Results for 'sad music'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. On the Value of Sad Music.Mario Attie-Picker, Tara Venkatesan, George E. Newman & Joshua Knobe - 2024 - The Journal of Aesthetic Education 58 (1):46-65.
    Many people appear to attach great value to sad music. But why? One way to gain insight into this question is to turn away from music and look instead at why people value sad conversations. In the case of conversations, the answer seems to be that expressing sadness creates a sense of genuine connection. We propose that sad music can also have this type of value. Listening to a sad song can give one a sense of genuine (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  44
    The pleasures of sad music: a systematic review.Matthew E. Sachs, Antonio Damasio & Assal Habibi - 2015 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 9:146300.
    Sadness is generally seen as a negative emotion, a response to distressing and adverse situations. In an aesthetic context, however, sadness is often associated with some degree of pleasure, as suggested by the ubiquity and popularity, throughout history, of music, plays, films and paintings with a sad content. Here, we focus on the fact that music regarded as sad is often experienced as pleasurable. Compared to other art forms, music has an exceptional ability to evoke a wide-range (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  3.  31
    Enjoying Sad Music: Paradox or Parallel Processes?Emery Schubert - 2016 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 10.
  4.  7
    Does sad music make one sad? An ethnographic perspective.Peter Manuel - 2005 - Contemporary Aesthetics 3.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Why listen to sad music if it makes one feel sad?Stephen Davies - 1997 - In Jenefer Robinson (ed.), Music & Meaning. Cornell University Press.
  6.  33
    The Pleasure Evoked by Sad Music Is Mediated by Feelings of Being Moved.Jonna K. Vuoskoski & Tuomas Eerola - 2017 - Frontiers in Psychology 8.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  7.  48
    Being Moved by Unfamiliar Sad Music Is Associated with High Empathy.Tuomas Eerola, Jonna K. Vuoskoski & Hannu Kautiainen - 2016 - Frontiers in Psychology 7.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  8.  29
    On the Enjoyment of Sad Music: Pleasurable Compassion Theory and the Role of Trait Empathy.David Huron & Jonna K. Vuoskoski - 2020 - Frontiers in Psychology 11.
  9.  92
    Sad Songs Say So Much: The Paradoxical Pleasures of Sad Music.Laura Sizer - 2019 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 77 (3):255-266.
    Listening to music can be an intensely moving experience. Many people love music in part because of its power to alter or amplify their moods, and turn to music for inspiration, comfort, or therapy. It is a puzzle, then, why many of us spend so much time listening to sad music. If music can influence our moods, and assuming that most people would prefer to be happy not sad, why would we choose to listen to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  10. Musical scaffolding and the pleasure of sad music: Comment on “An Integrative Review of the Enjoyment of Sadness Associated with Music".Joel Krueger - forthcoming - Physics of Life Reviews.
    Why is listening to sad music pleasurable? Eerola et al. convincingly argue that we should adopt an integrative framework — encompassing biological, psycho-social, and cultural levels of explanation — to answer this question. I agree. The authors have done a great service in providing the outline of such an integrative account. But in their otherwise rich discussion of the psycho-social level of engagements with sad music, they say little about the phenomenology of such experiences — including features that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  38
    Influence of trait empathy on the emotion evoked by sad music and on the preference for it.Ai Kawakami & Kenji Katahira - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  12.  6
    Where is “The Sadness” in Sad Music?:悲しい曲のどこが「悲しい」のか?.Tohru Genka - 2018 - Kagaku Tetsugaku 51 (2):65-82.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  46
    Happy, sad, scary and peaceful musical excerpts for research on emotions.Sandrine Vieillard, Isabelle Peretz, Nathalie Gosselin, Stéphanie Khalfa, Lise Gagnon & Bernard Bouchard - 2008 - Cognition and Emotion 22 (4):720-752.
