Results for 'Bolzano-Tarski programme'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Consequences and Design in General and Transcendental Logic.Elena G. Dragalina-Chernaya - 2018 - Kantian Journal 37 (1):25-39.
  2.  14
    Bolzano's Programme and Abstract Objects.Rolf George - 1997 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 53 (1):167-180.
    Most of the Bolzano literature is exegetical, neglecting, unfortunately, the great potential of his logic as the beginning of a PROGRAMME. Specifically, his unorthodox construai of the consequence relation as triadic, and his account of logical form are promising beginnings which even as they stand shed light on question of relevance, the ancient problems of enthymemes and others. Instead of developing these suggestions, Bolzano scholars have been occupied with elucidating the ontology of sentences in themselves, and related (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  31
    Bolzano's Programme and Abstract Objects.Rolf George - 1997 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 53 (1):167-180.
    Most of the Bolzano literature is exegetical, neglecting, unfortunately, the great potential of his logic as the beginning of a PROGRAMME. Specifically, his unorthodox construai of the consequence relation as triadic, and his account of logical form are promising beginnings which even as they stand shed light on question of relevance, the ancient problems of enthymemes and others. Instead of developing these suggestions, Bolzano scholars have been occupied with elucidating the ontology of sentences in themselves, and related (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. What are logical notions?Alfred Tarski - 1986 - History and Philosophy of Logic 7 (2):143-154.
    In this manuscript, published here for the first time, Tarski explores the concept of logical notion. He draws on Klein's Erlanger Programm to locate the logical notions of ordinary geometry as those invariant under all transformations of space. Generalizing, he explicates the concept of logical notion of an arbitrary discipline.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   223 citations  
  5.  51
    Bolzano's deducibility and tarski's logical consequence.Paul B. Thompson - 1981 - History and Philosophy of Logic 2 (1-2):11-20.
    In this paper I argue that Bolzano's concept of deducibility and Tarski's concept of logical consequence differ with respect to their philosophical intent. I distinguish between epistemic and ontic approaches to logic, and argue that Bolzano's deducibility presupposes an epistemic approach, while Tarski's logical consequence presupposes an ontic approach.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  6.  11
    Bolzanos Ableitbarkeit und Tarskis logische Folgerung.Mark Siebel - 1997 - In Julian Nida-Rümelin & Georg Meggle (eds.), Analyomen 2, Volume I: Logic, Epistemology, Philosophy of Science. De Gruyter. pp. 148-156.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  7.  14
    Philosophy and Logic in central Europe from Bolzano to Tarski.Peter M. Simons - 1992 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    This book with an introduction by Witold Marciszewski, views the history of philosophy and logic from 1837 to 1939 from the perspective of the cradle of modern exact philosophy - Central Europe. In a series of case studies, it illuminates the developments in this region, most notably in Austria and Poland, examining thinkers such as Bolzano, Brentano, Meinong, Husserl, Twardowski, Lesniewski, and Tarski, as well as the logicians like Frege and Russell with whom they bore a close resemblance. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  8. Tarski's theory of truth and a programme for semantics1.Krystyna Misiuna - 1996 - Dialogue and Universalism 6 (1-6):117.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  11
    Bolzano and Analytic Philosophy.Wolfgang Künne, Mark Siebel & Mark Textor (eds.) - 1997 - BRILL.
    Inhaltsverzeichnis/Table of Contents: Vorbemerkung/Preface. Dagfin FØLLESDAL: Bolzano's Legacy. Jan BERG: Bolzano, the Prescient Encyclopedist. Jan SEBESTIK: Bolzano, Exner and the Origins of Analytical Philosophy. Paul RUSNOCK: Bolzano and the Traditions of Analysis. Peter SIMONS: Bolzano on Collections. Ali BEHBOUD: Remarks on Bolzano's Collections. Mark SIEBEL: Variation, Derivability and Necessity. Edgar MORSCHER: Bolzano's Method of Variation: Three Puzzles. Rolf GEORGE: Bolzano's Programme andObjects. Mark TEXTOR: Bolzano's Sententialism. Wolfgang KÜNNE: Propositions in (...) and Frege. Michael DUMMETT: Comments on Wolfgang Künne's Paper. Carsten Uwe GIESKE: Bolzano's Notion of Testifying. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  10. From the Act of Judging to the Sentence: The Problem of Truth Bearers From Bolzano to Tarski.Jan Wole'nski & Artur Rojszczak - 2005 - Springer.
