Results for ' Crisis Standards of Care'

999 found
Order:
  1.  11
    Crisis Standards of Care—More Than Just a Thought Experiment?Anuj B. Mehta & Matthew K. Wynia - 2021 - Hastings Center Report 51 (5):53-55.
    Hastings Center Report, Volume 51, Issue 5, Page 53-55, September‐October 2021.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  14
    The University of California Crisis Standards of Care: Public Reasoning for Socially Responsible Medicine.Alex Rajczi, Judith Daar, Aaron Kheriaty & Cyrus Dastur - 2021 - Hastings Center Report 51 (5):30-41.
    Hastings Center Report, Volume 51, Issue 5, Page 30-41, September‐October 2021.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  3.  33
    Eliminating Categorical Exclusion Criteria in Crisis Standards of Care Frameworks.Catherine L. Auriemma, Ashli M. Molinero, Amy J. Houtrow, Govind Persad, Douglas B. White & Scott D. Halpern - 2020 - American Journal of Bioethics 20 (7):28-36.
    During public health crises including the COVID-19 pandemic, resource scarcity and contagion risks may require health systems to shift—to some degree—from a usual clinical ethic, focused on the well-being of individual patients, to a public health ethic, focused on population health. Many triage policies exist that fall under the legal protections afforded by “crisis standards of care,” but they have key differences. We critically appraise one of the most fundamental differences among policies, namely the use of criteria (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  4. Disability Rights as a Necessary Framework for Crisis Standards of Care and the Future of Health Care.Laura Guidry-Grimes, Katie Savin, Joseph A. Stramondo, Joel Michael Reynolds, Marina Tsaplina, Teresa Blankmeyer Burke, Angela Ballantyne, Eva Feder Kittay, Devan Stahl, Jackie Leach Scully, Rosemarie Garland-Thomson, Anita Tarzian, Doron Dorfman & Joseph J. Fins - 2020 - Hastings Center Report 50 (3):28-32.
    In this essay, we suggest practical ways to shift the framing of crisis standards of care toward disability justice. We elaborate on the vision statement provided in the 2010 Institute of Medicine (National Academy of Medicine) “Summary of Guidance for Establishing Crisis Standards of Care for Use in Disaster Situations,” which emphasizes fairness; equitable processes; community and provider engagement, education, and communication; and the rule of law. We argue that interpreting these elements through disability (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  5.  51
    Respecting Disability Rights — Toward Improved Crisis Standards of Care.Michelle M. Mello, Govind Persad & Douglas B. White - 2020 - New England Journal of Medicine (5):DOI: 10.1056/NEJMp2011997.
    We propose six guideposts that states and hospitals should follow to respect disability rights when designing policies for the allocation of scarce, lifesaving medical treatments. Four relate to criteria for decisions. First, do not use categorical exclusions, especially ones based on disability or diagnosis. Second, do not use perceived quality of life. Third, use hospital survival and near-term prognosis (e.g., death expected within a few years despite treatment) but not long-term life expectancy. Fourth, when patients who use ventilators in their (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  6.  18
    The theoretical and practical arguments against the unilateral withdrawal of life‐sustaining treatment during crisis standards of care: Does the Knobe effect apply to unilateral withdrawal?Fabien Maldonado & Michael B. Gill - 2022 - Bioethics 36 (9):964-969.
    Some argue that it is ethically justifiable to unilaterally withdraw life‐sustaining treatment during crisis standards of care without the patient's consent in order to reallocate it to another patient with a better chance of survival. This justification has been supported by two lines of argument: the equivalence thesis and the rule of the double effect. We argue that there are theoretical issues with the first and practical ones with the second, as supported by an experiment aimed at (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  18
    Ethics of Extracorporeal Membrane Oxygenation under Conventional and Crisis Standards of Care.William F. Parker, Mark Siegler & Gina M. Piscitello - 2022 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 33 (1):13-22.
