Results for 'Epistemology of Geometry'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  5
    Epistemology of Geometry: Structure-Constructivism (Ⅰ) - Beyond the Argument Between the Logical and the Phenomenological Interpretation on the Role of Intuition in Kant’s Theory of Geometry -. 문장수 - 2022 - Journal of the New Korean Philosophical Association 108:23-52.
    본 연구는 기하학에 대한 구조-구성주의 인식론을 정당화하는 것이다. 즉 구조주의와 구성주의를 융합하는 필자의 고유한 인식론으로 기하학적 인식의 본성을 해명하는 것이다. 그러나 현재의 연구는 이러한 큰 주제에 접근하기 위한 예비적 연구로서 칸트의 기하학적 직관 개념에 대한 역사-비판적 분석을 제공하는 데 한정된다. 잘 알려져 있는 것처럼, 칸트는 수학적 인식, 특히 기하학적 인식을 위해서 직관이 핵심적으로 중요하다고 주장했다. 그런데 칸트가 말하는 기하학적 인식을 위한 직관의 역할이 무엇인지는 여전히 논쟁적이다. 이점과 관련해서 역사적으로 대립적인 두 가지 해석이 있다. 하나는 베스(E. Beth), 힌티카(J. Hintikka), 프리드만(M. Fridman) (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  23
    The Epistemology of Geometry and Its Pedagogical Implication.Eunsuk Eun - 2022 - Journal of the Society of Philosophical Studies 65:191-245.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. The epistemology of geometry.Clark Glymour - 1977 - Noûs 11 (3):227-251.
    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of J STOR’s Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. J STOR’s Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non—commercial use.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  4.  45
    Epistemology of Geometry.Jeremy Gray - forthcoming - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  5. The Epistemology of Geometry I: the Problem of Exactness.Anne Newstead & Franklin James - 2010 - Proceedings of the Australasian Society for Cognitive Science 2009.
    We show how an epistemology informed by cognitive science promises to shed light on an ancient problem in the philosophy of mathematics: the problem of exactness. The problem of exactness arises because geometrical knowledge is thought to concern perfect geometrical forms, whereas the embodiment of such forms in the natural world may be imperfect. There thus arises an apparent mismatch between mathematical concepts and physical reality. We propose that the problem can be solved by emphasizing the ways in which (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  49
    Weyl, Reichenbach and the epistemology of geometry.Ryckman Thomas - 1994 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 25 (6):831-870.
  7.  44
    Glymour on deoccamization and the epistemology of geometry.Jane Duran - 1989 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 40 (1):127-134.
    Three lines of argument are employed to show that Glymour's position on the epistemology of geometry is probably not as strong theoretically as the position of the underdeterminists whom he attempts to refute. The first argument centers on Glymour's implicit use of a realist position on intertheoretic reference, similar to that employed by Boyd and other realists. Citations are made to various portions of Glymour's work, and the relationship between the imputed theory of reference and Glymour's position spelled (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  42
    From Gauss to Riemann Through Jacobi: Interactions Between the Epistemologies of Geometry and Mechanics?Maria de Paz & José Ferreirós - 2020 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 51 (1):147-172.
    The aim of this paper is to argue that there existed relevant interactions between mechanics and geometry during the first half of the nineteenth century, following a path that goes from Gauss to Riemann through Jacobi. By presenting a rich historical context we hope to throw light on the philosophical change of epistemological categories applied by these authors to the fundamental principles of both disciplines. We intend to show that presentations of the changing status of the principles of mechanics (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  63
    Frege’s philosophy of geometry.Matthias Schirn - 2019 - Synthese 196 (3):929-971.
    In this paper, I critically discuss Frege’s philosophy of geometry with special emphasis on his position in The Foundations of Arithmetic of 1884. In Sect. 2, I argue that that what Frege calls faculty of intuition in his dissertation is probably meant to refer to a capacity of visualizing geometrical configurations structurally in a way which is essentially the same for most Western educated human beings. I further suggest that according to his Habilitationsschrift it is through spatial intuition that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  10.  56
    A new semantics for the epistemology of geometry I: Modeling spacetime structure. [REVIEW]Robert Alan Coleman & Herbert Korté - 1995 - Erkenntnis 42 (2):141 - 160.
