatiales. Toutefois, dans la Théorie de la vision défendue et expliquée (1733), il assigne à l'optique géométrique un rôle théorique positif, à côté de sa propre théorie de la vision. Nous défendons la thèse suivant laquelle une image rétinienne, chez Berkeley, est une configuration de corpuscules en mouvement, tangibles de droit. Cette lecture corrobore l'interprétation (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  11
    Extrastriate activity reflects the absence of local retinal input.Poutasi W. B. Urale, Lydia Zhu, Roberta Gough, Derek Arnold & Dietrich Samuel Schwarzkopf - 2023 - Consciousness and Cognition 114 (C):103566.
    The physiological blind spot corresponds to the optic disc where the retina contains no light-detecting photoreceptor cells. Our perception seemingly fills in this gap in input. Here we suggest that rather than an active process, such perceptual filling-in could instead be a consequence of the integration of visual inputs at higher stages of processing discounting the local absence of retinal input. Using functional brain imaging, we resolved the retinotopic representation of the physiological blind spot in early human visual cortex (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  11
    IDOCS: Intelligent distributed ontology consensus system - The use of machine learning in retinal drusen phenotyping.George Thomas, Michael A. Grassi, John R. Lee, Albert O. Edwards, Michael B. Gorin, Ronald Klein, Thomas L. Casavant, Todd E. Scheetz, Edwin M. Stone & Andrew B. Williams - unknown
    PurposeTo use the power of knowledge acquisition and machine learning in the development of a collaborative computer classification system based on the features of age-related macular degeneration (AMD).MethodsA vocabulary was acquired from four AMD experts who examined 100 ophthalmoscopic images. The vocabulary was analyzed, hierarchically structured, and incorporated into a collaborative computer classification system called IDOCS. Using this system, three of the experts examined images from a second set of digital images compiled from more than 1000 patients with AMD. Images (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. AVOIDING NEUROSCIENCE's PROBLEMS WITH VISUAL IMAGES: EVIDENCE THAT RETINAS ARE CONSCIOUS.Mostyn W. Jones - manuscript
    Neuroscience hasn’t shown how quite similar sensory circuits encode quite different colors and other qualia, nor how the unified pictorial form of images is encoded, nor how these codes yield conscious images. Neuroscience’s fixation here on cortical codes may be the culprit. Treating conscious images partly as retinal substances may avoid these problems. The evidence for conscious retinal images is that (a) the cortical codes for images are quite problematic, (b) injecting retinas with certain genes turns dichromats into (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  19
    Picture this! Words versus images in Wittgenstein's nachlass Herbert Hrachovec.Words Versus Images In Wittgenstein'S. - 2004 - In Tamás Demeter (ed.), Essays on Wittgenstein and Austrian Philosophy: In Honour of J.C. Nyíri. BRILL. pp. 197.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  29
    Alhazen, Leonardo, and late-medieval speculation on the inversion of images in the eye.Bruce Eastwood - 1986 - Annals of Science 43 (5):413-446.
    No one before Platter and Kepler proposed retinal reception of an inverted visual image. The dominant tradition in visual theory, especially that of Alhazen and his Western followers, subordinated the intra-ocular geometry of visual rays to the requirement for an upright image and to preconceptions about the precise nature of the visual spirit and its part in vision. Henry of Langenstein and an anonymous glossator in the late Middle Ages proposed alternatives to Alhazen, including the suggestion of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  16
    Factors determining the direction of the visual after-image drift.T. G. Hermans - 1941 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 28 (2):187.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. The Sensory Core and the Medieval Foundations of Early Modern Perceptual Theory.Gary Hatfield & William Epstein - 1979 - Isis 70 (3):363-384.
    This article seeks the origin, in the theories of Ibn al-Haytham (Alhazen), Descartes, and Berkeley, of two-stage theories of spatial perception, which hold that visual perception involves both an immediate representation of the proximal stimulus in a two-dimensional ‘‘sensory core’’ and also a subsequent perception of the three dimensional world. The works of Ibn al-Haytham, Descartes, and Berkeley already frame the major theoretical options that guided visual theory into the twentieth century. The field of visual perception was the first area (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  28.  17
    Affordances of the Networked Image.Centre for the Study of the Networked Image, Geoff Cox, Annet Dekker, Andrew Dewdney & Katrina Sluis - 2021 - Nordic Journal of Aesthetics 30 (61-62):40-45.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Über den Homunkulus-Fehlschluß.Geert Keil - 2003 - Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 57 (1):1 - 26.
