Results for 'Frederick Cornwallis Conybeare'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Three Early Doctrinal Modifications of the Text of the Gospels.Frederick C. Conybeare - 1902 - Hibbert Journal 1:101.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. The Bounds of Cognition.Frederick Adams & Kenneth Aizawa - 2008 - Malden, MA, USA: Wiley-Blackwell. Edited by Kenneth Aizawa.
  3.  75
    Being and Nothingness.Frederick A. Olafson, Jean-Paul Sartre & Hazel E. Barnes - 1958 - Philosophical Review 67 (2):276.
  4.  57
    Pathmarks.Frederick A. Olafson - 2000 - Philosophical Review 109 (2):299-302.
  5. Defending the bounds of cognition.Frederick R. Adams & Kenneth Aizawa - 2010 - In Richard Menary (ed.), The Extended Mind. Cambridge, MA, USA: MIT Press.
    That about sums up what is wrong with Clark's view.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  6. Free speech: a philosophical enquiry.Frederick F. Schauer - 1982 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
  7. Heidegger and the Ground of Ethics: A Study of Mitsein.Frederick A. Olafson - 1998 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Written by one of the pre-eminent interpreters of Heidegger, this book is an important statement about the basis of human sociability that is a major contribution to the continuing debates about Heidegger in particular, and ethics in general. Existential philosophy is often thought to promote moral nihilism in which everything is permitted. This book demonstrates that, in the case of Martin Heidegger, any such accusation is unjust. On the contrary, Heidegger thought seriously about the implications of human co-existence, and this (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  8. The informational turn in philosophy.Frederick Adams - 2003 - Minds and Machines 13 (4):471-501.
    This paper traces the application of information theory to philosophical problems of mind and meaning from the earliest days of the creation of the mathematical theory of communication. The use of information theory to understand purposive behavior, learning, pattern recognition, and more marked the beginning of the naturalization of mind and meaning. From the inception of information theory, Wiener, Turing, and others began trying to show how to make a mind from informational and computational materials. Over the last 50 years, (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  9. The Intention/Volition Debate.Frederick Adams & Alfred R. Mele - 1992 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 22 (3):323-337.
    People intend to do things, try to do things, and do things. Do they also will to do things? More precisely, if people will to do things and their willing bears upon what they do, is willing, or volition, something distinct from intending and trying? This question is central to the intention/volition debate, a debate about the ingredients of the best theory of the nature and explanation of human action. A variety of competing conceptions of volition, intention, and trying have (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  10. Fodorian Semantics. Adams, Frederick & Kenneth Aizawa - 1994 - In Stephen P. Stich & Ted A. Warfield (eds.), Mental Representation: A Reader. Cambridge, USA: Blackwell.
  11. Heidegger la Wittgenstein or 'coping' with professor Dreyfus.Frederick A. Olafson - 1994 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 37 (1):45 – 64.
  12. The Role of Intention in Intentional Action.Frederick Adams & Alfred Mele - 1989 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 19 (4):511 - 531.
    A great deal of attention has been paid in recent years to the function- al roles of intentions in intentional action. In this paper we sketch and defend a position on this issue while attacking a provocative alternative. Our position has its roots in a cybernetic theory of purposive behavior and is only part of the larger task of understanding all goal-directed behavior. Indeed, a unified model of goal-directed behavior, with appropriate modifications for different types of systems, is a long-range (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  13. Testimonial Justification and Transindividual Reasons.Frederick F. Schmitt - 2006 - In Jennifer Lackey & Ernest Sosa (eds.), The epistemology of testimony. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 193--224.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  14. Heidegger and the Philosophy of Mind.Frederick Olafson - 1990 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 52 (1):165-166.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  15.  78
    A Goal-State Theory of Function Attributions.Frederick R. Adams - 1979 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 9 (3):493 - 518.
    The analysis of function-ascribing statements, such as “the function of x is y”, is proving to be a difficult matter. It is difficult because we are only beginning to see the complexity which is involved in ascribing functions. The process of discovery has been slow and tedious, with each newly constructed analysis of the meaning of functional ascriptions yielding insights into the structure of functional analysis and functional explanation. However, as each analysis is, in turn, dismantled, we seem to see (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  16.  38
    The social construction of the concept of law: A reply to Julie Dickson.Frederick Schauer - 2005 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 25 (3):493-501.