  11.  58
    A new semantics for the epistemology of geometry II: Epistemological completeness of newton—galilei and einstein—maxwell theory. [REVIEW]Robert Alan Coleman & Herbert Korté - 1995 - Erkenntnis 42 (2):161 - 189.
  12. The epistemological foundations of geometry in 19 th century.Ladislav Kvasz - 1998 - Philosophia Scientiae 3 (2):183-202.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. History of geometry and the development of the form of its language.Ladislav Kvasz - 1998 - Synthese 116 (2):141–186.
    The aim of this paper is to introduce Wittgenstein’s concept of the form of a language into geometry and to show how it can be used to achieve a better understanding of the development of geometry, from Desargues, Lobachevsky and Beltrami to Cayley, Klein and Poincaré. Thus this essay can be seen as an attempt to rehabilitate the Picture Theory of Meaning, from the Tractatus. Its basic idea is to use Picture Theory to understand the pictures of (...). I will try to show, that the historical evolution of geometry can be interpreted as the development of the form of its language. This confrontation of the Picture Theory with history of geometry sheds new light also on the ideas of Wittgenstein. (shrink)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  14.  11
    Leibniz on the Parallel Postulate and the Foundations of Geometry: The Unpublished Manuscripts.Vincenzo De Risi - 2016 - New York/London: Birkhäuser.
    This book offers a general introduction to the geometrical studies of Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz and his mathematical epistemology. In particular, it focuses on his theory of parallel lines and his attempts to prove the famous Parallel Postulate. Furthermore it explains the role that Leibniz’s work played in the development of non-Euclidean geometry. The first part is an overview of his epistemology of geometry and a few of his geometrical findings, which puts them in the context of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  15.  20
    Mathematizing Space: The Objects of Geometry from Antiquity to the Early Modern Age.Vincenzo De Risi (ed.) - 2015 - Birkhäuser.
    This book brings together papers of the conference on 'Space, Geometry and the Imagination from Antiquity to the Modern Age' held in Berlin, Germany, 27-29 August 2012. Focusing on the interconnections between the history of geometry and the philosophy of space in the pre-Modern and Early Modern Age, the essays in this volume are particularly directed toward elucidating the complex epistemological revolution that transformed the classical geometry of figures into the modern geometry of space. Contributors: Graciela (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  16.  96
    From inexactness to certainty: The change in Hume's conception of geometry.Vadim Batitsky - 1998 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 29 (1):1-20.
    Although Hume's analysis of geometry continues to serve as a reference point for many contemporary discussions in the philosophy of science, the fact that the first Enquiry presents a radical revision of Hume's conception of geometry in the Treatise has never been explained. The present essay closely examines Hume's early and late discussions of geometry and proposes a reconstruction of the reasons behind the change in his views on the subject. Hume's early conception of geometry as (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  17.  30
    The Determinate World: Kant and Helmholtz on the Physical Meaning of Geometry.David Jalal Hyder - 2009 - Berlin and New York: De Gruyter.
    This book offers a new interpretation of Hermann von Helmholtz's work on the epistemology of geometry. A detailed analysis of the philosophical arguments of Helmholtz's Erhaltung der Kraft shows that he took physical theories to be constrained by a regulative ideal. They must render nature "completely comprehensible", which implies that all physical magnitudes must be relations among empirically given phenomena. This conviction eventually forced Helmholtz to explain how geometry itself could be so construed. Hyder shows how Helmholtz (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  18.  5
    Thinking Geometry: A Matter of Philosophy. The Case of Helmholtz and Poincaré.María de Paz - 2011 - In Hassan Tahiri (ed.), Poincaré's Philosophy of Mathematics: Intuition Experience Creativity. pp. 107-121.
    The controversy between Euclidean and non-Euclidean geometry arose new philosophical and scientific insights which were relevant to the later development of natural science. Here we want to consider Poincaré and Helmholtz’s positions as two of the most important and original ones who contributed to the subsequent development of the epistemology of natural sciences. Based in these conceptions, we will show that the role of philosophy is still important for some aspects of science.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  88
    Epistemology of visual thinking in elementary real analysis.Marcus Giaquinto - 1994 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45 (3):789-813.
