Results for 'Kant's Categories'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Notes and Fragments.Immanuel Kant - 2009 - New York: Cambridge University Press. Edited by Paul Guyer.
    This 2005 volume provides an extensive translation of the notes and fragments that survived Kant's death in 1804. These include marginalia, lecture notes, and sketches and drafts for his published works. They are important as an indispensable resource for understanding Kant's intellectual development and published works, casting fresh light on Kant's conception of his own philosophical methods and his relations to his predecessors, as well as on central doctrines of his work such as the theory of space, (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  2. Kant's Schematism of Categories.S. Mishra - 1980 - Indian Philosophical Quarterly 7 (4):489.
  3. Kant’s Categories and Jung’s Types as Perspectival Maps To Stimulate Insight in a Counseling Session.Stephen R. Palmquist - 2005 - International Journal of Philosophical Practice 3 (1):1-27.
    After coining the term “philopsychy” to describe a “soul-loving” approach to philosophical practice, especially when it welcomes a creative synthesis of philosophy and psychology, this article identifies a system of geometrical figures (or “maps”) that can be used to stimulate reflection on various types of perspectival differences. The maps are part of the author’s previously established mapping methodology, known as the Geometry of Logic. As an illustration of how philosophy can influence the development of psychology, Immanuel Kant’s table of twelve (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4.  11
    Kant's transcendental deduction of categories.George S. Morris - 1881 - Journal of Speculative Philosophy 15 (3):253 - 274.
  5. Kant's Categories of Freedom.Susanne Bobzien - 2013 - In Kant - Analysen, Probleme, Kritik (English translation of 1988 article).
    ABSTRACT: A general interpretation and close textual analysis of Kant’s theory of the categories of freedom (or categories of practical reason) in his Critique of Practical Reason. My main concerns in the paper are the following: (1) I show that Kant’s categories of freedom have primarily three functions: as conditions of the possibility for actions (i) to be free, (ii) to be comprehensible as free and (iii) to be morally evaluated. (2) I show that for Kant actions, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  57
    Notes and fragments: logic, metaphysics, moral philosophy, aesthetics.Immanuel Kant - 2005 - New York: Cambridge University Press. Edited by Paul Guyer.
    This volume provides the first ever extensive translation of the notes and fragments that survived Kant's death in 1804. These include marginalia, lecture notes, and sketches and drafts for his published works. They are important as an indispensable resource for understanding Kant's intellectual development and published works, casting new light on Kant's conception of his own philosophical methods and his relations to his predecessors, as well as on central doctrines of his work such as the theory of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  7. Are Kant’s Categories Subjective?William F. Bristow - 2002 - Review of Metaphysics 55 (3):551-580.
    Argues that there is a significant respect in which Kant's categories are to be understood as subjective, namely, in the sense that they are to be understood as the self-legislated rules of our understanding. Argues that the subjectivism of Kant's idealism, by which is meant the relativization of knowledge of objects to our standpoint, is a consequence of the subjectivity of the categories, on this interpretation of their subjectivity. On the reading opposed here, Kant's subjectivism (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8.  41
    Kant's subjective deduction: A reappraisal.Ryan S. Kemp - 2018 - European Journal of Philosophy 26 (3):945-957.
    In the A-preface of the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant kindly warns his readers to pay special attention to the chapter on the “Deduction of the Pure Concepts of the Understanding.” Looking to mitigate the reader's effort, Kant goes on to explain the chapter's methodology, suggesting that the inquiry will have “two sides.” One side deals with the “objective validity” of the pure categories of the understanding; he calls this the “objective deduction.” The other deals with the powers of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9.  54
    Kant’s Categories of Practical Reason as Such.Robert J. Benton - 1980 - Kant Studien 71 (1-4):181-201.
  10.  42
    Kant’s Categories and their Schematism.Lauchlan Chipman - 1972 - Kant Studien 63 (1-4):36-50.
  11. Kant's categories and the capacity to judge: Responses to Henry Allison and Sally Sedgwick.Beatrice Longuenesse - 2000 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 43 (1):91 – 110.