    Ein Homunkulus im philosophischen Sprachgebrauch ist eine postulierte menschenähnliche Instanz, die ausdrücklich oder unausdrücklich zur Erklärung der Arbeitsweise des menschlichen Geistes herangezogen wird. Als Homunkulus-Fehlschluß wird die Praxis bezeichnet, Prädikate, die auf kognitive oder perzeptive Leistungen einer ganzen Person zutreffen, auch auf Teile von Personen oder auf subpersonale Vorgänge anzuwenden, was typischerweise zu einem Regreß führt. Der vorliegende Beitrag erörtert den Homunkulus-Fehlschluß zunächst in argumentationstheoretischer Hinsicht und stellt dabei ein Diagnoseschema auf. Dann werden zwei Anwendungsfelder erörtert: Instanzenmodelle der Psyche (Platon, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  30.  10
    The Human Condition in Hilary of Poitiers: The Will and Original Sin Between Origen and Augustine.Isabella Image - 2017 - Oxford University Press.
    This study examines the theology of the fourth-century bishop, Hilary of Poitiers, concentrating particularly on two commentaries written at different times in his life. The main focus of the study is on Hilary's anthropological theology.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  18
    The perception of the egocentric orientation of a line.Irvin Rock - 1954 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 48 (5):367.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  32.  14
    Projections, Perceptual Constancy, and Geometry.Yuval Dolev - 2022 - Review of Metaphysics 76 (2):305-323.
    Abstract:The notions "retinal images" and "retinal projection" are ubiquitous in both the scientific and philosophical literature on perception. However, this article argues that they belong to the former and should be kept out of the latter. In the context of the empirical investigation of perception, projections play a crucial role, and help articulate pressing research problems. But, as part of the phenomenological and conceptual analysis of perception, projections give rise to untenable models and to avoidable conundrums, such as (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Empirical evidence for perspectival similarity.Jorge Morales & Chaz Firestone - 2023 - Psychological Review 1 (1):311-320.
    When a circular coin is rotated in depth, is there any sense in which it comes to resemble an ellipse? While this question is at the center of a rich and divided philosophical tradition (with some scholars answering affirmatively and some negatively), Morales et al. (2020, 2021) took an empirical approach, reporting 10 experiments whose results favor such perspectival similarity. Recently, Burge and Burge (2022) offered a vigorous critique of this work, objecting to its approach and conclusions on both philosophical (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  34. Franck dalmas.Imagined Existences & A. Phenomenology of Image Creation - 2009 - In Anna-Teresa Tymieniecka (ed.), Existence, historical fabulation, destiny. Springer Verlag. pp. 93.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Sustained Representation of Perspectival Shape.Jorge Morales, Axel Bax & Chaz Firestone - 2020 - Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 117 (26):14873–14882.
    Arguably the most foundational principle in perception research is that our experience of the world goes beyond the retinal image; we perceive the distal environment itself, not the proximal stimulation it causes. Shape may be the paradigm case of such “unconscious inference”: When a coin is rotated in depth, we infer the circular object it truly is, discarding the perspectival ellipse projected on our eyes. But is this really the fate of such perspectival shapes? Or does a tilted (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  36. Perceiving the World Outside: How to Solve the Distality Problem for Informational Teleosemantics.Peter Https://Orcidorg288X Schulte - 2018 - Philosophical Quarterly 68 (271):349-369.
    Perceptual representations have distal content: they represent external objects and their properties, not light waves or retinal images. This basic fact presents a fundamental problem for ‘input-oriented’ theories of perceptual content. As I show in the first part of this paper, this even holds for what is arguably the most sophisticated input-oriented theory to date, namely Karen Neander's informational teleosemantics. In the second part of the paper, I develop a new version of informational teleosemantics, drawing partly on empirical psychology, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  37.  30
    Will understanding vision require a wholly empirical paradigm?Dale Purves, Yaniv Morgenstern & William T. Wojtach - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6:137070.