    Can visual thinking be a means of discovery in elementary analysis, as well as a means of illustration and a stimulus to discovery? The answer to the corresponding question for geometry and arithmetic seems to be ‘yes’ (Giaquinto [1992], [1993]), and so a positive answer might be expected for elementary analysis too. But I argue here that only in a severely restricted range of cases can visual thinking be a means of discovery in analysis. Examination of persuasive visual routes (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  20.  43
    Geometry and Measurement in Otto Hölder's Epistemology.Paola Cantu - 2012 - Philosophia Scientiae 17 (17-1):131-164.
    L’article a pour but d’analyser la conception de la géométrie et de la mesure présentée dans Intuition et Raisonnement [Hölder 1900], « Les axiomes de la grandeur et la théorie de la mensuration » [Hölder 1901] et La Méthode mathématique [Hölder 1924]. L’article examine les relations entre a) la démarcation introduite par Hölder entre géométrie et arithmétique à partir de la notion de ‘concept donné’, b) sa position philosophique par rapport à l’apriorisme kantien et à l’empirisme et c) le choix (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  84
    Descartes, Pascal, and the epistemology of mathematics: The case of the cycloid.Douglas Michael Jesseph - 2007 - Perspectives on Science 15 (4):410-433.
    This paper deals with the very different attitudes that Descartes and Pascal had to the cycloid—the curve traced by the motion of a point on the periphery of a circle as the circle rolls across a right line. Descartes insisted that such a curve was merely mechanical and not truly geometric, and so was of no real mathematical interest. He nevertheless responded to enquiries from Mersenne, who posed the problems of determining its area and constructing its tangent. Pascal, in contrast, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  63
    Logic of imagination. Echoes of Cartesian epistemology in contemporary philosophy of mathematics and beyond.David Rabouin - 2018 - Synthese 195 (11):4751-4783.
    Descartes’ Rules for the direction of the mind presents us with a theory of knowledge in which imagination, considered as an “aid” for the intellect, plays a key role. This function of schematization, which strongly resembles key features of Proclus’ philosophy of mathematics, is in full accordance with Descartes’ mathematical practice in later works such as La Géométrie from 1637. Although due to its reliance on a form of geometric intuition, it may sound obsolete, I would like to show that (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  23.  8
    An outline of the natural-historical epistemology of Merab Mamardashvili and the possibility of its phenomenological interpretation.Tatiana V. Litvin - 2019 - Studies in East European Thought 71 (3):293-303.
    The paper reconstructs the key epistemological ideas of Merab Mamardashvili which form the bridge between his philosophy and phenomenology. He advances four key concepts in his sketch of a natural historical epistemology: the geometry of causal experience, the belonging to a certain time, the chronotype of a subject, and the ‘elaboration’ of the mind by consciousness. The concept of “fruitful tautology” leads Mamardashvili to a new aesthetics of thinking. The semiotics, rightfully included in Russian social sciences, assumes that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Review: Hyder, The Determinate World: Kant and Helmholtz on the Physical Meaning of Geometry[REVIEW]Lydia Patton - 2010 - Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2010 (7).
    Hyder constructs two historical narratives. First, he gives an account of Helmholtz's relation to Kant, from the famous Raumproblem, which preoccupied philosophers, geometers, and scientists in the mid-19th century, to Helmholtz's arguments in his four papers on geometry from 1868 to 1878 that geometry is, in some sense, an empirical science (chapters 5 and 6). The second theme is the argument for the necessity of central forces to a determinate scientific description of physical reality, an abiding concern of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Phenomenological, epistemological and hermeneutic study of non-commutative geometry.Masaki Harada - 2012 - Revue Philosophique De Louvain 110 (2):293-324.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  54
    Some Mathematical, Epistemological, and Historical Reflections on the Relationship Between Geometry and Reality, Space–Time Theory and the Geometrization of Theoretical Physics, from Riemann to Weyl and Beyond.Luciano Boi - 2019 - Foundations of Science 24 (1):1-38.
