Results for ' Thomason's theory of events'

994 found
Order:
  1.  55
    Free construction of time from events.S. K. Thomason - 1989 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 18 (1):43 - 67.
    Some may be of the opinion that one event can begin before another only by virtue of the existence of some event (a “witness”) which wholly precedes the other and does not wholly precede the one (and similarly for “ends before” and “does not abut”). Those would prefer $\mathbb{F}$ 0 to $\mathbb{F}$ as a model for observers' apprehensions of events. Since G is a functor from $\mathbb{M}$ to $\mathbb{F}$ 0, the current construction (restricted to $\mathbb{F}$ 0) remains applicable.This work (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  2.  70
    On constructing instants from events.S. K. Thomason - 1984 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 13 (1):85 - 96.
  3.  10
    Russell's Theories of Events and Instants from the Perspective of Point-Free Ontologies in the Tradition of the Lvov-Warsaw School.Andrzej Pietruszczak - 2024 - History and Philosophy of Logic 45 (2):161-195.
    We classify two of Bertrand Russell's theories of events within the point-free ontology. The first of such approaches was presented informally by Russell in ‘The World of Physics and the World of Sense’ (Lecture IV in Our Knowledge of the External World of 1914). Based on this theory, Russell sketched ways to construct instants as collections of events. This paper formalizes Russell's approach from 1914. We will also show that in such a reconstructed theory, we obtain (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  20
    C. E. M. Yates. Recursively enumerable degrees and the degrees less than 0. Sets, models and recursion theory, Proceedings of the Summer School in Mathematical Logic and Tenth Logic Colloquium, Leicester, August-September 1965, edited by John N. Crossley, Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics, North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam, and Humanities Press, New York, 1967, pp. 264–271. [REVIEW]S. K. Thomason - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (4):589-589.
  5.  62
    A sceptical theory of inheritance in nonmonotonic semantic networks.John F. Horty, Richmond H. Thomason & David S. Touretzky - 1990 - Artificial Intelligence 42 (2-3):311-348.
    inheritance reasoning in semantic networks allowing for multiple inheritance with exceptions. The approach leads to a definition of iaheritance that is..
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  6. A Kantian Argument for Sovereignty Rights of Indigenous Peoples.Thomason Krista - 2014 - Public Reason 6 (1-2):21-34.
    Kant’s non-voluntarist conception of political obligation has led some philosophers to argue that he would reject self-government rights for indigenous peoples. Some recent scholarship suggests, however, that Kant’s critique of colonialism provides an argument in favor of granting self-government rights. Here I argue for a stronger conclusion: Kantian political theory not only can but must include sovereignty for indigenous peoples. Normally these rights are considered redress for historic injustice. On a Kantian view, however, I argue that they are not (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Shame and Contempt in Kant's Moral Theory.Krista K. Thomason - 2013 - Kantian Review 18 (2):221-240.
    Attitudes like shame and contempt seem to be at odds with basic tenets of Kantian moral theory. I argue on the contrary that both attitudes play a central role in Kantian morality. Shame and contempt are attitudes that protect our love of honour, or the esteem we have for ourselves as moral persons. The question arises: how are these attitudes compatible with Kant's claim that all persons deserve respect? I argue that the proper object of shame and contempt is (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  8. A Good Enough Heart: Kant and the Cultivation of Emotions.Krista K. Thomason - 2017 - Kantian Review 22 (3):441-462.
    One way of understanding Kant’s views about moral emotions is the cultivation view. On this view, emotions play a role in Kantian morality provided they are properly cultivated. I evince a sceptical position about the cultivation view. First, I show that the textual evidence in support of cultivation is ambiguous. I then provide an account of emotions in Kant’s theory that explains both his positive and negative views about them. Emotions capture our attention such that they both disrupt the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  9. Above All Things Human: Bestimmung in Salomo Friedlaender’s Kant for Children.Krista K. Thomason - 2024 - In Salomo Friedlaender (ed.), Kant for Children. De Gruyter. pp. 121-140. Translated by Bruce Krajewski.