    Based on electrophysiological and anatomical studies, a prevalent conception is that the visual system recovers features of the world from retinal images to generate perceptions and guide behavior. This paradigm, however, is unable to explain why visual perceptions differ from physical measurements, or how behavior could routinely succeed on this basis. An alternative is that vision does not recover features of the world, but assigns perceptual qualities empirically by associating frequently occurring stimulus patterns with useful responses on the basis (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Ecological Psychology and Enactivism: Perceptually-Guided Action vs. Sensation-Based Enaction1.Catherine Read & Agnes Szokolszky - 2020 - Frontiers in Psychology 11:532803.
    Ecological Psychology and Enactivism both challenge representationist cognitive science, but the two approaches have only begun to engage in dialogue. Further conceptual clarification is required in which differences are as important as common ground. This paper enters the dialogue by focusing on important differences. After a brief account of the parallel histories of Ecological Psychology and Enactivism, we cover incompatibility between them regarding their theories of sensation and perception. First, we show how and why in ecological theory perception is, crucially, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  39.  77
    Shape, perspective, and what is and is not perceived: Comment on Morales, Bax, and Firestone (2020).Johannes Burge & Tyler Burge - 2023 - Psychological Review 130 (4):1125-1136.
    Psychology and philosophy have long reflected on the role of perspective in vision. Since the dawn of modern vision science—roughly, since Helmholtz in the late 1800s—scientific explanations in vision have focused on understanding the computations that transform the sensed retinal image into percepts of the three-dimensional environment. The standard view in the science is that distal properties—viewpoint-independent properties of the environment (object shape) and viewpoint-dependent relational properties (3D orientation relative to the viewer)–are perceptually represented and that properties of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40.  42
    Psychophysical scaling: Judgments of attributes or objects?Gregory R. Lockhead - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):543-558.
    Psychophysical scaling models of the form R = f, with R the response and I some intensity of an attribute, all assume that people judge the amounts of an attribute. With simple biases excepted, most also assume that judgments are independent of space, time, and features of the situation other than the one being judged. Many data support these ideas: Magnitude estimations of brightness increase with luminance. Nevertheless, I argue that the general model is wrong. The stabilized retinal (...) literature shows that nothing is seen if light does not change over time. The classification literature shows that dimensions often combine to produce emergent properties that cannot be described by the elements in the stimulus. These and other effects cannot be adjusted for by simply adding variables to the general model because some factors do not combine linearly. The proposed alternative is that people initially judge the entire stimulus – the object in terms of its environment. This agrees with the constancy literature that shows that objects and their attributes are identified through their relations to other aspects of the scene. That the environment determines judgments is masked in scaling studies where the standard procedure is to hold context constant. In a typical brightness study the essential stimulus might be the intensity of the light or a difference between the light and the background. The two are perfectly confounded. This issue is examined in the case of audition. Judgments of the loudness of a tone depend on how much that tone differs from the previous tone in both pitch and loudness. To judge loudness people first seem to process the stimulus object in terms of differences between it and other aspects in the situation; only then do they assess the feature of interest. Psychophysical judgments will therefore be better interpreted by theories of attention that are based in biology or psychology than those that are based in classical physics. (shrink)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  41. Action-based Theories of Perception.Robert Briscoe & Rick Grush - 2015 - In The Stanford Encylcopedia of Philosophy. pp. 1-66.
    Action is a means of acquiring perceptual information about the environment. Turning around, for example, alters your spatial relations to surrounding objects and, hence, which of their properties you visually perceive. Moving your hand over an object’s surface enables you to feel its shape, temperature, and texture. Sniffing and walking around a room enables you to track down the source of an unpleasant smell. Active or passive movements of the body can also generate useful sources of perceptual information (Gibson 1966, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  42.  11
    The experimental control of visual factors.T. H. Howells & T. H. Cutler - 1933 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 16 (6):865.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. The logic of how-questions.William Jaworski - 2009 - Synthese 166 (1):133 - 155.