    The history and philosophy of science are destined to play a fundamental role in an epoch marked by a major scientific revolution. This ongoing revolution, principally affecting mathematics and physics, entails a profound upheaval of our conception of space, space–time, and, consequently, of natural laws themselves. Briefly, this revolution can be summarized by the following two trends: by the search for a unified theory of the four fundamental forces of nature, which are known, as of now, as gravity, electromagnetism, and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  24
    Conventionalism In Reid’s ‘geometry Of Visibles’.Edward Slowik - 2003 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 34 (3):467-489.
    The subject of this investigation is the role of conventions in the formulation of Thomas Reid’s theory of the geometry of vision, which he calls the ‘geometry of visibles’. In particular, we will examine the work of N. Daniels and R. Angell who have alleged that, respectively, Reid’s ‘geometry of visibles’ and the geometry of the visual field are non-Euclidean. As will be demonstrated, however, the construction of any geometry of vision is subject to a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  28. On the origin and significance of the axioms of geometry.H. Helmholtz - 1977 - In Robert Cohen & Elkana Yehuda (eds.), Hermann Von Helmholtz: Epistemological Writings. Reidel.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  29.  36
    Jesse Norman. After Euclid: Visual Reasoning and the Epistemology of Diagrams. Stanford: CSLI Publications, 2006. ISBN 1-57586-509-2 ; 1-57586-510-6 . Pp. vii +176. [REVIEW]Jesse Norman - 2007 - Philosophia Mathematica 15 (1):116-121.
    This monograph treats the important topic of the epistemology of diagrams in Euclidean geometry. Norman argues that diagrams play a genuine justificatory role in traditional Euclidean arguments, and he aims to account for these roles from a modified Kantian perspective. Norman considers himself a semi-Kantian in the following broad sense: he believes that Kant was right that ostensive constructions are necessary in order to follow traditional Euclidean proofs, but he wants to avoid appealing to Kantian a priori intuition (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  39
    The Geometry of Knowledge: Lewis, Becker, Carnap and the Formalization of Philosophy in the 1920s.Alan Richardson - 2003 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 34 (1):165-182.
    On an ordinary view of the relation of philosophy of science to science, science serves only as a topic for philosophical reflection, reflection that proceeds by its own methods and according to its own standards. This ordinary view suggests a way of writing a global history of philosophy of science that finds substantially the same philosophical projects being pursued across widely divergent scientific eras. While not denying that this view is of some use regarding certain themes of and particular time (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  31. On the origin and significance of the axioms of geometry.Hermann von Helmholtz - 1977 - In Robert Cohen & Elkana Yehuda (eds.), Hermann Von Helmholtz: Epistemological Writings. Reidel. pp. 1-26.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  9
    On the idea of point-free theories of space based on the example of Tarski’s Geometry of Solids.Grzegorz Sitek - 2022 - Philosophical Discourses 4:157-186.
    The paper presents the main idea of point-free theories of space based on Tarski's system of point-free geometry. First, the general idea of the so-called point-free ontology was discussed, as well as the epistemological and methodological reasons for its adoption. Next, Whitehead's method of extensive abstraction, which is the methodological basis for the construction of point-free theories of space, is presented, and the fundamental concepts of mereology are discussed. The main part of the paper is a discussion of Tarski’s (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  59
    Axiomatizations of hyperbolic geometry: A comparison based on language and quantifier type complexity.Victor Pambuccian - 2002 - Synthese 133 (3):331 - 341.
    Hyperbolic geometry can be axiomatized using the notions of order andcongruence (as in Euclidean geometry) or using the notion of incidencealone (as in projective geometry). Although the incidence-based axiomatizationmay be considered simpler because it uses the single binary point-linerelation of incidence as a primitive notion, we show that it issyntactically more complex. The incidence-based formulation requires some axioms of the quantifier-type forallexistsforall, while the axiom system based on congruence and order can beformulated using only forallexists-axioms.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  34.  25
    The Geometry of Otto Selz’s Natural Space.Klaus Robering - 2019 - Erkenntnis 86 (2):325-354.
