Results for 'Physical geometry'

988 found
Order:
  1. Vigier III.Spin Foam Spinors & Fundamental Space-Time Geometry - 2000 - Foundations of Physics 30 (1).
  2.  55
    Physical Geometry.James P. Binkoski - 2016 - Dissertation, University of Massachusetts, Amherst
    All physical theories, from classical Newtonian mechanics to relativistic quantum field theory, entail propositions concerning the geometric structure of spacetime. To give an example, the general theory of relativity entails that spacetime is curved, smooth, and four-dimensional. In this dissertation, I take the structural commitments of our theories seriously and ask: how is such structure instantiated in the physical world? Mathematically, a property like 'being curved' is perfectly well-defined insofar as we know what it means for a mathematical (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Time and physical geometry.Hilary Putnam - 1967 - Journal of Philosophy 64 (8):240-247.
  4. Physical Geometry and Fundamental Metaphysics.Cian Dorr - 2011 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 111 (1pt1):135-159.
    I explore some ways in which one might base an account of the fundamental metaphysics of geometry on the mathematical theory of Linear Structures recently developed by Tim Maudlin (2010). Having considered some of the challenges facing this approach, Idevelop an alternative approach, according to which the fundamental ontology includes concrete entities structurally isomorphic to functions from space-time points to real numbers.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5.  94
    On the hypotheses underlying physical geometry.J. Anandan - 1980 - Foundations of Physics 10 (7-8):601-629.
    The relationship between physics and geometry is examined in classical and quantum physics based on the view that the symmetry group of physics and the automorphism group of the geometry are the same. Examination of quantum phenomena reveals that the space-time manifold is not appropriate for quantum theory. A different conception of geometry for quantum theory on the group manifold, which may be an arbitrary Lie group, is proposed. This provides a unified description of gravity and gauge (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  6. Spacetime theory as physical geometry.Robert Disalle - 1995 - Erkenntnis 42 (3):317-337.
    Discussions of the metaphysical status of spacetime assume that a spacetime theory offers a causal explanation of phenomena of relative motion, and that the fundamental philosophical question is whether the inference to that explanation is warranted. I argue that those assumptions are mistaken, because they ignore the essential character of spacetime theory as a kind of physical geometry. As such, a spacetime theory does notcausally explain phenomena of motion, but uses them to construct physicaldefinitions of basic geometrical structures (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  7. Physical geometry and physical laws.Arthur Fine - 1964 - Philosophy of Science 31 (2):156-162.
  8. New Foundations for Physical Geometry: The Theory of Linear Structures.Tim Maudlin - 2014 - Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
    Tim Maudlin sets out a completely new method for describing the geometrical structure of spaces, and thus a better mathematical tool for describing and understanding space-time. He presents a historical review of the development of geometry and topology, and then his original Theory of Linear Structures.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  9. Time, topology and physical geometry.Tim Maudlin - 2010 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 84 (1):63-78.
    The standard mathematical account of the sub-metrical geometry of a space employs topology, whose foundational concept is the open set. This proves to be an unhappy choice for discrete spaces, and offers no insight into the physical origin of geometrical structure. I outline an alternative, the Theory of Linear Structures, whose foundational concept is the line. Application to Relativistic space-time reveals that the whole geometry of space-time derives from temporal structure. In this sense, instead of spatializing time, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  10.  77
    Constructing or completing physical geometry? On the relation between theory and evidence in accounts of space-time structure.Martin Carrier - 1990 - Philosophy of Science 57 (3):369-394.
    The aim of this paper is to discuss the relation between the observation basis and the theoretical principles of General Relativity. More specifically, this relation is analyzed with respect to constructive axiomatizations of the observation basis of space-time theories, on the one hand, and in attempts to complete them, on the other. The two approaches exclude one another so that a choice between them is necessary. I argue that the completeness approach is preferable for methodological reasons.
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  11.  44
    Time and Physical Geometry. A Formalization of Putnam’s Proof.Jan Czerniawski - forthcoming - Logic and Logical Philosophy:1.
    Putnam’s proof that time flow is incompatible with Relativity is underestimated, mostly due to Stein’s interpretation of the notion of reality in it as a two-term relation. This interpretation makes it vulnerable to easy criticism and makes various ways of escaping its conclusion possible. An alternative approach is proposed, resulting in a formalization which seems closer to Putnam’s intentions where reality is interpreted as a non-relational property. Although it makes the proof immune to all standard strategies of blocking the proof, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  17
    Physiological Optics and Physical Geometry.David Jalal Hyder - 2001 - Science in Context 14 (3):419-456.