  11. Philosophy and Logic in Central Europe from Bolzano to Tarski. Selected Essays.Peter Simons - 1994 - Erkenntnis 41 (2):275-279.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  12. Etchemendy and Bolzano on Logical Consequence.Paul Rusnock & Mark Burke - 2010 - History and Philosophy of Logic 31 (1):3-29.
    In a series of publications beginning in the 1980s, John Etchemendy has argued that the standard semantical account of logical consequence, due in its essentials to Alfred Tarski, is fundamentally mistaken. He argues that, while Tarski's definition requires us to classify the terms of a language as logical or non-logical, no such division is guaranteed to deliver the correct extension of our pre-theoretical or intuitive consequence relation. In addition, and perhaps more importantly, Tarski's account is claimed to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  13.  29
    Tarski, Davidson et la signification.Daniel Laurier - 1983 - Dialogue 22 (4):595-620.
    Depuis 1967, Donald Davidson defend l'idée qu'une théorie de la signification pour une langue naturelle doit prendre la forme d'une théorie tarskienne de la vérité. Je me propose ici d'exposer les grandes lignes de l a conception davidsonienne de la sémantique des langues naturelles et de chercher à préciser en quel sens une theorie tarskienne de la vérité pour une langue L constitue, selon Davidson, une théorié de la signification pour L. Je ferai pour cela abstraction des obstacles qu'il pourrait (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  12
    The Variety of Consequence, According to Bolzano.Johan van Benthem - 1985 - Studia Logica 44 (4):389-403.
    Contemporary historians of logic tend to credit Bernard Bolzano with the invention of the semantic notion of consequence, a full century before Tarski. Nevertheless, Bolzano's work played no significant rôle in the genesis of modern logical semantics. The purpose of this paper is to point out three highly original, and still quite relevant themes in Bolzano's work, being a systematic study of possible types of inference, of consistency, as well as their meta-theory. There are certain analogies (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  15.  24
    Le programme de Davidson et les langues naturelles.Daniel Laurier - 1985 - Dialogue 24 (2):195-212.
    Une théorie davidsonienne de la signification pour une langue L prend la forme d'une theorie tarskienne de la véeritée-dans-L. Une telle théeorie sera absolument radicale s'il est possible d'éetablir qu'elle est tarskienne, c'est-à-dire conforme à la convention T de Tarski, en n'utilisant que des donnéees empiriques dont la description ne fait intervenir aucun concept linguistique, tandis qu'elle sera relativement radicale s'il est possible d'éetablir qu'elle est tarskienne en n'utilisant que des donnéees empiriques dont la description ne fait intervenir aucun (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  67
    The variety of consequence, according to Bolzano.Johan Benthem - 1985 - Studia Logica 44 (4):389 - 403.
    Contemporary historians of logic tend to credit Bernard Bolzano with the invention of the semantic notion, of consequence, a full century before Tarski. Nevertheless, Bolzano's work played no significant rôle in the genesis of modern logical semantics. The purpose of this paper is to point out three highly original, and still quite relevant themes in Bolzano's work, being a systematic study of possible types of inference, of consistency, as well as their meta-theory. There are certain analogies (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  17.  3
    Sémantique et vérité: de Tarski à Davidson.François Rivenc - 1998 - Paris: Presses universitaires de France.
    Parmi les travaux contemporains en sémantique du langage ordinaire, le "programme de Davidson " se distingue par sa portée philosophique : la théorie de la vérité que propose Davidson à titre de cadre sémantique s'épanouit en effet en une véritable philosophie du langage, connue sous le nom d'interprétation radicale. Cet ouvrage tente une évaluation critique du programme de Davidson, à partir d'une question à la fois historique et conceptuelle : quels ont les rapports entre le projet d'une théorie (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Consequence Mining: Constans Versus Consequence Relations.Denis Bonnay & Dag Westerståhl - 2012 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 41 (4):671-709.
    The standard semantic definition of consequence with respect to a selected set X of symbols, in terms of truth preservation under replacement (Bolzano) or reinterpretation (Tarski) of symbols outside X, yields a function mapping X to a consequence relation ⇒x. We investigate a function going in the other direction, thus extracting the constants of a given consequence relation, and we show that this function (a) retrieves the usual logical constants from the usual logical consequence relations, and (b) is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  19.  3
    Sémantique et vérité. De Tarski à Davidson. [REVIEW]Martin Montminy - 2000 - Dialogue 39 (2):394-396.