    In response to Henry Allison's and Sally Sedwick's comments on my recent book, Kant and the Capacity to Judge, I explain Kant's description of the understanding as being essentially a "capacity to judge", and his view of the relationship between the categories and the logical functions of judgment. I defend my interpretation of Kant's argument in the Transcendental Deduction of the Categories in the B edition. I conclude that, in my interpretation, Kant's notions of the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  12. Kant's categories and their schematism.Lauchlan Chipman - 1982 - In Ralph Charles Sutherland Walker (ed.), Kant on Pure Reason. Oxford University Press. pp. 36-50.
  13.  22
    Kant’s Categories of Quantity and Quality, Reconsidered: From the Point of View of the History of Logic and Natural Science.Yasuhiko Tomida - 2022 - Philosophia 50 (5):2707-2731.
    According to Kant, the division of the categories “is not the result of a search after pure concepts undertaken at haphazard,” but is derived from the “complete” classification of judgments developed by traditional logic. However, the sorts of judgments that he enumerates in his table of judgments are not all ones that traditional logic has dealt with; consequently, we must say that he chose the sorts of judgments in question with a certain intention. Besides, we know that his choice (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  12
    Kant’s Categories Reconsidered.Robert Greenberg - 1998 - The Paideia Archive: Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 11:58-64.
    Adopting a Quinean criterion of ontological commitment, I consider the question of the ontological commitment of Kant's theory of our a priori knowledge of objects. Its direct concern is the customary view that the ontology of Kant's theory of knowledge in general, whether a priori or empirical, must be thought in terms of the a priori conditions or representations of space, time, and the categories. Accordingly, this view is accompanied by the customary interpretation of ontology as consisting (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Kant's categories of reality and existence.Wolfgang Schwarz - 1987 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 48 (2):343-346.
  16.  41
    Kant's Categories of Freedom as Rules of Moral Salience.Pavlos Kontos - 2011 - Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 65 (2):218-240.
    In diesem Artikel versuche ich deutlich zu machen dass, und aus welchem Grund, Kant den Kategorien der Freiheit eine Doppelfunktion zugeschrieben hat. Es wird sich zeigen, dass die Kategorien der Freiheit nicht nur als die ratio cognoscendi von freien Handlungen innerhalb der Sinnenwelt fungieren, sondern auch geeignet sind, die Begriffe von Gut und Böse als echte moralische Relevanzregeln zu begründen; mit anderen Worten, sie eignen sich als Regeln dafür, wie Umstände und Ereignisse mit moralischer Wichtigkeit aufzuspüren und zu bewerten sind. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Definitions of Kant’s categories.Tyke Nunez - 2014 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 44 (5-6):631-657.
    The consensus view in the literature is that, according to Kant, definitions in philosophy are impossible. While this is true prior to the advent of transcendental philosophy, I argue that with Kant's Copernican Turn definitions of some philosophical concepts, the categories, become possible. Along the way I discuss issues like why Kant introduces the ‘Analytic of Concepts’ as an analysis of the understanding, how this faculty, as the faculty for judging, provides the principle for the complete exhibition of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  18.  87
    Hegel’s Treatment of Transcendental Apperception in Kant.Sally S. Sedgwick - 1992 - The Owl of Minerva 23 (2):151-163.
    From the various discussions of Kant’s theoretical philosophy throughout Hegel’s works, it is not difficult to come away with the impression that Hegel thinks that the Kantian categories are derived from experience, and that the method of a “transcendental” investigation of the forms of subjectivity is nothing other than that of generalization upon observation. As early as the 1802-03 essay, Faith and Knowledge, for example, he characterizes the critical philosophy as the “completion and idealization” of Lockean “empirical psychology.” In (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19. Die Kategorien Der Freiheit Bei Kant (Kant's Categories of Freedom).Susanne Bobzien - 1988 - Kant 1:193-220.
    NOTE: The English translation is listed separately. ABSTRACT: A general interpretation and close textual analysis of Kant’s theory of the categories of freedom (or categories of practical reason) in his Critique of Practical Reason. My main concerns in the paper are the following: (1) I show that Kant’s categories of freedom have primarily three functions: as conditions of the possibility for actions (i) to be free, (ii) to be comprehensible as free and (iii) to be morally evaluated. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  20.  51
    The Rigidity of Kant’s Categories.Harold N. Lee - 1954 - Tulane Studies in Philosophy 3:113-121.