    Following ideas elaborated by Hering in his celebrated analysis of color, the psychologist and gestalt theorist Otto Selz developed in the 1930s a theory of “natural space”, i.e., space as it is conceived by us. Selz’s thesis is that the geometric laws of natural space describe how the points of this space are related to each other by directions which are ordered in the same way as the points on a sphere. At the end of one of his articles, Selz (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  25
    Axiomatizations of Hyperbolic Geometry: A Comparison Based on Language and Quantifier Type Complexity.Victor Pambuccian - 2002 - Synthese 133 (3):331-341.
    Hyperbolic geometry can be axiomatized using the notions of order andcongruence (as in Euclidean geometry) or using the notion of incidencealone (as in projective geometry). Although the incidence-based axiomatizationmay be considered simpler because it uses the single binary point-linerelation of incidence as a primitive notion, we show that it issyntactically more complex. The incidence-based formulation requires some axioms of the quantifier-type \forall\exists\forall, while the axiom system based on congruence and order can beformulated using only \forall\exists-axioms.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36.  74
    Review of J. Norman, After Euclid: Visual Reasoning and the Epistemology of Diagrams[REVIEW]F. Janet - 2007 - Philosophia Mathematica 15 (1):116-121.
    This monograph treats the important topic of the epistemology of diagrams in Euclidean geometry. Norman argues that diagrams play a genuine justificatory role in traditional Euclidean arguments, and he aims to account for these roles from a modified Kantian perspective. Norman considers himself a semi-Kantian in the following broad sense: he believes that Kant was right that ostensive constructions are necessary in order to follow traditional Euclidean proofs, but he wants to avoid appealing to Kantian a priori intuition (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  9
    Grasping the spirit in nature: Anschauung in Ørsted’s epistemology of science and beauty.Kristine Hays Lynning & Anja Skaar Jacobsen - 2011 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 42 (1):45-57.
    The intersection between art, poetry, philosophy and science was the leitmotif which guided the lives and careers of romantic natural philosophers including that of the Danish natural philosopher, H. C. Ørsted. A simple model of Ørsted’s career would be one in which it was framed by two periods of philosophical speculation: the youth’s curious and idealistic interest in new attractive thoughts and the experienced man’s mature reflections at the end of his life. We suggest that a closer look at the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  19
    Formalization of Hilbert's Geometry of Incidence and Parallelism.Jan von Plato - 1997 - Synthese 110 (1):127-141.
    Three things are presented: How Hilbert changed the original construction postulates of his geometry into existential axioms; In what sense he formalized geometry; How elementary geometry is formalized to present day's standards.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  78
    Formalization of Hilbert's geometry of incidence and parallelism.Jan von Plato - 1997 - Synthese 110 (1):127-141.
    Three things are presented: How Hilbert changed the original construction postulates of his geometry into existential axioms; In what sense he formalized geometry; How elementary geometry is formalized to present day's standards.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40. Fractal geometry is not the geometry of nature.Orly R. Shenker - 1994 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 25 (6):967-981.
    In recent years the magnificent world of fractals has been revealed. Some of the fractal images resemble natural forms so closely that Benoit Mandelbrot's hypothesis, that the fractal geometry is the geometry of natural objects, has been accepted by scientists and non-scientists alike. The present paper critically examines Mandelbrot's hypothesis. It first analyzes the concept of a fractal. The analysis reveals that fractals are endless geometrical processes, and not geometrical forms. A comparison between fractals and irrational numbers shows (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  41. Genetic epistemology, history of science and genetic psychology.Richard F. Kitchener - 1985 - Synthese 65 (1):3 - 31.
    Genetic epistemology analyzes the growth of knowledge both in the individual person (genetic psychology) and in the socio-historical realm (the history of science). But what the relationship is between the history of science and genetic psychology remains unclear. The biogenetic law that ontogeny recapitulates phylogeny is inadequate as a characterization of the relation. A critical examination of Piaget's Introduction à l'Épistémologie Généntique indicates these are several examples of what I call stage laws common to both areas. Furthermore, there is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  42. Hume on space, geometry, and diagrammatic reasoning.Graciela De Pierris - 2012 - Synthese 186 (1):169-189.