    Il n’est pas facile de voir quel est l’objectif de ce livre. Au chapitreI, Rivenc annonce que ce qui l’intéresse est le lien chez Davidson entre le format d’une théorie de la signification pour les langues naturelles et le thème de l’interprétation radicale qui serait à l’œuvre dans tout échange linguistique. En fait, Rivenc ne dit à peu près rien sur ce lien. Son livre consiste plutôt en une suite de critiques disparates du programme de Davidson, qu’il emprunte à (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  4
    Analytische Philosophie: Anspruch und Wirklichkeit eines Programms.Michael Otte - 2014 - Hamburg: Meiner.
    Anstelle einer Einleitung: ein Thema und eine Sichtweise desselben -- Analytische Philsophie zwischen Sprache, Logik und Mathematik -- Die analytische Philosophie und das Phänomenon der Komplementarität -- Kant, Bolzano und Peirce: die Unterschedung des Analytischen und Synthetischen, oder: von der Erkenntnistheorie zur Semantik und Zeichentheorie -- Ernst Cassirer und die Entwicklung von Analyse und Synthese seit Descartes und Leibniz -- Bertrand Russell (1872-1970) -- Die naturalisierte Erkenntnistheorie zwischen Wiener Kries und Pragmatismus: Willard Van Orward [sic] Quine -- Richard Rorty: (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. The Logic of Logical Necessity.Andrew Bacon & Kit Fine - manuscript
    Prior to Kripke's seminal work on the semantics of modal logic, McKinsey offered an alternative interpretation of the necessity operator, inspired by the Bolzano-Tarski notion of logical truth. According to this interpretation, `it is necessary that A' is true just in case every sentence with the same logical form as A is true. In our paper, we investigate this interpretation of the modal operator, resolving some technical questions, and relating it to the logical interpretation of modality and some (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22. Inferentialism without Verificationism: Reply to Prawitz.Julien Murzi - 2011 - In Emiliano Ippoliti, Carlo Cellucci & Emily Grosholz (eds.), Logic and Knowledge. Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholar Publishing. pp. 285-90.
    I discuss Prawitz’s claim that a non-reliabilist answer to the question “What is a proof?” compels us to reject the standard Bolzano-Tarski account of validity, andto account for the meaning of a sentence in broadly verificationist terms. I sketch what I take to be a possible way of resisting Prawitz’s claim---one that concedes the anti-reliabilist assumption from which Prawitz’s argument proceeds.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  8
    Consequence Relations with Real Truth Values.Daniele Mundici - 2021 - In Ofer Arieli & Anna Zamansky (eds.), Arnon Avron on Semantics and Proof Theory of Non-Classical Logics. Springer Verlag. pp. 249-264.
    Syntax and semantics in Łukasiewicz infinite-valued sentential logic Ł are harmonized by revising the Bolzano-Tarski paradigm of “semantic consequence,” according to which, θ\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$\theta $$\end{document} follows from Θ\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$\Theta $$\end{document} iff every valuation v that satisfies all formulas in Θ\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$\Theta $$\end{document} also satisfies θ.\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$\theta.$$\end{document} For (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  23
    Universal Properties of Łukasiewicz Consequence.Daniele Mundici - 2014 - Logica Universalis 8 (1):17-24.
    Boolean logic deals with {0, 1}-observables and yes–no events, as many-valued logic does for continuous ones. Since every measurement has an error, continuity ensures that small measurement errors on elementary observables have small effects on compound observables. Continuity is irrelevant for {0, 1}-observables. Functional completeness no longer holds when n-ary connectives are understood as [0, 1]-valued maps defined on [0, 1] n . So one must envisage suitable selection criteria for [0, 1]-connectives. Łukasiewicz implication has a well known characterization as (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  19
    Srovnání bolzanovy a tarského definice vyplývání.Marta Vlasáková - 1999 - Organon F: Medzinárodný Časopis Pre Analytickú Filozofiu 6 (1):1-5.
    Bernard Bolzano presents in his work Wissenschaftslehre a definition of derivability among sentences. Tarski publishes his well-known definition of logical consequence almost one hundred years later. This article intends to prove that the Bolzano´s definition is fully satisfactory compared to the Tarski´s one, even though no attention was drawn to Bolzano´s definition at that time.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  7
    The Completeness Theorem? So What!Göran Sundholm - 2024 - In Antonio Piccolomini D'Aragona (ed.), Perspectives on Deduction: Contemporary Studies in the Philosophy, History and Formal Theories of Deduction. Springer Verlag. pp. 39-50.
    Bolzano reduced inferential validity of the inference (from premise judgements to conclusion judgment) to the holding of logical consequence between the propositions (in themselves) that serve as contents of the respective judgements. This explicit reduction of inferential validity among judgements to logical consequence among propositions (or, alternatively, to logical truth of certain implicational propositions) has been largely taken over by current logical theory, say, by Wittgenstein’s Tractatus, by Hilbert and Ackermann, by Quine, and by Tarski also. Frege, though, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Truthmakers, Truthbearers and the Objectivity of Truth.Artur Rojszczak & Barry Smith - 2003 - In Jaako Hintikka (ed.), Philosophy and Logic: In Search of the Polish Tradition. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 229-268.
    The aim of this paper is to show that the account of objective truth taken for granted by logicians at least since the publication in 1933 of Tarski’s “The Concept of Truth in Formalized Languages” arose out of a tradition of philosophical thinking initiated by Bolzano and Brentano. The paper shows more specifically that certain investigations of states of affairs and other objectual correlates of judging acts, investigations carried out by Austrian and Polish philosophers around the turn of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  28.  96
    A completeness theorem for unrestricted first- order languages.Agustin Rayo & Timothy Williamson - 2003 - In J. C. Beall (ed.), Liars and heaps: new essays on paradox. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Here is an account of logical consequence inspired by Bolzano and Tarski. Logical validity is a property of arguments. An argument is a pair of a set of interpreted sentences (the premises) and an interpreted sentence (the conclusion). Whether an argument is logically valid depends only on its logical form. The logical form of an argument is fixed by the syntax of its constituent sentences, the meanings of their logical constituents and the syntactic differences between their non-logical constituents, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  29.  38
    A completeness theorem for unrestricted first- order languages.Agustin Rayo & Timothy Williamson - 2003 - In J. C. Beall (ed.), Liars and Heaps: New Essays on Paradox. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press UK. pp. 331-356.
    Here is an account of logical consequence inspired by Bolzano and Tarski. Logical validity is a property of arguments. An argument is a pair of a set of interpreted sentences (the premises) and an interpreted sentence (the conclusion). Whether an argument is logically valid depends only on its logical form. The logical form of an argument is fixed by the syntax of its constituent sentences, the meanings of their logical constituents and the syntactic differences between their non-logical constituents, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  30.  8
    Mathesis universalis: l'idée de mathématique universelle d'Aristote à Descartes.David Rabouin - 2009 - Paris: Presses universitaires de France.
    Fondée sous les auspices du père de notre modernité philosophique Descartes, puis consolidée par des penseurs aussi importants que Leibniz, Bolzano ou Husserl, la mathesis universalis paraît représenter à elle seule l'ambitieux programme du « rationalisme classique ». Des philosophes tels que Husserl, Russell, Heidegger ou Cassirer ont pu s'accorder en ce point. Le développement de la « science moderne » aurait porté ce grand « rêve dogmatique » pour mener vers son terme le destin de la métaphysique (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  31.  31
    Two Early Arabic Applications of Model-Theoretic Consequence.Wilfrid Hodges - 2018 - Logica Universalis 12 (1-2):37-54.
    We trace two logical ideas further back than they have previously been traced. One is the idea of using diagrams to prove that certain logical premises do—or don’t—have certain logical consequences. This idea is usually credited to Venn, and before him Euler, and before him Leibniz. We find the idea correctly and vigorously used by Abū al-Barakāt in 12th century Baghdad. The second is the idea that in formal logic, P logically entails Q if and only if every model of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  32.  18
    La logique, science recherchée.Brice Halimi - 2020 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 106 (2):145-164.
    Une théorie de la science qui permette une « étude systématique des formes » est l’ἐπιστήμη ζητοῦμένη de Cavaillès : ce dernier ne la trouve ni dans l’analytique kantienne, ni dans la théorie de la science de Bolzano ; pas plus que chez Frege, Carnap ou Tarski ; et ni dans la théorie de la démonstration, ni dans la mathesis husserlienne. Cet article défend l’idée qu’il aurait pu la trouver, ou du moins s’en approcher, s’il avait accordé davantage (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  24
    La notion bolzanienne de déductibilité.Mark Siebel - 2003 - Philosophiques 30 (1):171-189.