    Three experiments were conducted in order to validate 56 musical excerpts that conveyed four intended emotions (happiness, sadness, threat and peacefulness). In Experiment 1, the musical clips were rated in terms of how clearly the intended emotion was portrayed, and for valence and arousal. In Experiment 2, a gating paradigm was used to evaluate the course for emotion recognition. In Experiment 3, a dissimilarity judgement task and multidimensional scaling analysis were used to probe emotional content with no emotional labels. The (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  14.  10
    Analysis and Classification of Music-Induced States of Sadness.Oliver Herdson, Tuomas Eerola & Amir-Homayoun Javadi - 2023 - Emotion Review 15 (2):99-117.
    The enjoyment and pleasure derived from sad music has sparked fascination among researchers due to its seemingly paradoxical nature in producing positive affect. Research is yet to develop a comprehensive understanding of this “paradox.” Contradictory findings have resulted in a great variability within the literature, meaning results and interpretations can be difficult to derive. Consequently, this review collated the current literature, seeking to utilize the variability in the findings to propose a model of differential sad states, providing a means (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  31
    Liking for happy- and sad-sounding music: Effects of exposure.E. Glenn Schellenberg, Isabelle Peretz & Sandrine Vieillard - 2008 - Cognition and Emotion 22 (2):218-237.
    We examined liking for happy- and sad-sounding music as a function of exposure, which varied both in quantity (number of exposures) and in quality (focused or incidental listening). Liking ratings were higher for happy than for sad music after focused listening, but similar after incidental listening. In the incidental condition, liking ratings increased linearly as a function of exposure. In the focused condition, liking ratings were an inverted U-shaped function of exposure, with initial increases in liking (after 2 (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  16.  25
    It's Sad but I Like It: The Neural Dissociation Between Musical Emotions and Liking in Experts and Laypersons.Elvira Brattico, Brigitte Bogert, Vinoo Alluri, Mari Tervaniemi, Tuomas Eerola & Thomas Jacobsen - 2015 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 9.
  17.  26
    Emotional granularity and the musical enjoyment of sadness itself.Nathaniel F. Barrett, Jay Schulkin & Javier Bernacer - 2017 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 40.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18. Is the music really sad?Sidney Zink - 1960 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 19 (2):197-207.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  96
    Musical Contagion.Federico Lauria - 2023 - Encyclopedia.
    Music can contaminate us. Sometimes, listeners perceive music as expressing some emotion (say, sadness), and this elicits the same emotion in them (they feel sad). What is musical contagion? This entry presents the main theories of musical contagion that crystallize around the challenge to the leading theory of emotions as experiences of values. How and why does music contaminate us? Does musical contagion elicit garden variety emotions, such as sadness, joy, and anxiety? Does music contaminate us (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Musical meaning and expression.Stephen Davies - 1994 - Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
    We talk not only of enjoying music, but of understanding it. Music is often taken to have expressive import--and in that sense to have meaning. But what does music mean, and how does it mean? Stephen Davies addresses these questions in this sophisticated and knowledgeable overview of current theories in the philosophy of music. Reviewing and criticizing the aesthetic positions of recent years, he offers a spirited explanation of his own position. Davies considers and rejects in (...)
  21.  87
    Affective Responses to Music: An Affective Science Perspective.Federico Lauria - 2023 - Philosophies 8 (2):16.
    Music has strong emotional powers. How are we to understand affective responses to music? What does music teach us about emotions? Why are musical emotions important? Despite the rich literature in philosophy and the empirical sciences, particularly psychology and neuroscience, little attention has been paid to integrating these approaches. This extensive review aims to redress this imbalance and establish a mutual dialogue between philosophy and the empirical sciences by presenting the main philosophical puzzles from an affective science (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  31
    How Music-Inspired Weeping Can Help Terminally Ill Patients.Kay Norton - 2011 - Journal of Medical Humanities 32 (3):231-243.