    Kant's transcendental deduction yields twelve and only twelve categories, but behind the argument lie two assumptions: 1) newtonian physics gives unalterable and certain knowledge of phenomena; 2) the subject-predicate logic is the correct tool for the analysis of knowledge. this article examines the place of both assumptions in kant's doctrine and the relevance of each today. both assumptions must be discarded, and with them goes the rigidity of the categories; but the article shows how kant's (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. On the rationale of Kant‘s categorial imperative.Nicholas Rescher - 2000 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 3.
    Over the years, various critics have accused Kant of a rigorism that is the moral equivalent of fiat iustitia ruat caelum. But this involves a greatly mistaken view of the nature and bearing of his categorical imperative. What Kant does in ethics is to employ a two domain approach that separates a rigoristic realm of theory from a more flexible realm of praxis that is oriented towards the real world of our experience. In the moral sphere demands of the former, (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Kant's Metaphysical Deduction of the Categories: Towards a Systematic Reconstruction.Nicholas Stang - forthcoming - In Andrew Stephenson & Anil Gomes (eds.), Oxford Handbook of Kant. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  91
    Making sense of Kant's schematism.Making Sense of Kant'S. Schematism - 1995 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (4).
  24. The Threefold Synthesis as Key to Kant's Categories: Deriving Their Representational Contents From the Synthesis of an Empirical Intuition.Till Hoeppner - forthcoming - Revue Roumaine de Philosophie.
    I argue that Kant’s threefold synthesis of the fundamental act-types of the apprehension, reproduction, and recognition of a manifold of sense-impressions, as presented in the A-Deduction (see A97-110), holds the key to understanding the origin of the categories, or concepts of an object in general, as treated in their Metaphysical Deduction. To that end, I reconstruct Kant’s analysis of a synthesis of empirical intuition (I.), in order to then, on that basis, reconstruct Kant’s concept-formation of the categories (II.). (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Is Kant’s transcendental deduction of the categories fit for purpose?Anil Gomes - 2010 - Kantian Review 15 (2):118-137.
    James Van Cleve has argued that Kant’s Transcendental Deduction of the categories shows, at most, that we must apply the categories to experience. And this falls short of Kant’s aim, which is to show that they must so apply. In this discussion I argue that once we have noted the differences between the first and second editions of the Deduction, this objection is less telling. But Van Cleve’s objection can help illuminate the structure of the B Deduction, and (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  26. Kant’s Metaphysical and Transcendental Deductions of the Categories. Tasks, Steps, and Claims of Identity.Till Hoeppner - 2022 - In Giuseppe Motta, Dennis Schulting & Udo Thiel (eds.), Kant's Transcendental Deduction and the Theory of Apperception: New Interpretations. De Gruyter. pp. 461-492.
    Kant’s Metaphysical Deduction of the Categories justifies their apriority, i.e. that their contents originate in the understanding itself, while the Transcendental Deduction justifies their objectivity, both in that they purport to represent objects of experience and that they do so successfully. The apriority of the categories, as explained in terms of acts of synthesis required for having sensible intuitions of objects, is justified by establishing their generic identity with logical functions of judgment, i.e. acts of judgment required for (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  27. Kant’s Deduction From Apperception: An Essay on the Transcendental Deduction of the Categories.Dennis Schulting - 2019 - Berlin, Germany: De Gruyter.
    In focusing on the systematic deduction of the categories from a principle, Schulting takes up anew the controversial project of the eminent German Kant scholar Klaus Reich, whose monograph “The Completeness of Kant's Table of Judgments” made the case that the logical functions of judgement can all be derived from the objective unity of apperception and can be shown to link up with one another systematically. -/- Common opinion among Kantians today has it that Kant did not mean (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  28. Some Reflections on Kant's Category Theory.R. Singh - 1986 - Indian Philosophical Quarterly 13 (3-4):309.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  39
    Perception and Kant's Categories.Robert Greenberg - 1996 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 13 (3):345 - 361.
  30. Never Mind the Intuitive Intellect: Applying Kant’s Categories to Noumena.Colin Marshall - 2018 - Kantian Review 23 (1):27-40.