    ArgumentHermann von Helmholtz’s distinction between “pure intuitive” and “physicalgeometry must be counted as the most influential of his many contributions to the philosophy of science. In a series of papers from the 1860s and 70s, Helmholtz argued against Kant’s claim that our knowledge of Euclidean geometry was an a priori condition for empirical knowledge. He claimed that geometrical propositions could be meaningful only if they were taken to concern the behaviors of physical bodies used in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  13.  35
    New Foundations for Physical Geometry, by Tim Maudlin.Carolyn Brighouse - 2015 - Mind 124 (496):1332-1338.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  11
    The Completeness of Scientific Theories: On the Derivation of Empirical Indicators within a Theoretical Framework: The Case of Physical Geometry.Martin Carrier - 2012 - Springer.
    Earlier in this century, many philosophers of science (for example, Rudolf Carnap) drew a fairly sharp distinction between theory and observation, between theoretical terms like 'mass' and 'electron', and observation terms like 'measures three meters in length' and 'is _2° Celsius'. By simply looking at our instruments we can ascertain what numbers our measurements yield. Creatures like mass are different: we determine mass by calculation; we never directly observe a mass. Nor an electron: this term is introduced in order to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  15.  5
    Quantum Potential: Physics, Geometry and Algebra.Ignazio Licata - 2014 - Cham: Imprint: Springer. Edited by Davide Fiscaletti.
    Recently the interest in Bohm realist interpretation of quantum mechanics has grown. The important advantage of this approach lies in the possibility to introduce non-locality ab initio, and not as an "unexpected host". In this book the authors give a detailed analysis of quantum potential, the non-locality term and its role in quantum cosmology and information. The different approaches to the quantum potential are analysed, starting from the original attempt to introduce a realism of particles trajectories (influenced by de Broglie's (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  6
    Rigidity, Force and Physical Geometry.Carlton B. Weinberg - 1941 - Philosophy of Science 8 (4):506-532.
    From the desire to find support and confirmation for our personal sensory observations, and from the human interest in sharing our experiences with others, there emerges a basic principle of scientific method: We demand the possibility of intelligible communication and agreement concerning individuals' sensory perceptions in particular and their experiences in general. This requirement is made both for the natural and social sciences. The raw material offered for logical organization must be capable of exhibiting an inter-subjective character—such material, or protocols, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  17.  14
    Rigidity, force and physical geometry.Carleton B. Weinberg - 1941 - Philosophy of Science 8 (4):506-532.
    From the desire to find support and confirmation for our personal sensory observations, and from the human interest in sharing our experiences with others, there emerges a basic principle of scientific method: We demand the possibility of intelligible communication and agreement concerning individuals' sensory perceptions in particular and their experiences in general. This requirement is made both for the natural and social sciences. The raw material offered for logical organization must be capable of exhibiting an inter-subjective character—such material, or protocols, (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  56
    Algebraic Fields and the Dynamical Approach to Physical Geometry.Tushar Menon - 2019 - Philosophy of Science 86 (5):1273-1283.
    Brown and Pooley’s ‘dynamical approach’ to physical theories asserts, in opposition to the orthodox position on physical geometry, that facts about physical geometry are grounded in, or explained by, facts about dynamical fields, not the other way round. John Norton has claimed that the proponent of the dynamical approach is illicitly committed to spatiotemporal presumptions in ‘constructing’ space-time from facts about dynamical symmetries. In this article, I present an abstract, algebraic formulation of field theories and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  19.  49
    Husserl’s Conception of Physical Theories and Physical Geometry in the Time of the Prolegomena: A Comparison with Duhem’s and Poincaré’s Views.Guillermo E. Rosado Haddock - 2012 - Global Philosophy 22 (1):171-193.
    This paper discusses Husserl’s views on physical theories in the first volume of his Logical Investigations, and compares them with those of his contemporaries Pierre Duhem and Henri Poincaré. Poincaré’s views serve as a bridge to a discussion of Husserl’s almost unknown views on physical geometry from about 1890 on, which in comparison even with Poincaré’s—not to say Frege’s—or almost any other philosopher of his time, represented a rupture with the philosophical tradition and were much more in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. New Foundations for Physical Geometry: The Theory of Linear Structures, by Tim Maudlin: Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. x + 363, £50.00. [REVIEW]John P. Burgess - 2015 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 93 (1):187-190.