    Kant’s commitment to universalism has been called into question since increasing attention has been paid to his work on race in the last 20 years. This worry can easily be applied to Kant’s work on education: when Kant describes education as allowing humanity to fulfill its Bestimmung (vocation), scholars might reasonably conclude that such a claim only applies certain racial groups. Yet Salomo Friedlaender claims that if Kant’s moral theory is taught to children, “Every person is valued according to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Bayesians sometimes cannot ignore even very implausible theories (even ones that have not yet been thought of).Branden Fitelson & Neil Thomason - 2008 - Australasian Journal of Logic 6:25-36.
    In applying Bayes’s theorem to the history of science, Bayesians sometimes assume – often without argument – that they can safely ignore very implausible theories. This assumption is false, both in that it can seriously distort the history of science as well as the mathematics and the applicability of Bayes’s theorem. There are intuitively very plausible counter-examples. In fact, one can ignore very implausible or unknown theories only if at least one of two conditions is satisfied: (i) one is certain (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  11.  32
    Some Limitations to the Psychological Orientation in Semantic Theory.Richmond H. Thomason - 2011 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 40 (1):1 - 14.
    The psychological orientation treats semantics as a matter of idealized computation over symbolic structures, and semantic relations like denotation as relations between linguistic expressions and these structures. I argue that results similar to Gödel's incompleteness theorems and Tarski's theorem on truth create foundational difficulties for this view of semantics.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  12.  3
    To Remember a Vanishing World: D. L. Hightower's Photographs of Barbour County, Alabama, C. 1930-1965.Michael V. R. Thomason - 1997 - University Alabama Press.
    This remarkable collection of period photographs details day-to-day life and changing times in the Deep South. Draffus Lamar Hightower, 1899-1993, spent most of his life in Barbour County, Alabama. For many years he was the owner of a Chevrolet dealership, but he had another occupation as well. From his youth, he was fascinated with photography, and for fifty years he experimented with the craft both technically and artistically. Hightower, while participating fully in the 20th century, was also acutely aware of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. Iterative probability kinematics.Horacio Arló-Costa & Richmond Thomason - 2001 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 30 (5):479-524.
    Following the pioneer work of Bruno De Finetti [12], conditional probability spaces (allowing for conditioning with events of measure zero) have been studied since (at least) the 1950's. Perhaps the most salient axiomatizations are Karl Popper's in [31], and Alfred Renyi's in [33]. Nonstandard probability spaces [34] are a well know alternative to this approach. Vann McGee proposed in [30] a result relating both approaches by showing that the standard values of infinitesimal probability functions are representable as Popper functions, (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  14. Semantic analysis of tense logics.S. K. Thomason - 1972 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 37 (1):150-158.
    Although we believe the results reported below to have direct philosophical import, we shall for the most part confine our remarks to the realm of mathematics. The reader is referred to [4] for a philosophically oriented discussion, comprehensible to mathematicians, of tense logic.The “minimal” tense logicT0is the system having connectives ∼, →,F(“at some future time”), andP(“at some past time”); the following axioms:(whereGandHabbreviate ∼F∼ and ∼P∼ respectively); and the following rules:(8) fromαandα → β, inferβ,(9) fromα, infer any substitution instance ofα,(10) fromα, (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  15. Could Lakatos, even with Zahar's criterion for novel fact, evaluate the copernican research programme?Neil Thomason - 1992 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 43 (2):161-200.
    Why did Copernicus's research programme supersede Ptolemy's?’, Lakatos and Zahar argued that, on Zahar's criterion for ‘novel fact’, Copernican theory was objectively scientifically superior to Ptolemaic theory. They are mistaken, Lakatos and Zahar applied Zahar's criterion to ‘a historical thought-experiment’—fictional rather than real history. Further, in their fictional history, they compared Copernicus to Eudoxus rather than Ptolemy, ignored Tycho Brahe, and did not consider facts that would be novel for geostatic theories. When Zahar's criterion is applied to real (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  16.  38
    The extensions of the modal logic K.Michael C. Nagle & S. K. Thomason - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (1):102-109.
  17.  58
    Reduction of second‐order logic to modal logic.S. K. Thomason - 1975 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 21 (1):107-114.
  18.  89
    Semantic analysis of the modal syllogistic.S. K. Thomason - 1993 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 22 (2):111 - 128.
  19.  33
    Categories of frames for modal logic.S. K. Thomason - 1975 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 40 (3):439-442.