    L’article présente le concept de déductibilité que Bolzano introduit dans sa Wissenscahftslehre, indique quelques traits caractéristiques en vertu desquels ce concept diffère de plusieurs conceptions contemporaines de la conséquence et examine l’affirmation selon laquelle il présente une forte similarité avec la conception de Tarski et la logique de la pertinence.The article presents the concept of deducibility which Bolzano introduced in his Wissenschaftslehre, points out some of the characteristic features in virtue of which it differs from many modern (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Conceptions of logical implication.José M. Sagüillo - 2002 - Logica Trianguli 6:41-67.
    This is a survey paper of approaches to the concept of logical implication. Roughly stated the main motivation of these approaches is to provide a necessary and sufficient condition for a set of propositions to logically imply a single proposition. In regard to their affinities these approaches are grouped into two: the transformational conception and the informational conception. Some approaches in each conception are philosophical and some are mathematical in character, their common assumption being that they reflect a previous intuition (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  81
    The concept of logical consequence.Michael Detlefsen - 1993 - Philosophical Books 34 (1):1-10.
  36. An Interview with Donald Davidson.Donald Davidson - 2004 - In Problems of rationality. New York: Oxford University Press.
    The last chapter is an interview Ernest Lepore, Director of the Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science and a friend of the Davidson family, has conducted with the author in 1988. In this interview, the author speaks of his childhood, his student years at Harvard, and his service in the navy in the Second World War. He describes his academic career, which took him from Queens College to Stanford, Princeton, and Rockefeller University, and illuminates his personal and philosophical relationships with contemporary (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37. Internal and external consistency of arithmetic.Yvon Gauthier - 2001 - Logica Trianguli 5:19-41.
    What Gödel referred to as “outer” consistency is contrasted with the “inner” consistency of arithmetic from a constructivist point of view. In the settheoretic setting of Peano arithmetic, the diagonal procedure leads out of the realm of natural numbers. It is shown that Hilbert’s programme of arithmetization points rather to an “internalisation” of consistency. The programme was continued by Herbrand, Gödel and Tarski. Tarski’s method of quantifier elimination and Gödel’s Dialectica interpretation are part and parcel of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  31
    Metamathematics and philosophy.Jan Wolenski - 1983 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 12 (4):221-225.
    The relevance of metamathematical researches for philosophy of math- ematics is an indubitable matter. In the paper I shall speak about impli- cations of metamathematics for general philosophy, especially for classical epistemological problems. Let us start with a historical observation con- cerning Hilbert's programme, the rst research programme in metamathe- matics as a separate study of formal systems. This programme was strongly in uence by epistemological considerations. In fact, Hilbert wanted to se- cure all classical mathematics against (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  56
    A Davidsonian Truth-theoretic Semantics Treatment of an EkeGusii Proverb.Evans Gesura Mecha & Isaac Nilson Opande - 2021 - Macrolinguistics 9 (2):68-94.
    The paper examines some doctrines of the Davidsonian Programme of truth conditional Semantics that relates truth to meaning using Tarski’s T-Convention, in relation to its efficacy in a semantic valuation of the EkeGusii proverb: Nda ’indongi ereta morogi ereta moibi which exemplifies a kind of complex sentence that a given system of Semantics is meant to account for. The coverage of Davidsonian truth-conditional notion of T-convention and that of compositionality are considered to have only a partial reach in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Tense Logic and Ontology of Time.Avril Styrman - 2021 - Emilio M. Sanfilippo Et Al, Eds., Proceedings of FOUST 2021: 5th Workshop on Foundational Ontology, Held at JOWO 2021: Episode VII The Bolzano Summer of Knowledge, September 11–18, 2021, Bolzano, Italy, CEURWS, Vol. 2969, 2021.
    This work aims to make tense logic a more robust tool for ontologists, philosophers, knowledge engineers and programmers by outlining a fusion of tense logic and ontology of time. In order to make tense logic better understandable, the central formal primitives of standard tense logic are derived as theorems from an informal and intuitive ontology of time. In order to make formulation of temporal propositions easier, temporal operators that were introduced by Georg Henrik von Wright are developed, and mapped to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41. Russell’s Many Points.Thomas Mormann - 2009 - In Alexander Hieke & Hannes Leitgeb (eds.), Reduction, Abstraction, Analysis. Ontos. pp. 11--239.