  17. Goethe and the Sciences: A Reappraisal.Frederick Amrine, Francis J. Zucker & Harvey Wheeler - 1987 - Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 97:1-442.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  18. Positivism as Pariah.Frederick Schauer - 1996 - In Robert P. George (ed.), The autonomy of law: essays on legal positivism. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 31--55.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  19. The phenomenology of speech and harm.Frederick Schauer - 1993 - Ethics 103 (4):635-653.
  20.  7
    Principles and Persons: An Ethical Interpretation of Existentialism.Frederick Olafson - 2019 - Johns Hopkins University Press.
    He demonstrates that a broad parallelism exists between developments in ethical theory among Continental philosophers of the phenomenological persuasion and the more analytically inclined philosophers of the English-speaking world.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  21. Joint action: From individualism to supraindividualism.Frederick Schmitt - 2003 - In Frederick F. Schmitt (ed.), Socializing Metaphysics : the Nature of Social Reality. Rowman & Littlefield, 65-91. pp. 129--166.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  22. Empathy, neural imaging and the theory versus simulation debate.Frederick Adams - 2001 - Mind and Language 16 (4):368-392.
    This paper considers the debate over how we attribute beliefs, desires, and other mental states to our fellows. Do we employ a theory of mind? Or do we use simulational brain mechanisms, but employ no theory? One point of dispute between these theories focuses upon our ability to have empathic knowledge of the mind of another. I consider whether an argument posed by Ravenscroft settles the debate in favor of Simulation Theory. I suggest that the consideration of empathy does not (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  23.  10
    Herder on Nationality, Humanity, and History.Frederick M. Barnard - 2003 - McGill-Queen's Press - MQUP.
    The core of J.G. Herder's philosophy of nationalism lies in the conviction that human creativity must be embedded in the particular culture of a communal language. While he acknowledged that this cultural particular must be integrated into a more universal humanity, he insisted that each culture should preserve its incommensurable distinctiveness. He also called for a new method of enquiry regarding history, one that demands empathetic sensitivity toward the uniquely individual while realizing that there are few gains without losses. F.M. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  24.  29
    The dialectic of action: a philosophical interpretation of history and the humanities.Frederick A. Olafson - 1979 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  25. Causal contents.Frederick R. Adams - 1991 - In Brian P. McLaughlin (ed.), Dretske and his critics. Cambridge, Mass., USA: Blackwell.
  26. Principles and Persons: An Ethical Interpretation of Existentialism.Frederick A. Olafson - 1967 - Philosophy 44 (167):79-80.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  27. The Dialectic of Action: A Philosophical Interpretation of History and the Humanities.Frederick A. Olafson - 1979 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 87 (4):567-568.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  28.  32
    Reliability, objectivity and the background of justification.Frederick F. Schmitt - 1984 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 62 (1):1 – 15.
  29.  57
    Feedback about feedback: Reply to Ehring.Frederick Adams - 1986 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 24 (1):123-131.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  30.  40
    Individualism, subjectivity, and presence: A response to Taylor Carman.Frederick A. Olafson - 1994 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 37 (3):331 – 337.
  31.  51
    Consensus, respect, and weighted averaging.Frederick F. Schmitt - 1985 - Synthese 62 (1):25 - 46.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  32.  69
    Knowledge, justification, and reliability.Frederick F. Schmitt - 1983 - Synthese 55 (2):209 - 229.
    Recent epistemology divides theories of knowledge according to their diagnoses of cases of failed knowledge, Gettier cases. Two rival camps have emerged: naturalism and justificationism. Naturalism attributes the failure of knowledge in these cases to the cognizer's failure to stand in a strong natural position vis-à-vis the proposition believed. Justificationism traces the failure to the cognizer's failure to be strongly justified in his belief. My aim is to reconcile these camps by offering a version of naturalism, a reliability theory of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  33.  8
    Feedback About Feedback: Reply to Ehring.Frederick Adams - 2010 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 24 (1):123-131.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  34.  7
    Herder's Social and Political Thought: From Enlightenment to Nationalism.Frederick M. Barnard - 1965 - Clarendon Press.
  35.  15
    Naturalism and the Human Condition: Against Scientism.Frederick A. Olafson - 2001 - New York: Routledge.