  20.  50
    Reduction of tense logic to modal logic. I.S. K. Thomason - 1974 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 39 (3):549-551.
  21.  56
    Reduction of tense logic to modal logic II.S. K. Thomason - 1975 - Theoria 41 (3):154-169.
  22.  25
    Sublattices of the Recursively Enumerable Degrees.S. K. Thomason - 1971 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 17 (1):273-280.
  23.  44
    Sublattices of the Recursively Enumerable Degrees.S. K. Thomason - 1971 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 17 (1):273-280.
  24.  54
    Relational models for the modal syllogistic.S. K. Thomason - 1997 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 26 (2):129-141.
    An interpretation of Aristotle's modal syllogistic is proposed which is intuitively graspable, if only formally correst. The individuals to which a term applies, and possibly-applies, are supposed to be determined in a uniform way by the set of individuals to which the term necessarily-applies.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  25.  25
    [Omnibus Review].S. K. Thomason - 1978 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 43 (2):373-376.
  26.  72
    Independent propositional modal logics.S. K. Thomason - 1980 - Studia Logica 39 (2-3):143 - 144.
    We show that the join of two classical [respectively, regular, normal] modal logics employing distinct modal operators is a conservative extension of each of them.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  27.  40
    Noncompactness in propositional modal logic.S. K. Thomason - 1972 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 37 (4):716-720.
  28.  23
    The logical consequence relation of propositional tense logic.S. K. Thomason - 1975 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 21 (1):29-40.
  29.  60
    Reduction of tense logic to modal logic II.S. K. Thomason - 1974 - Theoria 40 (3):154-169.
  30.  8
    Philosophical Logic and Artificial Intelligence.Richmond H. Thomason - 1988 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    cians concerned with using logical tools in philosophy have been keenly aware of the limitations that arise from the original con centration of symbolic logic on the idiom of mathematics, and many of them have worked to create extensions of the received logical theories that would make them more generally applicable in philosophy. Carnap's Testability and Meaning, published in 1936 and 1937, was a good early example of this sort of research, motivated by the inadequacy of first-order formalizations of dis (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Possible worlds and many truth values.S. Thomason - 1977 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 6 (3):107-109.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  32.  24
    David Makinson. Some embedding theorems for modal logic. Notre Dame journal of formal logic, vol. 12 , pp. 252–254.S. K. Thomason - 1974 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 39 (2):351.
  33.  46
    A theorem on initial segments of degrees.S. K. Thomason - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (1):41-45.
    A set S of degrees is said to be an initial segment if c ≤ d ∈ S→-c∈S. Shoenfield has shown that if P is the lattice of all subsets of a finite set then there is an initial segment of degrees isomorphic to P. Rosenstein [2] (independently) proved the same to hold of the lattice of all finite subsets of a countable set. We shall show that “countable set” may be replaced by “set of cardinality at most that of (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  25
    On initial segments of hyperdegrees.S. K. Thomason - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (2):189-197.
  35.  28
    Spring meeting of the association for symbolic logic: Toronto, 1993.S. K. Thomason - 1994 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 59 (1):346-349.
  36.  11
    Hobbes’s Theory of Responsibility as Support for Sommerville’s Argument Against Hobbes’s Approval of Independency.S. A. Lloyd - 2022 - Hobbes Studies 35 (1):51-66.
    Just as some types of philosophical analysis are more useful than others to historians or political scientists, so, I find, are some sorts of historical research more useful to philosophers than are other sorts. Sommerville makes history useful to non-historians by clarifying the large-scale historical background against which his investigative questions are posed, and then separating out crucial figures, ideas, and events from arcana of interest primarily to specialist historians. His interpretations are relatively neutral, striking a welcome balance between (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  32
    David Makinson. A generalisation of the concept of a relational model for modal logic. Theoria , vol. 36 , pp. 331–335.S. K. Thomason - 1973 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 38 (3):520.
  38. DA Gillies, Frege, Dedekind and Peano on the Foundations of Arithmetic Reviewed by.S. K. Thomason - 1984 - Philosophy in Review 4 (3):111-113.
  39.  35
    Modal operators and functional completeness, II.S. K. Thomason - 1977 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 42 (3):391-399.