    Music’s power to improve the ‘human condition’ has been acknowledged since ancient times. Something as counter-intuitive as weeping in response to music can ameliorate suffering for a time even for terminally ill patients. Several benefits—including catharsis, communication, and experiencing vitality—can be associated with grieving in response to “sad” music. In addressing the potential rewards of such an activity for terminally ill patients, this author combines concepts from philosopher Jerrold R. Levinson’s article, entitled “Music and Negative Emotion,” (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23. Music Listening in Times of COVID-19 Outbreak: A Brazilian Study.Fabiana Silva Ribeiro, João Paulo Araújo Lessa, Guilherme Delmolin & Flávia H. Santos - 2021 - Frontiers in Psychology 12:647473.
    The COVID-19 outbreak required diverse strategies, such as social distancing and self-isolation, to avoid a healthcare system crisis. However, these measures have been associated with the onset or increase of anxiety and depression symptoms in the population. Music listening was previously shown to regulate emotion, consequently reducing depression symptoms. Since previous studies with Brazilian samples have already shown a high prevalence of depressive symptoms during the first confinement period, the aim of this study was threefold: (i) to compare groups (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  15
    Imagination, music, and the emotions: a philosophical study.Saam Trivedi - 2017 - Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
    Articulates an imaginationist solution to the question of how purely instrumental music can be perceived by a listener as having emotional content. Both musicians and laypersons can perceive purely instrumental music without words or an associated story or program as expressing emotions such as happiness and sadness. But how? In this book, Saam Trivedi discusses and critiques the leading philosophical approaches to this question, including formalism, metaphorism, expression theories, arousalism, resemblance theories, and persona theories. Finding these to be (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  12
    Sad flowers: analyzing affective trajectory in Schubert's “Trockne Blumen”.Michael Spitzer - 2013 - In Tom Cochrane, Bernardino Fantini & Klaus R. Scherer (eds.), The Emotional Power of Music: Multidisciplinary Perspectives on Musical Arousal, Expression, and Social Control. Oxford University Press. pp. 7.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  18
    Musical Understanding, Musical Works, and Emotional Expression: Implications for education.David J. Elliott - 2005 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 37 (1):93-103.
    What do musicians, critics, and listeners mean when they use emotion‐words to describe a piece of instrumental music? How can ‘pure’ musical sounds ‘express’ emotions such as joyfulness, sadness, anguish, optimism, and anger? Sounds are not living organisms; sounds cannot feel emotions. Yet many people around the world believe they hear emotions in sounds and/or feel the emotions expressed by musical patterns. Is there a reasonable explanation for this dilemma?These issues gain additional importance when we ask them in the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Musical understanding, musical works, and emotional expression: Implications for education.David J. Elliott - 2005 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 37 (1):93–103.
    What do musicians, critics, and listeners mean when they use emotion‐words to describe a piece of instrumental music? How can ‘pure’ musical sounds ‘express’ emotions such as joyfulness, sadness, anguish, optimism, and anger? Sounds are not living organisms; sounds cannot feel emotions. Yet many people around the world believe they hear emotions in sounds and/or feel the emotions expressed by musical patterns. Is there a reasonable explanation for this dilemma? These issues gain additional importance when we ask them in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  47
    Form and meaning in music: Revisiting the affective character of the major and minor modes.Timothy Justus, Laura Gabriel & Adela Pfaff - 2018 - Auditory Perception and Cognition 1 (3–4):229–247.
    Musical systems develop associations over time between aspects of musical form and concepts from outside of the music. Experienced listeners internalize these connotations, such that the formal elements bring to mind their extra-musical meanings. An example of musical form-meaning mapping is the association that Western listeners have between the major and minor modes and happiness and sadness, respectively. We revisit the emotional semantics of musical mode in a study of 44 American participants (musicians and non-musicians) who each evaluated the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  29.  5
    Rethinking Music Education and Social Change by Alexandra Kertz-Welzel (review).Graça Mota - 2023 - Philosophy of Music Education Review 31 (1):99-104.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Rethinking Music Education and Social Change by Alexandra Kertz-WelzelGraça MotaAlexandra Kertz-Welzel, Rethinking Music Education and Social Change (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2022)I began to read this book shortly after the invasion of Ukraine by the Russian troops. Amidst this most terrible and brutal context, reading and re-reading the book that Alexandra Kertz-Welzel offers was both a blessing and an intense exercise of food for thought. A (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  47
    Music and Affect: The Influence of the Xing Zi Ming Chu on the Xunzi and Yueji.Franklin Perkins - 2017 - Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 16 (3):325-340.