    Extracorporeal membrane oxygenation (ECMO) is a form of life support for cardiac and/or pulmonary failure with unique ethical challenges compared to other forms of life support. Ethical challenges with ECMO exist when conventional standards of care apply, and are exacerbated during periods of absolute ECMO scarcity when “crisis standards of care” are instituted. When conventional standards of care apply, we propose that it is ethically permissible to withhold placing patients on ECMO for reasons (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  8.  22
    Legal Briefing: Crisis Standards of Care and Legal Protections during Disasters and Emergencies.Thaddeus M. Pope & Mitchell F. Palazzo - 2010 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 21 (4):358-367.
    This article outlines current safe harbors in the law for healthcare practitioners who work in a disaster setting. It reviews available legal protection in crisis situations with respect to the Emergency Medical Treatment and Labor Act (EMTALA), criminal liability, and licensure.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  15
    Revisiting Legal Foundations of Crisis Standards of Care.James G. Hodge - 2020 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 48 (1):221-224.
  10.  21
    Practical, Ethical, and Legal Challenges Underlying Crisis Standards of Care.James G. Hodge, Dan Hanfling & Tia P. Powell - 2013 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 41 (s1):50-55.
    Public health emergencies invariably entail difficult decisions among medical and emergency first responders about how to allocate essential, scarce resources. To the extent that these critical choices can profoundly impact community and individual health outcomes, achieving consistency in how these decisions are executed is valuable. Since the terrorist attacks on September 11, 2001, however, public and private sector allocation plans and decisions have followed uncertain paths. Lacking empirical evidence and national input, various entities and actors have proffered multifarious approaches on (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  11.  17
    Standard Racism: Trying to Use “Crisis Standards of Care” in the COVID-19 Pandemic.Sondra S. Crosby & George J. Annas - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics 21 (8):1-3.
    Lowering the standard of care in a pandemic is a recipe for inferior care and discrimination. Wealthy white patients will continue to get “standard of care” medicine, while the poor and racial mino...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  18
    “We’re Not Ready, But I Don’t Think You’re Ever Ready.” Clinician Perspectives on Implementation of Crisis Standards of Care.Elizabeth Chuang, Pablo A. Cuartas, Tia Powell & Michelle Ng Gong - 2020 - AJOB Empirical Bioethics 11 (3):148-159.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  13.  11
    The Crisis in Standards of Care.Gregory E. Kaebnick - 2021 - Hastings Center Report 51 (5):2-2.
    Hastings Center Report, Volume 51, Issue 5, Page 2-2, September‐October 2021.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  10
    A Real-World Ethical Analysis of Contingency Measures Enacted for Crisis Standards of Care during the COVID-19 Pandemic.Joyeeta G. Dastidar - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics 21 (8):22-24.
    The Nuclear Threat Initiative focuses on preventing catastrophes related to weapons of mass destruction, with a wide range of attacks including nuclear, biologic, radiologic, chemical and cyb...
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  17
    Reflections on New Evidence on Crisis Standards of Care in the COVID-19 Pandemic.Mark R. Mercurio, Mark D. Siegel, John Hughes, Ernest D. Moritz, Jennifer Kapo, Jennifer L. Herbst, Sarah C. Hull, Karen Jubanyik, Katherine Kraschel, Lauren E. Ferrante, Lori Bruce, Stephen R. Latham & Benjamin Tolchin - 2021 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 32 (4):358-360.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  7
    The Lifeboat at World's End: Moving Beyond Crisis Standards of Care.James E. Black - 2022 - Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 65 (4):559-568.
    ABSTRACT:It may be too late to avoid the climate crisis, likely to be humanity's most expensive, widespread, and enduring catastrophe. This is a qualitatively different kind of catastrophe, in which increased costs, decreased revenue, and no possibility of bailout force communities to harshly cut budgets, especially in health care. Little is known about making such brutal cuts fair or efficient, nor how to help the public accept them. The crisis presents an opportunity for bioethicists to play a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  22
    Defending the Inclusion of Categorical Exclusion Criteria in Crisis Standard of Care Frameworks.Janet Malek - 2020 - American Journal of Bioethics 20 (7):156-158.