  40.  11
    Noncompactness in Propositional Modal Logic.S. K. Thomason, Kit Fine, Martin Gerson & Martin Sebastian Gerson - 1983 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 48 (2):488-495.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  21
    Review: J. R. Shoenfield, Ernest Nagel, Patrick Suppes, Alfred Tarski, Some Applications of Degrees. [REVIEW]S. K. Thomason - 1972 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 37 (3):610-610.
  42.  62
    Humean Causation and Kim’s Theory of Events.Terence Horgan - 1980 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 10 (4):663 - 679.
    In recent years Jaegwon Kim has propounded and elaborated an influential theory of events. He takes an event to be the exemplification of an empirical property by a concrete object at a time. He also has proposed and endorsed a version of the “Humean” tradition concerning causation: the view that causal relations between concrete events depend upon general "covering laws." But although his explication of the covering-law conception of causation seems quite natural within the framework of his (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  43.  14
    Review: David Makinson, Some Embedding Theorems for Modal Logic. [REVIEW]S. K. Thomason - 1974 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 39 (2):351-351.
  44.  30
    J. R. Shoenheld. Some applications of degrees. Logic, methodology and philosophy of science, Proceedings of the 1960 International Congress, edited by Ernest Nagel, Patrick Suppes, and Alfred Tarski, Stanford University Press, Stanford, Calif., 1962, pp. 56–59. [REVIEW]S. K. Thomason - 1972 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 37 (3):610.
  45.  49
    C. I. Lewis’s Theory of Meaning and Theory of Value. [REVIEW]B. R. S. - 1978 - Review of Metaphysics 32 (1):158-158.
    This examination of C. I. Lewis’s theory of meaning and theory of value argues that while Lewis’s own statement of the connection between them is inadequate, a way can be shown which allows for a connection between the two. The amount of space devoted to this endeavor is even briefer than the length of the book indicates, for the last nineteen pages consist of an appendix on Quine’s theory of meaning, and there are numbered but blank pages (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  17
    On logic and the theory of science.Jean Cavaillès - 2021 - New York, NY: Sequence Press. Edited by Knox Peden & Robin Mackay.
    In this short, dense essay, Jean Cavaillès evaluates philosophical efforts to determine the origin - logical or ontological - of scientific thought, arguing that, rather than seeking to found science in original intentional acts, a priori meanings, or foundational logical relations, any adequate theory must involve a history of the concept. Cavaillès insists on a historical epistemology that is conceptual rather than phenomenological, and a logic that is dialectical rather than transcendental. His famous call (cited by Foucault) to abandon (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47.  57
    Peter Aczel. Quantifiers, games and inductive definitions. Proceedings of the Third Scandinavian Logic Symposium, edited by Stig Kanger, Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics, vol. 82, North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam and Oxford, and American Elsevier Publishing Company, Inc., New York, 1975, pp. 1–14. - Kit Fine. Some connections between elementary and modal logic. Proceedings of the Third Scandinavian Logic Symposium, edited by Stig Kanger, Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics, vol. 82, North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam and Oxford, and American Elsevier Publishing Company, Inc., New York, 1975, pp. 15–31. - Bengt Hansson and Peter Gärdenfors. Filtations and the finite frame property in Boolean semantics. Proceedings of the Third Scandinavian Logic Symposium, edited by Stig Kanger, Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics, vol. 82, North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam and Oxford, and American Elsevier Publishing Compa. [REVIEW]S. K. Thomason - 1978 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 43 (2):373-376.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. D.A. Gillies, Frege, Dedekind And Peano On The Foundations Of Arithmetic. [REVIEW]S. Thomason - 1984 - Philosophy in Review 4:111-113.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  24
    Review: C. E. M. Yates, John N. Crossley, Recursively Enumerable Degrees and the Degrees Less Than $0^{(1)}$. [REVIEW]S. K. Thomason - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (4):589-589.
  50.  19
    Titgemeyer Dieter. Untersuchungen über die Struktur des Kleene-Postschen Halbverbandes der Grade der rekursiven Unlösbarkeit. Archiv für mathematische Logik und Grundlagenforschung, vol. 8 no. 1–2 , pp. 45–62. [REVIEW]S. K. Thomason - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (1):155-156.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 994