    The Xing Zi Ming Chu 性自命出 presents a distinctive account of human dispositions that centers on the spontaneous arising of affects like joy and sadness. This focus on emotion grounds a particular conception of the function of music and ritual that gives music a central role in self-cultivation. Although the account of human dispositions in XZMC was ultimately overshadowed by the opposing views of Mengzi 孟子 and Xunzi 荀子 and the question of whether our dispositions are good or (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  7
    Influence of Background Musical Emotions on Attention in Congenital Amusia.Natalia B. Fernandez, Patrik Vuilleumier, Nathalie Gosselin & Isabelle Peretz - 2021 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 14.
    Congenital amusia in its most common form is a disorder characterized by a musical pitch processing deficit. Although pitch is involved in conveying emotion in music, the implications for pitch deficits on musical emotion judgements is still under debate. Relatedly, both limited and spared musical emotion recognition was reported in amusia in conditions where emotion cues were not determined by musical mode or dissonance. Additionally, assumed links between musical abilities and visuo-spatial attention processes need further investigation in congenital amusics. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Rubber Ring: Why do we listen to sad songs?Aaron Smuts - 2011 - In John Gibson & Noel Carroll (eds.), Narrative, Emotion, and Insight. Penn State UP. pp. 131.
    In this essay, I discuss a few ways in which songs are used, ways in which listeners engage with and find meaning in music. I am most interested in sad songs—those that typically feature narratives about lost love, separation, missed opportunity, regret, hardship, and all manner of heartache. Many of us are drawn to sad songs in moments of emotional distress. The problem is that sad songs do not always make us feel better; to the contrary, they often make (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  33. The Perception of Music: Sources of Significance.Christopher Peacocke - 2009 - Modern Schoolman 86 (3-4):239-260.
    We can experience music as sad, as exuberant, as sombre. We can experience it as expressing immensity, identification with the rest of humanity, or gratitude. The foundational question of what it is for music to express these or anything else is easily asked; and it has proved extraordinarily difficult to answer satisfactorily. The question of what it is for emotion or other states to be heard in music is not the causal or computational question of how it (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  34.  11
    Rethinking Social Action through Music: The Search for Coexistence and Citizenship in Medellín’s Music Schools by Geoffrey Baker (review).Kim Boeskov - 2023 - Philosophy of Music Education Review 31 (1):92-98.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Rethinking Social Action through Music: The Search for Coexistence and Citizenship in Medellín’s Music Schools by Geoffrey BakerKim BoeskovGeoffrey Baker: Rethinking Social Action through Music: The Search for Coexistence and Citizenship in Medellín’s Music Schools (Cambridge, UK: Open Book Publishers, 2021)If indeed there exists, as Geir Johansen has proposed,1 a self-critical movement within the field of music education, Geoffrey Baker is undoubtedly one (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  21
    Epic and Tragic Music: The Union of the Arts in the Eighteenth Century.Joshua Billings - 2011 - Journal of the History of Ideas 72 (1):99-117.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Epic and Tragic Music: The Union of the Arts in the Eighteenth CenturyJoshua BillingsI. The Union of the Arts in WeimarAround 1800 in Weimar, thought on Greek tragedy crystallized around the union of speech, music, and gesture—what Wagner would later call the Gesamtkunstwerk. Friedrich Schiller and Johann Gottfried Herder both found something lacking in modern spoken theater in comparison with ancient tragedy’s synthesis of the arts. Schiller’s (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  5
    Why, Delilah? When music and lyrics move us in different directions.Laura Sizer & Eva M. Dadlez - forthcoming - Philosophical Studies:1-23.