    Hume’s discussion of space, time, and mathematics at T 1.2 appeared to many earlier commentators as one of the weakest parts of his philosophy. From the point of view of pure mathematics, for example, Hume’s assumptions about the infinite may appear as crude misunderstandings of the continuum and infinite divisibility. I shall argue, on the contrary, that Hume’s views on this topic are deeply connected with his radically empiricist reliance on phenomenologically given sensory images. He insightfully shows that, working within (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  43. Epistemological Crisis of Quantum Theory.João Renato Amorim Feitosa - 2022 - Revista de Filosofia Moderna E Contemporânea 10 (1):35-54.
    We can easily verify that the development of the main theories of knowledge in the modern period of Western philosophy was closely related to the status quo of the development of mathematics and science in a general way. This characteristic is especially evident in the Kantian project of providing the philosophical basis to explain the possibility of (Euclidean) geometry and Newtonian physics, which Kant based on principles which he considered sine qua non conditions of human knowledge. However, the physics (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. How to Define a Number? A General Epistemological Account of Simon Stevin’s Art of Defining.Jurgen Naets - 2010 - Topoi 29 (1):77-86.
    This paper explores Simon Stevin’s l’Arithmétique of 1585, where we find a novel understanding of the concept of number. I will discuss the dynamics between his practice and philosophy of mathematics, and put it in the context of his general epistemological attitude. Subsequently, I will take a close look at his justificational concerns, and at how these are reflected in his inductive, a postiori and structuralist approach to investigating the numerical field. I will argue that Stevin’s renewed conceptualisation of the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  45.  32
    Formalization of Hilbert's geometry of incidence and parallelism.Jan Platvono - 1997 - Synthese 110 (1):127-141.
    Three things are presented: How Hilbert changed the original construction postulates of his geometry into existential axioms; In what sense he formalized geometry; How elementary geometry is formalized to present day's standards.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46. Talking at cross-purposes: how Einstein and the logical empiricists never agreed on what they were disagreeing about.Marco Giovanelli - 2013 - Synthese 190 (17):3819-3863.
    By inserting the dialogue between Einstein, Schlick and Reichenbach into a wider network of debates about the epistemology of geometry, this paper shows that not only did Einstein and Logical Empiricists come to disagree about the role, principled or provisional, played by rods and clocks in General Relativity, but also that in their lifelong interchange, they never clearly identified the problem they were discussing. Einstein’s reflections on geometry can be understood only in the context of his ”measuring (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  47.  20
    Demarcating Descartes’s geometry with clarity and distinctness.Stella S. Moon - 2023 - Synthese 202 (4):1-29.
    Descartes’s doctrine of clarity and distinctness states that whatever is clearly and distinctly perceived is true. This paper looks at his early doctrine from Rules for the Direction of the Mind, and its application to the demarcation problem of curves in Descartes’s Geometry. This paper offers and defends a novel account of the demarcation criterion of curves: a curve is geometrical just in case it is clearly and distinctly perceivable. This account connects Descartes’s rationalist epistemological programme with his ontological (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  20
    Correction: Grothendieck’s theory of schemes and the algebra–geometry duality.Gabriel Catren & Fernando Cukierman - 2022 - Synthese 200 (4):1-1.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  67
    Poincaré on the Foundations of Arithmetic and Geometry. Part 2: Intuition and Unity in Mathematics.Katherine Dunlop - 2017 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 7 (1):88-107.
    Part 1 of this article exposed a tension between Poincaré’s views of arithmetic and geometry and argued that it could not be resolved by taking geometry to depend on arithmetic. Part 2 aims to resolve the tension by supposing not merely that intuition’s role is to justify induction on the natural numbers but rather that it also functions to acquaint us with the unity of orders and structures and show practices to fit or harmonize with experience. I argue (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  82
    Why Euclid’s geometry brooked no doubt: J. H. Lambert on certainty and the existence of models.Katherine Dunlop - 2009 - Synthese 167 (1):33-65.
    J. H. Lambert proved important results of what we now think of as non-Euclidean geometries, and gave examples of surfaces satisfying their theorems. I use his philosophical views to explain why he did not think the certainty of Euclidean geometry was threatened by the development of what we regard as alternatives to it. Lambert holds that theories other than Euclid's fall prey to skeptical doubt. So despite their satisfiability, for him these theories are not equal to Euclid's in justification. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000