    Volume 20, Issue 7, July 2020, Page 156-158.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  23
    Rationing Crisis: Bogus Standards of Care Unmasked by Covid-19.George J. Annas - 2020 - American Journal of Bioethics 20 (7):167-169.
    Volume 20, Issue 7, July 2020, Page 167-169.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  36
    Can China’s ‘standard of care’ for COVID-19 be replicated in Europe?Vera Lucia Raposo - 2020 - Journal of Medical Ethics 46 (7):451-454.
    The Director-General of the WHO has suggested that China’s approach to the COVID-19 crisis could be the standard of care for global epidemics. However, as remarkable as the Chinese strategy might be, it cannot be replicated in other countries and certainly not in Europe. In Europe, there is a distribution of power between the European Union and its member states. In contrast, China’s political power is concentrated in the central government. This enables it to take immediate measures that (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20.  47
    In Defense of (Some) Altered Standards of Care for Ebola Infections in Developed Countries.Philip M. Rosoff - 2015 - HEC Forum 27 (1):1-9.
    The current outbreak of Ebola virus infection in West Africa continues to spread. Several patients have now been treated in the United States and preparations are being made for more. Because of the strict isolation required for their care, questions have been raised about what diagnostic and therapeutic interventions should be available. I discuss the ethical challenges associated with caring for patients in strict isolation and personnel wearing bulky protective gear with reduced dexterity and flexibility, the limitations this may (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  21.  16
    Mind the gap please: ethical considerations in the transition of virtual consultations from crisis to usual care.Tania Moerenhout - 2022 - Journal of Medical Ethics 48 (1):36-37.
    Although telepsychiatry consultations have been tried and tested for several years, at least in relatively limited numbers and settings, the current COVID-19 pandemic has caused an exponential increase in their application. Even as lockdown restrictions were lifted and a return to face-to-face consultations was possible, many practitioners and patients decided to uphold teleconsultations for some or a large part of their interactions. This was mostly driven by the exceptional circumstances of the pandemic, as ongoing safety concerns, the need for PPE (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  22
    Our Next Pandemic Ethics Challenge? Allocating “Normal” Health Care Services.Jeremy R. Garrett, Leslie Ann McNolty, Ian D. Wolfe & John D. Lantos - 2020 - Hastings Center Report 50 (3):79-80.
    The pandemic creates unprecedented challenges to society and to health care systems around the world. Like all crises, these provide a unique opportunity to rethink the fundamental limiting assumptions and institutional inertia of our established systems. These inertial assumptions have obscured deeply rooted problems in health care and deflected attempts to address them. As hospitals begin to welcome all patients back, they should resist the temptation to go back to business as usual. Instead, they should retain the more (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  6
    Reciprocity and Liability Protections during the Covid‐19 Pandemic.Valerie Gutmann Koch & Diane E. Hoffmann - 2021 - Hastings Center Report 51 (3):5-7.
    During the Covid‐19 pandemic, as resources dwindled, clinicians, health care institutions, and policymakers have expressed concern about potential legal liability for following crisis standards of care (CSC) plans. Although there is no robust empirical research to demonstrate that liability protections actually influence physician behavior, we argue that limited liability protections for health care professionals who follow established CSC plans may instead be justified by reliance on the principle of reciprocity. Expecting physicians to do something they (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24. Against Personal Ventilator Reallocation.Joel Michael Reynolds, Laura Guidry-Grimes & Katie Savin - 2020 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 30 (2):272-284.
    The COVID-19 (Coronavirus disease of 2019) pandemic has led to intense conversations about ventilator allocation and reallocation during a crisis standard of care. Multiple voices in the media and multiple state guidelines mention reallocation as a possibility. Drawing upon a range of neuroscientific, phenomenological, ethical, and sociopolitical considerations, the authors argue that taking away someone’s personal ventilator is a direct assault on their bodily and social integrity. They conclude that personal ventilators should not be part of reallocation pools (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  25. The Complex Relationship Between Disability Discrimination and Frailty Scoring.Joel Michael Reynolds, Charles E. Binkley & Andrew Shuman - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics 21 (11):74-76.