    Bertrand Russell was one of the protagonists of the programme of reducing “disagreeable” concepts to philosophically more respectable ones. Throughout his life he was engaged in eliminating or paraphrasing away a copious variety of allegedly dubious concepts: propositions, definite descriptions, knowing subjects, and points, among others. The critical aim of this paper is to show that Russell’s construction of points, which has been considered as a paradigm of a logical construction überhaupt, fails for principal mathematical reasons. Russell could have (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42. Tarski's system of geometry.Alfred Tarski & Steven Givant - 1999 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 5 (2):175-214.
    This paper is an edited form of a letter written by the two authors (in the name of Tarski) to Wolfram Schwabhäuser around 1978. It contains extended remarks about Tarski's system of foundations for Euclidean geometry, in particular its distinctive features, its historical evolution, the history of specific axioms, the questions of independence of axioms and primitive notions, and versions of the system suitable for the development of 1-dimensional geometry.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  43.  16
    Aritmética Semántica: un prefacio.John Corcoran & Gabriel Garduño-Soto - 2020 - Agora 39 (1).
    La teoría de números, o la aritmética pura, concierne a los números naturales mismos, no a la notación usada, y en particular no a los numerales. La teoría de ristras, o la sintaxis pura, concierne a los numerales como ristras de caracteres «no-interpretados», al margen de los números que puedan denotar cuando son usados. La teoría de los números es puramente aritmética, la teoría de ristras es puramente sintáctica… en tanto se considere el universo del discurso solo. La aritmética semántica (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Bernard Bolzano, 1781-1848: Studien und Quellen.Bernard Bolzano & Werner Schuffenhauer (eds.) - 1981 - Berlin: Akademie Verlag.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  15
    Bernard Bolzano, Leben und Wirkung.Bernard Bolzano, Curt Christian & Jaromír Loužil (eds.) - 1981 - Wien: Verlag der Österreichischen Akademie der Wissenschaften.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  19
    Bernard Bolzano-Gesamtausgabe: Schriften. Lehrbuch der Religionswissenschaft.Bernard Bolzano & Eduard Winter - 2006 - Frommann Holzboog. Edited by Eduard Winter.
    Einleitungsband. 1. T. Biographie -- 2. T. Bolzano-Bibliographie und Editionsprinzipien der Gesamtausgabe. (v. <1-2>). Supplement <1-2> -- Reihe I, Schriften -- Bd. 2. Erbauungsreden für Akademiker -- Bd. 6. Lehrbuch der Religionswissenschaft, Erster Teil. (2 v.) -- Bd. 7. Lehrbuch der Religionswissenschaft, Zweiter Teil. (2 v.) -- Bd. 8. Lehrbuch der Religionswissenschaft, Dritter Teil. (v. <1-4 >) -- Bd. 11. Wissenschaftslehre (3 v.) -- Bd. 12. Wissenschaftslehre. (3 v.) -- Bd. 13. Wissenschaftslehre. (3 v.) -- Bd. 14. Wissenschaftslehre. (v. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  47.  4
    Bernard Bolzanos Wissenschaftslehre in vier Bänden.Bernard Bolzano & Wolfgang Schultz - 1929 - Leipzig,: F. Meiner. Edited by Wolfgang Schultz.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  10
    Bernard Bolzano: de la Methode Mathematique Et La Correspondance Avec Exner.Bernard Bolzano - 2008 - Librarie Philosophique J. Vrin.
    Bernard Bolzano (1781-1848) a passe toute sa vie en Boheme, qui faisait encore partie de l'Empire autrichien. Apres des etudes de philosophie, mathematique et theologie, il est devenu pretre et professeur de Science de la religion a l'Universite de Prague. Heritier de l'Aufklarung, il a consacre sa vie a la reforme de la semi-feodale societe autrichienne et a la reforme des sciences a priori: logique, mathematique et theologie. Ses critiques de la constitution et de l'ordre existant lui valurent d'etre (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. The semantic conception of truth and the foundations of semantics.Alfred Tarski - 1943 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 4 (3):341-376.
  50. Address at the Princeton University Bicentennial Conference on Problems of Mathematics (December 17–19, 1946), By Alfred Tarski.Alfred Tarski & Hourya Sinaceur - 2000 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 6 (1):1-44.
    This article presents Tarski's Address at the Princeton Bicentennial Conference on Problems of Mathematics, together with a separate summary. Two accounts of the discussion which followed are also included. The central topic of the Address and of the discussion is decision problems. The introductory note gives information about the Conference, about the background of the subjects discussed in the Address, and about subsequent developments to these subjects.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000