    According to strong metaphysical readings of Kant, Kant believes there are noumenal substances and causes. Proponents of these readings have shown that these readings can be reconciled with Kant’s claims about the limitations of human cognition. An important new challenge to such readings, however, has been proposed by Markus Kohl, focusing on Kant’s occasional statements about the divine or intuitive intellect. According to Kohl, how an intuitive intellect represents is a decisive measure for how noumena are for Kant, but an (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  31.  2
    The Rigidity of Kant’s Categories.Harold N. Lee - 1954 - Tulane Studies in Philosophy 3:113-121.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  95
    What’s Wrong with Kant’s Categories, Professor Hegel?Rolf-Peter Horstmann - 1995 - Proceedings of the Eighth International Kant Congress 1:1005-1015.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  33.  15
    Queer Ontogeny and the Circuits of Sexuality; or, On the Queerness of Theory.Kevin S. Amidon - 2023 - Telos: Critical Theory of the Contemporary 2023 (204):101-122.
    ExcerptQueer theory has a problem. This problem does not belong uniquely to queer theory, for it is common to and has consequences for all theory— social, psychological, literary, natural scientific, or otherwise—that seeks categories for the explanation of human phenomena. Queer theory, however, encounters and embodies this problem in uniquely significant ways. Queer theory seems, in fact, to have developed largely out of the friction generated by this problem in other earlier forms of theory—and may thus, ironically, contain the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Kant’s Deduction and Apperception: Explaining the Categories.Dennis Schulting - 2012 - London and Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave-Macmillan.
    Dennis Schulting offers a thoroughgoing, analytic account of the first half of the Transcendental Deduction of the Categories in the B-edition of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason that is different from existing interpretations in at least one important aspect: its central claim is that each of the 12 categories is wholly derivable from the principle of apperception, which goes against the current view that the Deduction is not a proof in a strict philosophical sense and the standard (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  35. Marx’s Social Ontology. [REVIEW]W. S. A. - 1979 - Review of Metaphysics 32 (4):755-756.
    Marx is generally taken to be important in the history of thought as a social philosopher, that is, a philosopher whose main categories are human individuals, their interactions, and the development and modification of institutions, values, and the like. Not so, according to Carol C. Gould, who contends, rather, that Marx is important in the history of thought as a metaphysician, that is, a philosopher whose main categories are particulars, classes, the relation of individuals to class concepts, change, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  33
    On Kant’s Derivation of the Categories.Santiago de Jesus Sanchez Borboa - 2018 - Kant Studien 109 (4):511-536.
    In this paper, I put forth a novel interpretation of how the third categories under each heading in the table of categories are derived. Drawing on a passage from the first Critique and a letter to Schultz, I argue that in order to derive these categories, a special act of the understanding is required. I propose that we interpret this special act as consisting of an application of the third logical function under the corresponding heading that unites (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  28
    Experience and Judgment. [REVIEW]S. R. - 1973 - Review of Metaphysics 27 (2):391-392.
    This book is a good example of Husserl’s phenomenology at work. It contains three parts, each filled with interesting analyses. Part One examines prepredicative experience and describes how certain aspects come to prominence against others, how similarities arise, how a prepredicative sense of attribution occurs. It discusses the difference between the ego’s being affected and his act of attention, explores prepredicative modalities, and the elementary state of relations in experience. In Part Two Husserl moves to explicit predication as his theme, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  8
    Kant's First Drafts of the Deduction of the Categories.Wolfgang Carl - 1989 - In Eckart Förster (ed.), Kant’s Transcendental Deductions: The Three ‘Critiques’ and the ‘Opus Postumum’. Stanford University Press. pp. 1-20.
  39.  7
    Kant's deduction of the categories, with special relation to the views of dr. Stirling.Edward Caird - 1880 - Journal of Speculative Philosophy 14 (1):110 - 134.
  40. Categories versus Schemata: Kant’s Two-Aspect Theory of Pure Concepts and his Critique of Wolffian Metaphysics.Karin de Boer - 2016 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 54 (3):441-468.
    in a late note, dated 1797, Kant refers to the schematism of the pure understanding as one of the most difficult as well as one of the most important issues treated in the Critique of Pure Reason.1 His treatment of this theme is indeed notorious for its obscurity.2 As I see it, part of the problem is caused by the fact that Kant frames his discussion in terms that he could expect his readers to be familiar with, while he gradually (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  41. Kant's Schematism of the categories: An interpretation and defence.Nicholas F. Stang - 2022 - European Journal of Philosophy 31 (1):30-64.