    In "Frailty Triage: Is Rationing Intensive Medical Treatment on the Grounds of Frailty Ethical?," Wilkinson (2021) argues that the use of frailty scores in ICU triage does not necessarily involve discrimination on the basis of disability. In support of this argument, he claims, “it is not the disability per se that the score is measuring – rather it is the underlying physiological and physical vulnerability." While we appreciate the attention Wilkinson explicitly pays to disability in this piece, we find the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  20
    When Is Age Choosing Ageist Discrimination?Teneille R. Brown, Leslie P. Francis & James Tabery - 2020 - Hastings Center Report 51 (1):13-15.
    When the Covid‐19 pandemic reached the United States in spring 2020, many states and hospitals announced crisis standards of care plans that used age as a categorical exclusion criterion. Such age choosing was quickly flagged as discriminatory, and so some states and hospitals shifted to embedding age as a tiebreaker deeper in their plans. Different rationales were given for using age as a tiebreaker: that younger patients were more likely to survive than older patients, that saving younger (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  12
    The draw of the few: the challenge of crisis guidelines for extremely scarce resources.Jacob M. Appel - 2022 - Journal of Medical Ethics 48 (12):1032-1036.
    The COVID-19 pandemic has focused considerable attention on crisis standards of care (CSCs). Most public CSCs at present are effective tools for allocating scarce but not uncommon resources (like ventilators and dialysis machines). However, a different set of challenges arise with regard to extremely scarce resources (ESRs), where the number of patients in need may exceed the availability of the intervention by magnitudes of hundreds or thousands. Using the allocation of extracorporeal membrane oxygenation machines as a case (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  35
    Moral distress in nurses caring for patients with Covid-19.Henry J. Silverman, Raya Elfadel Kheirbek, Gyasi Moscou-Jackson & Jenni Day - 2021 - Nursing Ethics 28 (7-8):1137-1164.
    Background:Moral distress occurs when constraints prevent healthcare providers from acting in accordance with their core moral values to provide good patient care. The experience of moral distress in nurses might be magnified during the current Covid-19 pandemic.Objective:To explore causes of moral distress in nurses caring for Covid-19 patients and identify strategies to enhance their moral resiliency.Research design:A qualitative study using a qualitative content analysis of focus group discussions and in-depth interviews. We purposively sampled 31 nurses caring for Covid-19 patients (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  29.  12
    The COVID-19 Crisis and Clinical Ethics in New York City.Kenneth M. Prager & Joseph J. Fins - 2020 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 31 (3):228-232.
    The COVID-19 pandemic that struck New York City in the spring of 2020 was a natural experiment for the clinical ethics services of NewYork-Presbyterian (NYP). Two distinct teams at NYP’s flagship academic medical centers—at NYP/ Columbia University Medical Center (Columbia) and NYP/ Weill Cornell Medical Center (Weill Cornell)—were faced with the same pandemic and operated under the same institutional rules. Each campus used time as an heuristic to analyze our collective response. The Columbia team compares consults during the pandemic with (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  30.  11
    Staffing crisis capacity: a different approach to healthcare resource allocation for a different type of scarce resource.Catherine R. Butler, Laura B. Webster & Douglas S. Diekema - forthcoming - Journal of Medical Ethics.
    Severe staffing shortages have emerged as a prominent threat to maintaining usual standards of care during the COVID-2019 pandemic. In dire settings of crisis capacity, healthcare systems assume the ethical duty to maximise aggregate population-level benefit of existing resources. To this end, existing plans for rationing mechanical ventilators and intensive care unit beds in crisis capacity focus on selecting individual patients who are most likely to survive and prioritising these patients to receive scarce resources. However, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Standard of Care, Institutional Obligations, and Distributive Justice.Douglas MacKay - 2015 - Bioethics 29 (4):352-359.