    _Naturalism and the Human Condition_ is a compelling account of why naturalism, or the 'scientific world-view' cannot provide a full account of who and what we are as human beings. Drawing on sources including Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty, Husserl and Sartre, Olafson exposes the limits of naturalism and stresses the importance of serious philosophical investigation of human nature.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  36.  84
    Qualitative and Quantitative Features of Music Reported to Support Peak Mystical Experiences during Psychedelic Therapy Sessions.Frederick S. Barrett, Hollis Robbins, David Smooke, Jenine L. Brown & Roland R. Griffiths - 2017 - Frontiers in Psychology 8.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37.  82
    The Function of Epistemic Justification.Frederick Adams - 1986 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 16 (3):465 - 492.
    Assume that epistemic justification has a cognitive function and that a belief's being justified is not just its being caused by the appropriate information (for this property of the belief may be cognitively impenetrable). What is the function of epistemic justification? it cannot be to actualize knowledge-The belief's being caused by appropriate information alone does that! so what is its function? I suggest it is to cause us to believe and/or take action.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  38.  6
    The Mark of the Cognitive, Extended Cognition Style.Frederick Adams & Kenneth Aizawa - 2008 - In Frederick Adams & Kenneth Aizawa (eds.), The Bounds of Cognition. Malden, MA, USA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 76–87.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Cognition as Information Processing, as Computation, and as Abiding in the Meaningful Operationalism Is This Merely a Terminological Issue? Conclusion.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  39.  93
    What is wrong with epistemic circularity?Frederick F. Schmitt - 2004 - Philosophical Issues 14 (1):379–402.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  40. Mental representation.Frederick R. Adams - 2002 - In Stephen P. Stich & Ted A. Warfield (eds.), Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind. Blackwell.
  41.  9
    Temporal and Reciprocal Relations Between Worry and Rumination Among Subgroups of Metacognitive Beliefs.Frederick Anyan, Roxanna Morote & Odin Hjemdal - 2020 - Frontiers in Psychology 11.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  21
    8. Epistemic Dimensions of Self-Deception.Frederick F. Schmitt - 1988 - In Brian P. McLaughlin & Amélie Oksenberg Rorty (eds.), Perspectives on Self-Deception. University of California Press. pp. 183-204.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  43.  50
    Justification as reliable indication or reliable process?Frederick F. Schmitt - 1981 - Philosophical Studies 40 (3):409 - 417.
  44. Positivism through thick and thin.Frederick Schauer - 1998 - In Brian Bix (ed.), Analyzing law: new essays in legal theory. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 65--78.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  45.  31
    Testimony and evidence: A rebuttal.Frederick Schmitt - 1988 - Social Epistemology 2 (4):323 – 326.
  46. Individual identity in Descartes and Spinoza.Frederick Ablondi - 1994 - Studia Spinozana: An International and Interdisciplinary Series 10:69-92.
  47. Trying.Frederick Adams - 1995 - Journal of Philosophical Research 20:549-561.
    Sue knows that, unaided, she cannot lift the 1,000 pound weight, but surely she can try. Can she not? For even if she believes it is impossible to succeed in lifting the weight, trying to lift the weight need not involve success. So surely, it would seem that nothing could be easier than for Sue to give lifting the weight a try. In this paper, I agrue that, appearances aside, it is not possible for someone to try to do what (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  48. Swampman's revenge: Squabbles among the representationalists.Frederick R. Adams & Laura A. Dietrich - 2004 - Philosophical Psychology 17 (3):323-40.
    There are both externalist and internalist theories of the phenomenal content of conscious experiences. Externalists like Dretske and Tye treat the phenomenal content of conscious states as representations of external properties. Internalists think that phenomenal conscious states are reducible to electrochemical states of the brain in the style of the type-type identity theory. In this paper, we side with the representationalists and visit a dispute between them over the test case of Swampman. Does Swampman have conscious phenomenal states or not? (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  49.  41
    Introduction.Frederick Adams - 2007 - Journal of Philosophical Research 32 (9999):1-5.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  50.  73
    Fodor's modal argument.Frederick Adams - 1993 - Philosophical Psychology 6 (1):41-56.
    What we do, intentionally, depends upon the intentional contents of our thoughts. For about ten years Fodor has argued that intentional behavior causally depends upon the narrow intentional content of thoughts (not broad). His main reason is a causal powers argument—brains of individuals A and B may differ in broad content, but, if A and B are neurophysically identical, their thoughts cannot differ in causal power, despite differences in broad content. Recently Fodor (Fodor, 1991) presents a new 'modal' version of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000