    Philosophers and scientists are concerned with the why and the how of things. Questions like the following are so much grist for the philosopher’s and scientist’s mill: How can we be free and yet live in a deterministic universe?, How do neural processes give rise to conscious experience?, Why does conscious experience accompany certain physiological events at all?, How is a three-dimensional perception of depth generated by a pair of two-dimensional retinal images?. Since Belnap and Steel’s pioneering work on (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  44. Is the Eye Like What It Sees? A Critique of Aristotle on Sensing by Assimilation.Mohan Matthen - 2019 - Vivarium 57 (3-4):268-292.
    Aristotle held that perception consists in the reception of external sensory qualities (or sensible forms) in the sensorium. This idea is repeated in many forms in contemporary philosophy, including, with regard to vision, in the idea (still not firmly rejected) that the retinal image consists of points of colour. In fact, this is false. Colour is a quality that is constructed by the visual system, and though it is possible to be a realist about colour, it is completely (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  35
    The Pre-Objective World.Michael Kullman & Charles Taylor - 1958 - Review of Metaphysics 12 (1):108 - 132.
    Merleau-Ponty's views are the fruit of the method of "phenomenological description," in part taken over from Husserl. This consists of describing our "original" experience of the world without assuming the truth or validity of any statements we may know about it. Unlike the Cartesian method it does not mean that we should suppose false those statements we know are true, but rather that we should "put these in brackets," or "suspend" their rel- evance, consider them as void of ontological implications. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  46.  21
    The imitation of nature.John Hyman - 1989 - New York, NY, USA: Blackwell.
    Available from UMI in association with The British Library. Requires signed TDF. ;Metaphor and analogy are the scaffolding of science. Kepler's theory of the retinal picture could not have been built without the analogy between an eye and a camera obscura, and, two hundred and fifty years later, Charles Darwin devoted most of the first chapter of The origin of Species to discussion of pigeon fanciers. Unlike Darwin, Kepler was bewitched by his own imagination and was led to wonder (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  47.  47
    Failures to see: Attentive blank stares revealed by change blindness.Gideon P. Caplovitz, Robert Fendrich & Howard C. Hughes - 2008 - Consciousness and Cognition 17 (3):877-886.
    Change blindness illustrates a remarkable limitation in visual processing by demonstrating that substantial changes in a visual scene can go undetected. Because these changes can ultimately be detected using top–down driven search processes, many theories assign a central role to spatial attention in overcoming change blindness. Surprisingly, it has been reported that change blindness can occur during blink-contingent changes even when observers fixate the changing location [O’Regan, J. K., Deubel, H., Clark, J. J., & Rensink, R. A. . Picture changes (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  48.  32
    Motion perception during selfmotion: The direct versus inferential controversy revisited.Alexander H. Wertheim - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):293-311.
    According to the traditional inferential theory of perception, percepts of object motion or stationarity stem from an evaluation of afferent retinal signals (which encode image motion) with the help of extraretinal signals (which encode eye movements). According to direct perception theory, on the other hand, the percepts derive from retinally conveyed information only. Neither view is compatible with a perceptual phenomenon that occurs during visually induced sensations of ego motion (vection). A modified version of inferential theory yields a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  49.  14
    Neuronal death of the cancellation theory?Claude Prablanc - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):274-275.
    The question of how the brain can construct a stable representation of the external world despite eye movements is a very old one. If there have been some wrong statements of problems (such as the inverted retinal image), other statements are less naive and have led to analytic solutions possibly adopted by the brain to counteract the spurious effects of eye movements. Following the MacKay (1973) objections to the analytic view of perceptual stability, Bridgeman et al. claim that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  7
    The Role of Size Contrast and Empty Space in the Explanation of the Moon Illusion.Farshad Nemati - forthcoming - Foundations of Science:1-18.
    The much larger appearance of the moon near horizon than the perceived size of the moon at zenith has motivated many scientists to develop theories that aim at explaining this puzzling phenomenon. Considering that the size of retinal images of the moon in these positions are very similar, the explanation of difference in their apparent sizes has relied on perceptual cues of distance embedded in the retinal image of their respective contexts. Although this account of the moon (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000