    The problem of standard of care in clinical research concerns the level of treatment that investigators must provide to subjects in clinical trials. Commentators often formulate answers to this problem by appealing to two distinct types of obligations: professional obligations and natural duties. In this article, I investigate whether investigators also possess institutional obligations that are directly relevant to the problem of standard of care, that is, those obligations a person has because she occupies a particular institutional role. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  32.  14
    Fatphobia and Inequities in Scarce Resource Allocation: Reflections on CSC Planning Two Years Later.Madeline Ward - 2022 - International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 15 (1):100-101.
    Crisis standards of care are a significant change in the standard level of medical care that can be given compared to normal healthcare operations. CSC are implemented when a healthcare facility is overrun due to catastrophic events like earthquakes, or in the case of SARS-CoV-2, a global pandemic. Especially in disasters, resources like hospital beds, pharmaceuticals, and staff become stretched thin, and facilities must adapt their allocation strategies for distributing scarce resources. Inevitably, a question arises: How (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  10
    Standard of Care, Institutional Obligations, and Distributive Justice.Douglas MacKay - 2013 - Bioethics 29 (4):262-273.
    The problem of standard of care in clinical research concerns the level of treatment that investigators must provide to subjects in clinical trials. Commentators often formulate answers to this problem by appealing to two distinct types of obligations: professional obligations and natural duties. In this article, I investigate whether investigators also possess institutional obligations that are directly relevant to the problem of standard of care, that is, those obligations a person has because she occupies a particular institutional role. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  34. The Standard of Care in Medical Negligence—Moving on from Bolam?Harvey Teff - 1998 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 18 (3):473-484.
    Historically, the standard of care in medical negligence provided considerable scope for external evaluation of clinical judgment. Under the Bolam test, however, determining the standard was seen by the courts as essentially a matter for the medical profession, to be resolved by expert testimony with minimal court scrutiny. In recent years, courts have become more willing to probe such testimony and challenge the credibility of medical experts, although they would very rarely override clinical judgment. The House of Lords' decision (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  35.  42
    The standard of care debate: the Declaration of Helsinki versus the international consensus opinion.R. K. Lie - 2004 - Journal of Medical Ethics 30 (2):190-193.
    The World Medical Association’s revised Declaration of Helsinki endorses the view that all trial participants in every country are entitled to the worldwide best standard of care. In this paper the authors show that this requirement has been rejected by every national and international committee that has examined this issue. They argue that the consensus view now holds that it is ethically permissible, in some circumstances, to provide research participants less than the worldwide best care. Finally, the authors (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  36.  12
    Acknowledging the Burdens of ‘Blackness’.Nneka O. Sederstrom & Jada Wiggleton-Little - 2021 - HEC Forum 33 (1-2):19-33.
    The novel coronavirus of 2019 exposed, in an undeniable way, the severity of racial inequities in America’s healthcare system. As the urgency of the pandemic grew, administrators, clinicians, and ethicists became concerned with upholding the ethical principle of “most lives saved” by re-visiting crisis standards of care and triage protocols. Yet a colorblind, race-neutral approach to “most lives saved” is inherently inequitable because it reflects the normality and invisibility of ‘whiteness’ while simultaneously disregarding the burdens of ‘Blackness’. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  37.  48
    What Has Covid‐19 Exposed in Bioethics? Four Myths.Susan M. Wolf - 2021 - Hastings Center Report 51 (3):3-4.
    The Covid‐19 pandemic has exposed four myths in bioethics. First, the flood of bioethics publications on how to allocate scarce resources in crisis conditions has assumed authorities would declare the onset of crisis standards of care, yet few have done so. This leaves guidelines in limbo and patients unprotected. Second, the pandemic's realities have exploded traditional boundaries between clinical, research, and public health ethics, requiring bioethics to face the interdigitation of learning, doing, and allocating. Third, without (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  28
    With crisis comes opportunity: Building ethical competencies in light of COVID-19.Alisha Desai, C. Lankford & J. Schwartz - 2020 - Ethics and Behavior 30 (6):401-413.