    Songs that combine happy music and sad, violent, or morally disturbing lyrics raise questions about the relationship between music and lyrics in song, including the question of how such songs affect the listener, and of the ethical implications of listening – and perhaps singing along with – such songs. To explore those perplexing cases in which the affective impact of music and lyrics seem entirely incompatible, we first examine how song music – and the sympathetic musical (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  11
    The Ethical Power of Music: Ancient Greek and Chinese Thoughts.Yuhwen Wang - 2004 - Journal of Aesthetic Education 38 (1):89.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Journal of Aesthetic Education 38.1 (2004) 89-104 [Access article in PDF] The Ethical Power of Music:Ancient Greek and Chinese Thoughts Yuhwen Wang Both the ancient Chinese and Greeks from around the fifth century B.C. to around third century A.D. recognized the immense impact that music has on the development of one's personality, and both regarded it as crucial in cultivation for the proper disposition in youth. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  38.  44
    The ethical power of music: Ancient greek and chinese thoughts.Yuhwen Wang - 2004 - Journal of Aesthetic Education 38 (1):89-104.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Journal of Aesthetic Education 38.1 (2004) 89-104 [Access article in PDF] The Ethical Power of Music:Ancient Greek and Chinese Thoughts Yuhwen Wang Both the ancient Chinese and Greeks from around the fifth century B.C. to around third century A.D. recognized the immense impact that music has on the development of one's personality, and both regarded it as crucial in cultivation for the proper disposition in youth. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  39.  40
    The Recognition of Emotions in Music and Landscapes: Extending Contour Theory.Marta Benenti & Cristina Meini - 2018 - Philosophia 46 (3):647-664.
    While inanimate objects can neither experience nor express emotions, in principle they can be expressive of emotions. In particular, music is a paradigmatic example of something expressive of emotions that surely cannot feel anything at all. The Contour theory accounts for music expressiveness in terms of those resemblances that hold between its external and perceivable properties and the typical contour of human emotional behavior. Provided that some critical aspects are emended – notably, the stress on the perception of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  40.  32
    Understanding the Score: Film Music Communicating to and Influencing the Audience.Jessica Green - 2010 - Journal of Aesthetic Education 44 (4):81.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Understanding the Score: Film Music Communicating to and Influencing the AudienceJessica Green (bio)IntroductionWhen most people sit down to watch a film, their focus usually stays on the very dynamic images that move onscreen. The dialogue, as a form of diegetic sound, is probably the next piece of the film they concentrate on, but this only imitates actual experience, since most people understand communication by both watching and listening. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  20
    Teaching General Music in Grades 4-8: A Musicianship Approach (review).Katherine Strand - 2005 - Philosophy of Music Education Review 13 (1):121-126.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Teaching General Music in Grades 4–8: A Musicianship ApproachKatherine StrandThomas Regelski, Teaching General Music in Grades 4–8: A Musicianship Approach ( Oxford: Oxford University Press 2004)In this recent addition to the world of texts for secondary methods classes, Teaching General Music in Grades 4–8: A Musicianship Approach, Thomas Regelski takes a new look at the challenging task of teaching the pre-adolescent and adolescent age group. (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  2
    Kazak Türklüğünü aydınlatanlara Nısanbayev'in bakışı.Sadık K. Tural (ed.) - 1999 - Maltepe, Ankara: Atatürk Yüksek Kurumu, Atatürk Kültür Merkezi Başkanlığı.