  21.  42
    Differential Sheaves and Connections: A Natural Approach to Physical Geometry.Anastasios Mallios & Elias Zafiris - 2015 - World Scientific.
    This unique book provides a self-contained conceptual and technical introduction to the theory of differential sheaves. This serves both the newcomer and the experienced researcher in undertaking a background-independent, natural and relational approach to "physical geometry". In this manner, this book is situated at the crossroads between the foundations of mathematical analysis with a view toward differential geometry and the foundations of theoretical physics with a view toward quantum mechanics and quantum gravity. The unifying thread is provided (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22. Physical force of geometrical curvature? Einstein, Grünbaum, and the measurability of physical geometry.Martin Carrier - unknown
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23. I—Tim Maudlin: Time, Topology and Physical Geometry.Tim Maudlin - 2010 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 84 (1):63-78.
  24.  21
    Images and Logic of the Light Cone: Tracking Robb’s Postulational Turn in Physical Geometry.Jordi Cat - 2016 - Revista de Humanidades de Valparaíso 8:39-100.
    Previous discussions of Robb’s work on space and time have offered a philosophical focus on causal interpretations of relativity theory or a historical focus on his use of non-Euclidean geometry, or else ignored altogether in discussions of relativity at Cambridge. In this paper I focus on how Robb’s work made contact with those same foundational developments in mathematics and with their applications. This contact with applications of new mathematical logic at Göttingen and Cambridge explains the transition from his electron (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  62
    Husserl’s Conception of Physical Theories and Physical Geometry in the Time of the Prolegomena: A Comparison with Duhem’s and Poincaré’s Views. [REVIEW]Guillermo E. Rosado Haddock - 2012 - Axiomathes 22 (1):171-193.
    This paper discusses Husserl’s views on physical theories in the first volume of his Logical Investigations , and compares them with those of his contemporaries Pierre Duhem and Henri Poincaré. Poincaré’s views serve as a bridge to a discussion of Husserl’s almost unknown views on physical geometry from about 1890 on, which in comparison even with Poincaré’s—not to say Frege’s—or almost any other philosopher of his time, represented a rupture with the philosophical tradition and were much more (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  20
    Imagining physically impossible self-rotations: geometry is more important than gravity.Sarah H. Creem, Maryjane Wraga & Dennis R. Proffitt - 2001 - Cognition 81 (1):41-64.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  27. The Physical Content of Minkowski Geometry.Brent Mundy - 1986 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 37 (1):25-54.
    The standard coordinate-based formulation of the space-time theory of special relativity (Minkowski geometry) is philosophically unsatisfactory for various reasons. We here present an explicit axiomatic formulation of that theory in terms of primitives with a definitive physical interpretation, prove its equivalence to the standard coordinate formulation, and draw various philosophical conclusions concerning the physical content and assumptions of the space-time theory. The prevalent causal interpretation of physical Minkowski geometry deriving from Reichenbach is criticised on the (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  28.  4
    Celebrating Evangelista Torricelli’s Opera Geometrica (1644–2024): Details in History and Historiography of Physics, Geometry and Mathematics. [REVIEW]Raffaele Pisano & Paolo Bussotti - 2023 - In Raffaele Pisano, Jean Dhombres, Patricia Radelet de Grave & Paolo Bussotti (eds.), Homage to Evangelista Torricelli’s Opera Geometrica 1644–2024: Text, Transcription, Commentaries and Selected Essays as New Historical Insights. Springer Verlag. pp. 3-92.
    InCelebratingthisDIUMessayHistoriographywe describeIEMNTorricelli’s lifeLille Universityand worksUdine University in their scientific context, including the ArchimedeanArchimedean heritage in Torricelli’s works. We analyse the changes of Torricelli’s works and explain the novelties of the edition we are offering. Then, we provide a picture of the most significant results obtained by Torricelli (1608–1647), particularly in mechanicsMechanicsand geometryGeometry. Furthermore, we also focus on the Torricelli’s methodology, specifying how he provedProved two of his achievements, given their novelty and mathematical meaning: (a) the volumeVolume of the “solido acutissimo”; (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  44
    Physics and geometry.Jean-Marie Souriau - 1983 - Foundations of Physics 13 (1):133-151.