    ABSTRACT The emergence of the coronavirus disease 2019 pandemic has wide-ranging implications for the field of professional psychology. As clinical practice has rapidly adapted to ensure continuity of care, doctoral students have encountered unique opportunities for ethics-related competency development across practicum training settings. This article discusses the relevant American Psychological Association Ethics Code standards and additional ethical considerations facing trainees as they navigate their foundational clinical experiences and develop as professional psychologists in light of a pandemic.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  39.  16
    Customary Standard of Care: A Challenge for Regulation and Practice.Sandra H. Johnson - 2013 - Hastings Center Report 43 (6):9-10.
    Law wrangles with setting and applying standards for the practice of medicine in many different arenas. One of the most prominent is medical malpractice litigation in which the trial process examines a physician's performance and measures it against the standard of care. The profession's prevailing custom, with some substantial tolerance for “respectable minority” views, has been the gold standard for scrutinizing physician practice and treatment decisions in the malpractice context. Using the profession's custom as the measure against which (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  40.  35
    The standard of care debate: against the myth of an "international consensus opinion".U. Schuklenk - 2004 - Journal of Medical Ethics 30 (2):194-197.
    It is argued by Lie et al in the current issue of the Journal of Medical Ethics that an international consensus opinion has formed on the issue of standards of care in clinical trials undertaken in developing countries. This opinion, so they argue, rejects the Declaration of Helsinki’s traditional view on this matter. They propose furthermore that the Declaration of Helsinki has lost its moral authority in the controversy in research ethics. Although the latter conclusion is supported by (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  41.  53
    Defining standard of care in the developing world: The intersection of international research ethics and health systems analysis.Adnan A. Hyder & Liza Dawson - 2005 - Developing World Bioethics 5 (2):142–152.
    ABSTRACT In recent years there has been intense debate regarding the level of medical care provided to ‘standard care’ control groups in clinical trials in developing countries, particularly when the research sponsors come from wealthier countries. The debate revolves around the issue of how to define a standard of medical care in a country in which many people are not receiving the best methods of medical care available in other settings. In this paper, we argue that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  42.  19
    Defining Standard of Care in the Developing World: The Intersection of International Research Ethics and Health Systems Analysis.Liza Dawson Adnan A. Hyder - 2005 - Developing World Bioethics 5 (2):142-152.
    ABSTRACT In recent years there has been intense debate regarding the level of medical care provided to ‘standard care’ control groups in clinical trials in developing countries, particularly when the research sponsors come from wealthier countries. The debate revolves around the issue of how to define a standard of medical care in a country in which many people are not receiving the best methods of medical care available in other settings. In this paper, we argue that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  43.  61
    Triage and justice in an unjust pandemic: ethical allocation of scarce medical resources in the setting of racial and socioeconomic disparities.Benjamin Tolchin, Sarah C. Hull & Katherine Kraschel - 2021 - Journal of Medical Ethics 47 (3):200-202.
    Shortages of life-saving medical resources caused by COVID-19 have prompted hospitals, healthcare systems, and governmentsto develop crisis standards of care, including 'triage protocols' to potentially ration medical supplies during the public health emergency. At the same time, the pandemic has highlighted and exacerbated racial, ethnic, and socioeconomic health disparities that together constitute a form of structural racism. These disparities pose a critical ethical challenge in developing fair triage systems that will maximize lives saved without perpetuating systemic inequities. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44. Equipoise, standard of care, and consent: Responding to the authorisation of new COVID-19 treatments in randomised controlled trials.Soren Holm, Jonathan Lewis & Rafael Dal-Ré - 2022 - Journal of Medical Ethics:1-6.
    In response to the COVID-19 pandemic, large-scale research and pharmaceutical regulatory processes have proceeded at a dramatically increased pace with new and effective, evidence-based COVID-19 interventions rapidly making their way into the clinic. However, the swift generation of high-quality evidence and the efficient processing of regulatory authorisation have given rise to more specific and complex versions of well-known research ethics issues. In this paper, we identify three such issues by focusing on the authorisation of Molnupiravir, a novel antiviral medicine aimed (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  37
    Utilitarian Principlism as a Framework for Crisis Healthcare Ethics.Laura Vearrier & Carrie M. Henderson - 2021 - HEC Forum 33 (1):45-60.