  43. Behind Zarathustra's Eyes: The Bad, Sad Man Meets Nietzsche's Prophet.M. Blake Wilson - 2016 - In Rocco Gennaro & Casey Harison (eds.), The Who and Philosophy. Lexington Books.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Music critics and aestheticians are, on the surface, advocates and guardians of good music. But what exactly is “good”.Pop Music - 2004 - In Christopher Washburne & Maiken Derno (eds.), Bad music: the music we love to hate. New York: Routledge. pp. 62.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. “I like bad music.” That's my usual response to people who ask me about my musi.Rock Critics Need Bad Music - 2004 - In Christopher Washburne & Maiken Derno (eds.), Bad music: the music we love to hate. New York: Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  66
    Response to Kingsley Price, "How Can Music Seem to be Emotional".Forest Hansen - 2004 - Philosophy of Music Education Review 12 (1):76-79.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Philosophy of Music Education Review 12.1 (2004) 76-79 [Access article in PDF] Response to Kingsley Price, "How Can Music Seem to be Emotional" Forest Hansen Lake Forest College Just as at the International Symposium in Philosophy of Music Education IV (PME-IV) in Birmingham, Kingsley Price has demonstrated his acute logical prowess and his alluring wit. Then as now he was addressing the question of how (...) can seem to have feelings, how it is that we attribute merriment, joy, sorrow, sadness, and the like to passages of instrumental music. On that occasion he systematically dissected the general theory which explains such attributions by reference to feelings or emotions caused in the listener, and he more explicitly criticized the causal model theories of Peter Kivy, Jerrold Levinson, and Roger Scruton. He half-promised, then, that he would in time examine another kind of relevant theory-namely one that explains by showing that music means feelings.Now he has examined for us what is probably the strongest version of such a theory-that of Susanne Langer-and found it wanting. And he has left us in limbo by refusing to reveal his own true and best theory. Perhaps for that we must wait for PME-VI!By way of responding to Price, I want to point out two things in his argument which I find rather slippery, one perhaps not so important and one that I think is [End Page 76] quite important. Then I will make a quasi-defense of Langer's theory of meaning which may evade Price's criticism. Finally, I would like to hazard a guess as to the kind of position which Price might put forward if he were not so reticent.First, the point that is not so important. There has long been an amazing amount of uncertainly about what constitutes an emotion or a feeling, amazing because philosophers and subsequently psychologists have been reflecting on and doing mental and laboratory experiments in the area for a long, long time. Some take feeling to be the larger field of which emotions are a subset; others do the reverse. Some differentiate feelings or emotions or both in terms of related behavior, whereas others put them in the box of subjective experience. So my first comments are meant to be cautionary with respect to speaking about feelings or emotions.Price, for instance, speaks of love as a kind of emotion. I find that peculiar, especially in the way he describes Romeo's love as "continuous, not a succession of discrete moments" and as something that has a more or less clear beginning and end with no lapses in between. But there must be many times that Romeo does not experience the so-called emotion, when he is asleep, for instance, or doing nothing between acts. I love my wife Valerie, but when I am speaking now, and in most of my actions every day, I am not experiencing some set of feelings that combine to make the emotion "Forest's love of Valerie." Often what we call emotions are only intermittently experienced and are perhaps best understood as dispositions or attitudes or beliefs or commitments.My second, and I hope more telling, point is to note how Price is playful with the notion of "reality." He makes it sound as if the distinction between appearance and reality is something that can be quite clear and unambiguous, even if it is not so in particular situations like that of a person seeing a nonexistent oasis or of Lady Macbeth seeing a nonexistent spot on her hand. But note how Price so often gives us examples from the world, so to speak, of art. Lady Macbeth and Romeo do not exist as real people. Those who enact their parts do, of course, but the Lady Macbeth actor is not fooled about the spot on the hand, and the Romeo actor might quite dislike the Juliet actor and not even be sexually attracted to her. Unlike us poor mortals, Romeo and Juliet live and die again and again... (shrink)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  39