    Differential geometry, the contemporary heir of the infinitesimal calculus of the 17th century, appears today as the most appropriate language for the description of physical reality. This holds at every level: The concept of “connexion,” for instance, is used in the construction of models of the universe as well as in the description of the interior of the proton. Nothing is apparently more contrary to the wisdom of physicists; all the same, “it works.” The pages that follow show (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Geometry as a Branch of Physics: Background and Context for Einstein's 'Geometry and Experience.'.Michael Friedman - 2002 - In David B. Malament (ed.), Reading Natural Philosophy: Essays in the History and Philosophy of Science and Mathematics. Open Court. pp. 193--229.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  31. Fundamental and Emergent Geometry in Newtonian Physics.David Wallace - 2020 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 71 (1):1-32.
    Using as a starting point recent and apparently incompatible conclusions by Saunders and Knox, I revisit the question of the correct spacetime setting for Newtonian physics. I argue that understood correctly, these two versions of Newtonian physics make the same claims both about the background geometry required to define the theory, and about the inertial structure of the theory. In doing so I illustrate and explore in detail the view—espoused by Knox, and also by Brown —that inertial structure is (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  32.  86
    Topics in Noncommutative Geometry Inspired Physics.Rabin Banerjee, Biswajit Chakraborty, Subir Ghosh, Pradip Mukherjee & Saurav Samanta - 2009 - Foundations of Physics 39 (12):1297-1345.
    In this review article we discuss some of the applications of noncommutative geometry in physics that are of recent interest, such as noncommutative many-body systems, noncommutative extension of Special Theory of Relativity kinematics, twisted gauge theories and noncommutative gravity.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33. Physics as geometry.John Archibald Wheeler - 1980 - Epistemologia 3:59.
  34. Physics, Philosophy, and the fundations of the Geometry.Michael Friedman - 2002 - Diálogos. Revista de Filosofía de la Universidad de Puerto Rico 37 (79):121-142.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  35.  36
    From the Geometry of Pure Spinors with Their Division Algebras to Fermion Physics.Paolo Budinich - 2002 - Foundations of Physics 32 (9):1347-1398.
    The Cartan equations defining simple spinors (renamed “pure” by C. Chevalley) are interpreted as equations of motion in compact momentum spaces, in a constructive approach in which at each step the dimensions of spinor space are doubled while those of momentum space increased by two. The construction is possible only in the frame of the geometry of simple or pure spinors, which imposes contraint equations on spinors with more than four components, and then momentum spaces result compact, isomorphic to (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36. “In Nature as in Geometry”: Du Châtelet and the Post-Newtonian Debate on the Physical Significance of Mathematical Objects.Aaron Wells - 2023 - In Wolfgang Lefèvre (ed.), Between Leibniz, Newton, and Kant: Philosophy and Science in the Eighteenth Century. Springer Verlag. pp. 69-98.
    Du Châtelet holds that mathematical representations play an explanatory role in natural science. Moreover, she writes that things proceed in nature as they do in geometry. How should we square these assertions with Du Châtelet’s idealism about mathematical objects, on which they are ‘fictions’ dependent on acts of abstraction? The question is especially pressing because some of her important interlocutors (Wolff, Maupertuis, and Voltaire) denied that mathematics informs us about the properties of material things. After situating Du Châtelet in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  44
    Weyl's geometry and physics.Nathan Rosen - 1982 - Foundations of Physics 12 (3):213-248.
    It is proposed to remove the difficulty of nonitegrability of length in the Weyl geometry by modifying the law of parallel displacement and using “standard” vectors. The field equations are derived from a variational principle slightly different from that of Dirac and involving a parameter σ. For σ=0 one has the electromagnetic field. For σ<0 there is a vector meson field. This could be the electromagnetic field with finite-mass photons, or it could be a meson field providing the “missing (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  38.  7
    The Geometry of an Art, The History of the Mathematical Theory of Perspective from Alberti to Monge. Sources and Studies in the History of Mathematics and Physical Sciences. [REVIEW]Christa Binder - 2012 - Annals of Science 69 (2):291-294.
  39.  51
    The Astronomy of Eudoxus: Geometry or Physics?Larry Wright - 1973 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 4 (2):165.
  40.  88
    Space and Geometry from the Point of View of Physical Inquiry.Ernst Mach - 1903 - The Monist 14 (1):1-32.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  41. Space and Geometry in the Light of physiological, psychological and physical Inquiry.E. Mach & T. J. Mccormack - 1907 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 64:101-102.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  42.  25
    Anthropological Weight and Physical Irreality of Euclidian Geometry.Víctor Gómez Pin - 2008 - Proceedings of the Xxii World Congress of Philosophy 18:129-139.