    This paper introduces the model of Utilitarian Principlism as a framework for crisis healthcare ethics. In modern Western medicine, during non-crisis times, principlism provides the four guiding principles in biomedical ethics—autonomy, nonmaleficence, beneficence, and justice; autonomy typically emerges as the decisive principle. The physician–patient relationship is a deontological construct in which the physician’s primary duty is to the individual patient and the individual patient is paramount. For this reason, we term the non-crisis ethical framework that guides modern (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  46.  56
    The Credit Crisis and the Moral Responsibility of Professionals in Finance.Johan J. Graafland & Bert W. Ven - 2011 - Journal of Business Ethics 103 (4):605-619.
    Starting from MacIntyre’s virtue ethics, we investigate several codes of conduct of banks to identify the type of virtues that are needed to realize their mission. Based on this analysis, we define three core virtues: honesty, due care, and accuracy. We compare and contrast these codes of conduct with the actual behavior of banks that led to the credit crisis and find that in some cases banks did not behave according to the moral standards they set themselves. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  47.  17
    Embracing the wild profusion: A Foucauldian analysis of the impact of healthcare standardization on nursing knowledge and practice.Allie Slemon - 2018 - Nursing Philosophy 19 (4):e12215.
    Standardization has emerged as the dominant principle guiding the organization and provision of healthcare, with standards resultantly shaping how nurses conceptualize and deliver patient care. Standardization has been critiqued as homogenizing diverse patient experiences and diminishing nurses’ skills and critical thinking; however, there has been limited examination of the philosophical implications of standardization for nursing knowledge and practice. In this manuscript, I draw on Foucault's philosophy of order and categorization to inform an analysis of the consequences of healthcare (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48.  14
    Equipoise, standard of care and consent: responding to the authorisation of new COVID-19 treatments in randomised controlled trials.Soren Holm, Jonathan Lewis & Rafael Dal-Ré - 2023 - Journal of Medical Ethics 49 (7):465-470.
    In response to the COVID-19 pandemic, large-scale research and pharmaceutical regulatory processes have proceeded at a dramatically increased pace with new and effective, evidence-based COVID-19 interventions rapidly making their way into the clinic. However, the swift generation of high-quality evidence and the efficient processing of regulatory authorisation have given rise to more specific and complex versions of well-known research ethics issues. In this paper, we identify three such issues by focusing on the authorisation of molnupiravir, a novel antiviral medicine aimed (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  20
    Introducing Standards of Care in the Commercialization of Nanotechnology.Vivian Weil - 2006 - International Journal of Applied Philosophy 20 (2):205-213.
    While the entire “wish-list” of expected benefits from nanotechnology has received little scrutiny in the U.S. with regard to issues of social justice, ethics specialists and social scientists are beginning to focus on the responsible conduct of actual nano research and development (R&D) in government, commercial, and academic institutions. In view of the current rush to commercialization, the rush by universities to “get aboard,” and the importance of public trust, it is essential to investigate strategies to promote responsible conduct in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  50
    On pandemics and the duty to care: whose duty? who cares?Carly Ruderman, C. Shawn Tracy, Cécile M. Bensimon, Mark Bernstein, Laura Hawryluck, Randi Z. Shaul & Ross E. G. Upshur - 2006 - BMC Medical Ethics 7 (1):5.
    BackgroundAs a number of commentators have noted, SARS exposed the vulnerabilities of our health care systems and governance structures. Health care professionals (HCPs) and hospital systems that bore the brunt of the SARS outbreak continue to struggle with the aftermath of the crisis. Indeed, HCPs – both in clinical care and in public health – were severely tested by SARS. Unprecedented demands were placed on their skills and expertise, and their personal commitment to their profession was (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
1 — 50 / 999