    Response to June Boyce-Tillman, "Towards an Ecology of Music Education".Mark Garberich - 2004 - Philosophy of Music Education Review 12 (2):188-193.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Philosophy of Music Education Review 12.2 (2004) 188-193 [Access article in PDF] Response to June Boyce-Tillman, "Towards an Ecology of Music Education" Mark Garberich Michigan State University June Boyce-Tillman's "Towards an Ecology of Music Education" challenges the foundations of music education philosophy and its application to practice. Beginning with the identification and clarification of what are described as "subjugated ways of knowing," she advocates the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  13
    Response to Kingsley Price,?How can Music Seem to be Emotional?Forest Hansen - 2004 - Philosophy of Music Education Review 12 (1):76-79.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Philosophy of Music Education Review 12.1 (2004) 76-79 [Access article in PDF] Response to Kingsley Price, "How Can Music Seem to be Emotional" Forest Hansen Lake Forest College Just as at the International Symposium in Philosophy of Music Education IV (PME-IV) in Birmingham, Kingsley Price has demonstrated his acute logical prowess and his alluring wit. Then as now he was addressing the question of how (...) can seem to have feelings, how it is that we attribute merriment, joy, sorrow, sadness, and the like to passages of instrumental music. On that occasion he systematically dissected the general theory which explains such attributions by reference to feelings or emotions caused in the listener, and he more explicitly criticized the causal model theories of Peter Kivy, Jerrold Levinson, and Roger Scruton. He half-promised, then, that he would in time examine another kind of relevant theory-namely one that explains by showing that music means feelings.Now he has examined for us what is probably the strongest version of such a theory-that of Susanne Langer-and found it wanting. And he has left us in limbo by refusing to reveal his own true and best theory. Perhaps for that we must wait for PME-VI!By way of responding to Price, I want to point out two things in his argument which I find rather slippery, one perhaps not so important and one that I think is [End Page 76] quite important. Then I will make a quasi-defense of Langer's theory of meaning which may evade Price's criticism. Finally, I would like to hazard a guess as to the kind of position which Price might put forward if he were not so reticent.First, the point that is not so important. There has long been an amazing amount of uncertainly about what constitutes an emotion or a feeling, amazing because philosophers and subsequently psychologists have been reflecting on and doing mental and laboratory experiments in the area for a long, long time. Some take feeling to be the larger field of which emotions are a subset; others do the reverse. Some differentiate feelings or emotions or both in terms of related behavior, whereas others put them in the box of subjective experience. So my first comments are meant to be cautionary with respect to speaking about feelings or emotions.Price, for instance, speaks of love as a kind of emotion. I find that peculiar, especially in the way he describes Romeo's love as "continuous, not a succession of discrete moments" and as something that has a more or less clear beginning and end with no lapses in between. But there must be many times that Romeo does not experience the so-called emotion, when he is asleep, for instance, or doing nothing between acts. I love my wife Valerie, but when I am speaking now, and in most of my actions every day, I am not experiencing some set of feelings that combine to make the emotion "Forest's love of Valerie." Often what we call emotions are only intermittently experienced and are perhaps best understood as dispositions or attitudes or beliefs or commitments.My second, and I hope more telling, point is to note how Price is playful with the notion of "reality." He makes it sound as if the distinction between appearance and reality is something that can be quite clear and unambiguous, even if it is not so in particular situations like that of a person seeing a nonexistent oasis or of Lady Macbeth seeing a nonexistent spot on her hand. But note how Price so often gives us examples from the world, so to speak, of art. Lady Macbeth and Romeo do not exist as real people. Those who enact their parts do, of course, but the Lady Macbeth actor is not fooled about the spot on the hand, and the Romeo actor might quite dislike the Juliet actor and not even be sexually attracted to her. Unlike us poor mortals, Romeo and Juliet live and die again and again... (shrink)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  3
    Hitabiyat.Sadık Vicdanı̂ - 1920 - Bursa: Hüdavendigâr Vilâyet Matbaası.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  8
    Rimbaud'nun Şiirlerinde Alışılmamış Bağdaştırmalar.Sadık Türkoğlu - 2013 - Journal of Turkish Studies 8 (Volume 8 Issue 10):671-671.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000