    The aim of the Schematism chapter of the Critique of Pure Reason is to solve the problem posed by the “inhomogeneity” of intuitions and categories: the sensible properties of objects represented in intuition are of a different kind than the properties represented by categories. Kant's solution is to introduce what he calls “transcendental schemata,” which mediate the subsumption of objects under categories. I reconstruct Kant's solution in terms of two substantive premises, which I call Subsumption (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  17
    Kant's Transcendental Deduction of the Categories: Unity, Representation, and Apperception.Lawrence J. Kaye - 2015 - Lanham: Lexington Books.
    This book is a comprehensive exposition of the Transcendental Deduction of the Categories in both editions of Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  43.  75
    Kant's reception in France: Theories of the categories in academic philosophy, psychology, and social science.Warren Schmaus - 2003 - Perspectives on Science 11 (1):3-34.
    : It has been said that Kant's critical philosophy made it impossible to pursue either the Cartesian rationalist or the Lockean empiricist program of providing a foundation for the sciences (e.g., Guyer 1992). This claim does not hold true for much of nineteenth century French philosophy, especially the eclectic spiritualist tradition that begins with Victor Cousin (1792-1867) and Pierre Maine de Biran (1766-1824) and continues through Paul Janet (1823-99). This tradition assimilated Kant's transcendental apperception of the unity of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  44.  68
    Kant's Conception of the Categories.T. K. Seung - 1989 - Review of Metaphysics 43 (1):107 - 132.
    THE PURE INTUITIONS OF SPACE AND TIME and the pure concepts of understanding are the two basic elements in Kant's critical philosophy. Whereas his account of pure intuitions is relatively straightforward, his theory of categories is quite complicated. When he presents space and time as two forms of intuition, he never sees the need to prove that there are no other forms of intuition than these two. But when he presents his table of categories, he tries to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45.  92
    Kant's Transcendental Idealism and the Categories.Eric Watkins - 2002 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 19 (2):191 - 215.
  46.  27
    Evil in Modern Thought: An Alternative History of Philosophy (review).Paul S. Miklowitz - 2004 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 42 (3):347-348.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Evil in Modern Thought: An Alternative History of PhilosophyPaul S. MiklowitzSusan Neiman. Evil in Modern Thought: An Alternative History of Philosophy. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2002. Pp. xii + 358. Cloth, $29.95.Contemporary philosophy in America tends to regard epistemological questions as the most fundamental of the discipline, but Susan Neiman's Evil in Modern Thought sets itself against this assumption in an attempt to sketch "an alternative history of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Kant's schematism of the categories and the problem of pattern recognition.Peter Krausser - 1976 - Synthese 33 (2-4):175 - 192.
  48. Kant’s Perspectival Solution to the Mind-Body Problem—Or, Why Eliminative Materialists Must Be Kantians.Stephen R. Palmquist - 2016 - Culture and Dialogue 4 (1):194-213.
    Kant’s pre-1770 philosophy responded to the mind-body problem by applying a theory of “physical influx”. His encounter with Swedenborg’s mysticism, however, left him disillusioned with any dualist solution to Descartes’ problem. One of the major goals of the Critical philosophy was to provide a completely new solution to the mind-body problem. Kant’s new solution is “perspectival” in the sense that all Critical theories are perspectival: it acknowledges a deep truth in both of the controversy’s extremes (i.e., what we might nowadays (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Pure versus Empirical Forms of Thought: Schelling’s Critique of Kant’s Categories and the Beginnings of Naturphilosophie.Dalia Nassar - 2014 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 52 (1):113-134.
    The Origins of Schelling’s Naturphilosophie and its relation to his transcendental philosophy have for a long time intrigued historians of philosophy.1 When did Schelling’s interest in the philosophy of nature commence,2 and what inspired this apparent transition in his thought?3 How did his Naturphilosophie figure into his later departure from Fichte, and in what ways did his early commitments influence this departure?4 These have been the overarching questions of the debate, and they have been answered from varying angles. However, by (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  14
    Space, Geometry, and Kant's Transcendental Deduction of the Categories.Thomas C. Vinci - 2014 - New York, US: Oup Usa.
    Thomas C. Vinci argues that Kant's Deductions demonstrate Kant's idealist doctrines and have the structure of an inference to the best explanation for correlated domains. With the Deduction of the Categories the correlated domains are intellectual conditions and non-geometrical laws of the empirical world. With the Deduction of the Concepts of Space, the correlated domains are the geometry of pure objects of intuition and the geometry of empirical objects.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000