    Il est tout à fait possible de soutenir que l’espace de Newton manque d’objectivité physique (ce qui est un corollaire de la théorie einsténienne) et néanmoins prendre tout à fait au sérieux la thèse de l’espace euclidien comme condition de possibilité de l’expérience. Condition de possibilité de l’émergence d’un sujet qui configure son monde en remettant tout point de son environnement à une métrique. Cette métrique ne serait autre que celle qui donne sens à la géométrie que l’on a appris (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  59
    Non-euclidean geometry and physics (1926).Albert Einstein - 2005 - Scientiae Studia 3 (4):677-681.
  44.  78
    Spin Axioms in Different Geometries of Relativistic Continuum Physics.Heiko Herrmann, W. Muschik, G. Rückner & H.-H. Von Borzeszkowski - 2004 - Foundations of Physics 34 (6):1005-1021.
    The 24 components of the relativistic spin tensor consist of 3 + 3 basic spin fields and 9 + 9 constitutive fields. Empirically only three basic spin fields and nine constitutive fields are known. This empirem can be expressed by two spin axioms, one of them denying purely relativistic spin fields, and the other one relating the three additional basic fields and the nine additional constitutive fields to the known (and measurable) ones. This identification by the spin axioms is material-independent (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  10
    The Symbolic Universe. Geometry and Physics 1890–1930.Jean Eisenstaedt - 2002 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 33 (1):145-148.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  30
    Geometry and chronometry in philosophical perspective.Adolf Grünbaum - 1968 - Minneapolis,: University of Minnesota Press.
    Geometry and Chronometry in Philosophical Perspective was first published in 1968. Minnesota Archive Editions uses digital technology to make long-unavailable books once again accessible, and are published unaltered from the original University of Minnesota Press editions. In this volume Professor Grünbaum substantially extends and comments upon his essay "Geometry, Chronometry, and Empiricism," which was first published in Volume III of the Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Commenting on the essay when it first appeared J. J. C. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  47.  30
    The Determinate World: Kant and Helmholtz on the Physical Meaning of Geometry.David Jalal Hyder - 2009 - Berlin and New York: De Gruyter.
    This book offers a new interpretation of Hermann von Helmholtz's work on the epistemology of geometry. A detailed analysis of the philosophical arguments of Helmholtz's Erhaltung der Kraft shows that he took physical theories to be constrained by a regulative ideal. They must render nature "completely comprehensible", which implies that all physical magnitudes must be relations among empirically given phenomena. This conviction eventually forced Helmholtz to explain how geometry itself could be so construed. Hyder shows how (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  48. Relativity and geometry.Roberto Torretti - 1983 - New York: Dover Publications.
    This high-level study discusses Newtonian principles and 19th-century views on electrodynamics and the aether. Additional topics include Einstein's electrodynamics of moving bodies, Minkowski spacetime, gravitational geometry, time and causality, and other subjects. Highlights include a rich exposition of the elements of the special and general theories of relativity.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  49.  50
    Some Mathematical, Epistemological, and Historical Reflections on the Relationship Between Geometry and Reality, Space–Time Theory and the Geometrization of Theoretical Physics, from Riemann to Weyl and Beyond.Luciano Boi - 2019 - Foundations of Science 24 (1):1-38.
    The history and philosophy of science are destined to play a fundamental role in an epoch marked by a major scientific revolution. This ongoing revolution, principally affecting mathematics and physics, entails a profound upheaval of our conception of space, space–time, and, consequently, of natural laws themselves. Briefly, this revolution can be summarized by the following two trends: by the search for a unified theory of the four fundamental forces of nature, which are known, as of now, as gravity, electromagnetism, and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  60
    Thomas precession: Its underlying gyrogroup axioms and their use in hyperbolic geometry and relativistic physics.Abraham A. Ungar - 1997 - Foundations of Physics 27 (6):881-951.
    Gyrogroup theory and its applications is introduced and explored, exposing the fascinating interplay between Thomas precession of special relativity theory and hyperbolic geometry. The abstract Thomas precession, called Thomas gyration, gives rise to grouplike objects called gyrogroups [A, A. Ungar, Am. J. Phys.59, 824 (1991)] the underlying axions of which are presented. The prefix gyro extensively used in terms like gyrogroups, gyroassociative and gyrocommutative laws, gyroautomorphisms, and gyrosemidirect products, stems from their underlying abstract Thomas gyration. Thomas gyration is tailor (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
1 — 50 / 988