12 found
Order:
Disambiguations
Neil Thomason [12]Neil Ryland Thomason [1]
See also
Neil Thomason
University of Melbourne
  1.  24
    60% Proof Lakatos, Proof, and Paraconsistency.Graham Priest & Neil Thomason - 2007 - Australasian Journal of Logic 5:89-100.
    Imre Lakatos’ Proofs and Refutations is a book well known to those who work in the philosophy of mathematics, though it is perhaps not widely referred to. Its general thrust is out of tenor with the foundationalist perspective that has dominated work in the philosophy of mathematics since the early years of the 20th century. It seems to us, though, that the book contains striking insights into the nature of proof, and the purpose of this paper is to explore and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  2. Bayesians sometimes cannot ignore even very implausible theories (even ones that have not yet been thought of).Branden Fitelson & Neil Thomason - 2008 - Australasian Journal of Logic 6:25-36.
    In applying Bayes’s theorem to the history of science, Bayesians sometimes assume – often without argument – that they can safely ignore very implausible theories. This assumption is false, both in that it can seriously distort the history of science as well as the mathematics and the applicability of Bayes’s theorem. There are intuitively very plausible counter-examples. In fact, one can ignore very implausible or unknown theories only if at least one of two conditions is satisfied: (i) one is certain (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  3. Could Lakatos, even with Zahar's criterion for novel fact, evaluate the copernican research programme?Neil Thomason - 1992 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 43 (2):161-200.
    Why did Copernicus's research programme supersede Ptolemy's?’, Lakatos and Zahar argued that, on Zahar's criterion for ‘novel fact’, Copernican theory was objectively scientifically superior to Ptolemaic theory. They are mistaken, Lakatos and Zahar applied Zahar's criterion to ‘a historical thought-experiment’—fictional rather than real history. Further, in their fictional history, they compared Copernicus to Eudoxus rather than Ptolemy, ignored Tycho Brahe, and did not consider facts that would be novel for geostatic theories. When Zahar's criterion is applied to real history, the (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  4. The power of ARCHED hypotheses: Feyerabend's Galileo as a closet rationalist.Neil Thomason - 1994 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45 (1):255-264.
  5.  27
    Some problems with Chisholm and Potter's solution to the paradox of analysis.Neil Thomason - 1992 - Metaphilosophy 23 (1-2):132-138.
  6.  48
    Making Student Groups Work.Neil Thomason - 1990 - Teaching Philosophy 13 (2):111-125.
  7.  25
    Wittgenstein provided no evidence for the claim that there is not ?One thing in common which makes us use the same word for all? Games.Neil Thomason - 1991 - Metaphilosophy 22 (4):320-323.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  17
    Elk Theories—A Galilean Strategy for Validating a New Scientific Discovery.Neil Thomason - 1996 - In P. Riggs (ed.), Natural Kinds, Laws of Nature and Scientific Methodology. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 123--144.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  76
    Philosophy Discussions With Less B.S.Neil Thomason - 1995 - Teaching Philosophy 18 (1):15-30.
    The purpose of this paper is to explore various pedagogical tools that facilitate productive and effective classroom discussion in philosophy courses. Adequate preparation for classroom discussion is not merely a matter of doing the assigned reading, but requires students to take careful notes on the reading, to read the text systematically, and to compose questions. Instead of teaching students remedial reading skills, the author suggests a series of assignments (in and outside of class) that help students develop critical reading skills. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10.  2
    Science and Relativism: Some Key Controversies in the Philosophy of Science.Neil Thomason - 1993 - Philosophical Books 34 (4):249-253.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  34
    Sherlock Holmes, Galileo, and the Missing History of Science.Neil Thomason - 1994 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1994:323 - 333.
    There is a common (although not universal) claim among historians and philosophers that Copernican theory predicted the phases of Venus. This claim ignores a prominant feature of the writings of, among others, Copernicus, Galileo and Kepler-the possibility that Venus might be self illuminating or translucent. I propose that such over-simplifications of the history of science emerges from "psychological predictivism", the tendency to infer from "E is good evidence for H" to "H predicts E." If this explanation is correct, then in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  4
    Small is Beautiful.Neil Thomason - 1990 - Thinking: The Journal of Philosophy for Children 9 (1):38-41.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark