Results for 'genesis of mathematical knowledge'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  70
    Mathematical Knowledge and Pattern Cognition.Michael D. Resnik - 1975 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 5 (1):25 - 39.
    This paper is concerned with the genesis of mathematical knowledge. While some philosophers might argue that mathematics has no real subject matter and thus is not a body of knowledge, I will not try to dissuade them directly. I shall not attempt such a refutation because it seems clear to me that mathematicians do know such things as the Mean Value Theorem, The Fundamental Theorem of Arithmetic, Godel's Theorems, etc. Moreover, this is much more evident to (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  2. Hermann Lotze and the Genesis of Husserl's early philosophy (1886-1901).Denis Fisette - forthcoming - In N. De Warren (ed.), From Lotze to Husserl: Psychology, Mathematics and Philosophy in Göttingen. Springer.
    The purpose of this study is to assess Husserl’s debt to Lotze’s philosophy during the Halle period (1886-1901). I shall first track the sources of Husserl’s knowledge of Lotze’s philosophy during his studies with Brentano in Vienna and then with Stumpf in Halle. I shall then briefly comment on Husserl’s references to Lotze in his early work and research manuscripts for the second volume of his Philosophy of Arithmetic. In the third section, I examine Lotze’s influence on Husserl’s antipsychologistic (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  3.  46
    Mathematics from the Structural Point of View.Michael D. Resnik - 1988 - Revue Internationale de Philosophie 42 (4):400-424.
    This paper is a nontechnical exposition of the author's view that mathematics is a science of patterns and that mathematical objects are positions in patterns. the new elements in this paper are epistemological, i.e., first steps towards a postulational theory of the genesis of our knowledge of patterns.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  4. Influence of Christian Weltanschaugung on the Genesis of Modern Science.Rinat M. Nugayev - 2012 - Religion Studies (3):1-14.
    Origins of the Copernican Revolution that led to modern science genesis can be explained only by the joint influence of external and internal factors. The author tries to take this influence into account with a help of his own growth of knowledge model according to which the growth of science consists in interaction, interpenetration and unification of various scientific research programmes spreading from different cultural milieux. Copernican Revolution consisted in revealation and elimination of the gap between Ptolemy’s (...) astronomy and Aristotelian qualitative physics. But the very realization of the gap between physics and astronomy appeared to be possible because at least at its first stages modern science was a result of Christian Weltanschaugung development with its aspiration for elimination of pagan components. Of all the external factors religion was the strongest one. Key words: scientific revolution, Christian weltanschaugung, modernity, Copernicus, Ptolemy. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  17
    Epistemologies of predictive policing: Mathematical social science, social physics and machine learning.Jens Hälterlein - 2021 - Big Data and Society 8 (1).
    Predictive policing has become a new panacea for crime prevention. However, we still know too little about the performance of computational methods in the context of predictive policing. The paper provides a detailed analysis of existing approaches to algorithmic crime forecasting. First, it is explained how predictive policing makes use of predictive models to generate crime forecasts. Afterwards, three epistemologies of predictive policing are distinguished: mathematical social science, social physics and machine learning. Finally, it is shown that these epistemologies (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  4
    The Rules of Ferrous Metallurgy: Genesis and Structure of a Field of Engineering Science, 1870–1914.Stefan Krebs - 2010 - NTM Zeitschrift für Geschichte der Wissenschaften, Technik und Medizin 18 (1):29-60.
    The ways in which the sciences have been delineated and categorized throughout history provide insights into the formation, stabilization, and establishment of scientific systems of knowledge. The Dresdener school’s approach for explaining and categorizing the genesis of the engineering disciplines is still valid, but needs to be complemented by further-reaching methodological and theoretical reflections. Pierre Bourdieu’s theory of social practice is applied to the question of how individual agents succeed in influencing decisively a discipline’s changing object orientation, institutionalisation (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. The nature of mathematical knowledge.Philip Kitcher - 1983 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    This book argues against the view that mathematical knowledge is a priori,contending that mathematics is an empirical science and develops historically,just as ...
  8. Copernican Revolution: Unification of Mundane Physics with Mathematics of the Skies.Rinat M. Nugayev (ed.) - 2012 - Logos: Innovative Technologies Publishing House.
    What were the reasons of the Copernican Revolution ? How did modern science (created by a bunch of ambitious intellectuals) manage to force out the old one created by Aristotle and Ptolemy, rooted in millennial traditions and strongly supported by the Church? What deep internal causes and strong social movements took part in the genesis, development and victory of modern science? The author comes to a new picture of Copernican Revolution on the basis of the elaborated model of scientific (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  81
    The growth of mathematical knowledge.Emily Grosholz & Herbert Breger (eds.) - 2000 - Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    This book draws its inspiration from Hilbert, Wittgenstein, Cavaillès and Lakatos and is designed to reconfigure contemporary philosophy of mathematics by making the growth of knowledge rather than its foundations central to the study of mathematical rationality, and by analyzing the notion of growth in historical as well as logical terms. Not a mere compendium of opinions, it is organised in dialogical forms, with each philosophical thesis answered by one or more historical case studies designed to support, complicate (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  10. The growth of mathematical knowledge: An open world view.Carlo Cellucci - 2000 - In Emily Grosholz & Herbert Breger (eds.), The growth of mathematical knowledge. Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 153--176.
    In his book The Value of Science Poincaré criticizes a certain view on the growth of mathematical knowledge: “The advance of science is not comparable to the changes of a city, where old edifices are pitilessly torn down to give place to new ones, but to the continuous evolution of zoological types which develop ceaselessly and end by becoming unrecognizable to the common sight, but where an expert eye finds always traces of the prior work of the centuries (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  11. Short-circuiting the definition of mathematical knowledge for an Artificial General Intelligence.Samuel Alexander - 2020 - Cifma.
    We propose that, for the purpose of studying theoretical properties of the knowledge of an agent with Artificial General Intelligence (that is, the knowledge of an AGI), a pragmatic way to define such an agent’s knowledge (restricted to the language of Epistemic Arithmetic, or EA) is as follows. We declare an AGI to know an EA-statement φ if and only if that AGI would include φ in the resulting enumeration if that AGI were commanded: “Enumerate all the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  58
    The Autonomy of Mathematical Knowledge: Hilbert's Program Revisited.Curtis Franks - 2009 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Most scholars think of David Hilbert's program as the most demanding and ideologically motivated attempt to provide a foundation for mathematics, and because they see technical obstacles in the way of realizing the program's goals, they regard it as a failure. Against this view, Curtis Franks argues that Hilbert's deepest and most central insight was that mathematical techniques and practices do not need grounding in any philosophical principles. He weaves together an original historical account, philosophical analysis, and his own (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  13. Positing Mathematical Objects.Michael D. Resnik - 1997 - In Michael David Resnik (ed.), Mathematics as a science of patterns. New York ;: Oxford University Press.
    If, as I grant, mathematical objects are abstract entities existing outside of space and time, and if the idea of supernaturally grasping abstract entities is scientifically unacceptable, then we need to explain how we can attain mathematical knowledge using our ordinary faculties. I try to meet this challenge through a postulational account of the genesis of our mathematical knowledge, according to which our ancestors introduced mathematical objects by first positing geometric ideals and then (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. What is the problem of mathematical knowledge?Michael Potter - 2007 - In Michael Potter, Mary Leng & Alexander Paseau (eds.), Mathematical Knowledge.
    Suggests that the recent emphasis on Benacerraf's access problem locates the peculiarity of mathematical knowledge in the wrong place. Instead we should focus on the sense in which mathematical concepts are or might be "armchair concepts" – concepts about which non-trivial knowledge is obtainable a priori.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15.  53
    Criticism and growth of mathematical knowledge.Gianluigi Oliveri - 1997 - Philosophia Mathematica 5 (3):228-249.
    This paper attempts to show that mathematical knowledge does not grow by a simple process of accumulation and that it is possible to provide a quasi-empirical (in Lakatos's sense) account of mathematical theories. Arguments supporting the first thesis are based on the study of the changes occurred within Eudidean geometry from the time of Euclid to that of Hilbert; whereas those in favour of the second arise from reflections on the criteria for refutation of mathematical theories.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  16.  19
    The aesthetic value of mathematical knowledge and mathematics teaching.V. A. Erovenko - 2016 - Liberal Arts in Russia 5 (2):108.
    The article is devoted to identifying the value of the phenomenon of aesthetic value and beauty of mathematical knowledge and the beauty of mathematical theory of teaching mathematics. The aesthetic potential of mathematical knowledge allows the use of theater technology in the educational process with the active dialogic interaction between teacher and students. The criteria of beauty in mathematical theories are distinguished: the realization of beauty as the unity of the whole, and in the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  43
    The experiential foundations of mathematical knowledge.Nicolas D. Goodman - 1981 - History and Philosophy of Logic 2 (1-2):55-65.
    A view of the sources of mathematical knowledge is sketched which emphasizes the close connections between mathematical and empirical knowledge. A platonistic interpretation of mathematical discourse is adopted throughout. Two skeptical views are discussed and rejected. One of these, due to Maturana, is supposed to be based on biological considerations. The other, due to Dummett, is derived from a Wittgensteinian position in the philosophy of language. The paper ends with an elaboration of Gödel's analogy between (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  18. The autonomy of mathematical knowledge: Hilbert's program revisited.Curtis Franks - 2011 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 17 (1):119-122.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  19.  4
    Religion in Alexandre Kojève’s atheistic philosophy of science.Ivan Sergeevich Kurilovich - 2024 - Studies in East European Thought 76 (1):91-107.
    This paper focuses on Kojève’s account of history and philosophy of science. Kojève’s understanding of science can be characterized as internalism, which is evident in his holistic view of philosophy, theology, quantum physics, and the history of classical Newtonian mechanics. It precipitates the facilitation of a further inquiry into the Christian genesis, secular evolution, and subsequent de-Christianization of scientific thought. The paper includes a critical scrutiny of Kojève’s philosophical tenets, followed by a comparative analysis of the views of Hegel, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  18
    The Genesis of ‘Useful Knowledge’.M. Berg - 2007 - History of Science 45 (2):123-133.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  21.  21
    The Nature of Mathematical Knowledge.Donald Gillies - 1985 - Philosophical Quarterly 35 (138):104-107.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  22.  25
    The Nature of Mathematical Knowledge.Penelope Maddy - 1985 - Philosophy of Science 52 (2):312-314.
  23.  71
    Phenomenological Interpretation of Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason.Martin Heidegger - 1997 - Indiana University Press.
    The text of Martin Heidegger’s 1927–28 university lecture course on Emmanuel Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason presents a close interpretive reading of the first two parts of this masterpiece of modern philosophy. In this course, Heidegger continues the task he enunciated in Being and Time as the problem of dismatling the history of ontology, using temporality as a clue. Within this context the relation between philosophy, ontology, and fundamental ontology is shown to be rooted in the genesis of the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  24.  12
    Organisation, Transformation, and Propagation of Mathematical Knowledge in Omega.Serge Autexier, Christoph Benzmüller, Dominik Dietrich & Marc Wagner - 2008 - Mathematics in Computer Science 2 (2):253-277.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25.  34
    Godel's Disjunction: The Scope and Limits of Mathematical Knowledge.Leon Horsten & Philip Welch (eds.) - 2016 - Oxford, England: Oxford University Press UK.
    The logician Kurt Godel in 1951 established a disjunctive thesis about the scope and limits of mathematical knowledge: either the mathematical mind is equivalent to a Turing machine (i.e., a computer), or there are absolutely undecidable mathematical problems. In the second half of the twentieth century, attempts have been made to arrive at a stronger conclusion. In particular, arguments have been produced by the philosopher J.R. Lucas and by the physicist and mathematician Roger Penrose that intend (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  26.  3
    The Social Constitution of Mathematical Knowledge: Objectivity, Semantics, and Axiomatics.Paola Cantù - 2024 - In Bharath Sriraman (ed.), Handbook of the History and Philosophy of Mathematical Practice. Cham: Springer. pp. 2847-2877.
    The philosophy of mathematical practice sometimes investigates the social constitution of mathematics but does not always make explicit the philosophical-normative framework that guides the discussion. This chapter investigates some recent proposals in the philosophy of mathematical practice that compare social facts and mathematical objects, discussing similarities and differences. An attempt will be made to identify, through a comparison with three different perspectives in social ontology, the kind of objectivity attributed to mathematical knowledge, the type of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  48
    Mathematical Knowledge and the Interplay of Practices.José Ferreirós - 2015 - Princeton, USA: Princeton University Press.
    On knowledge and practices: a manifesto -- The web of practices -- Agents and frameworks -- Complementarity in mathematics -- Ancient Greek mathematics: a role for diagrams -- Advanced math: the hypothetical conception -- Arithmetic certainty -- Mathematics developed: the case of the reals -- Objectivity in mathematical knowledge -- The problem of conceptual understanding.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  28.  70
    Proof, rigour and informality : a virtue account of mathematical knowledge.Fenner Stanley Tanswell - 2016 - St Andrews Research Repository Philosophy Dissertations.
    This thesis is about the nature of proofs in mathematics as it is practiced, contrasting the informal proofs found in practice with formal proofs in formal systems. In the first chapter I present a new argument against the Formalist-Reductionist view that informal proofs are justified as rigorous and correct by corresponding to formal counterparts. The second chapter builds on this to reject arguments from Gödel's paradox and incompleteness theorems to the claim that mathematics is inherently inconsistent, basing my objections on (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  29. Knowledge of Mathematics without Proof.Alexander Paseau - 2015 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 66 (4):775-799.
    Mathematicians do not claim to know a proposition unless they think they possess a proof of it. For all their confidence in the truth of a proposition with weighty non-deductive support, they maintain that, strictly speaking, the proposition remains unknown until such time as someone has proved it. This article challenges this conception of knowledge, which is quasi-universal within mathematics. We present four arguments to the effect that non-deductive evidence can yield knowledge of a mathematical proposition. We (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  30. Problem: The Nature of Mathematical Knowledge According to Descartes.Elie Denissoff - 1952 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 26:179.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  44
    The Nature of Mathematical Knowledge.Charles Parsons - 1986 - Philosophical Review 95 (1):129.
  32. Locke's Theory of Mathematical Knowledge and of a Possible Science of Ethics.J. Gibson - 1896 - Philosophical Review 5:324.
  33.  30
    Historical dynamics of implicit and intuitive elements of mathematical knowledge.L. B. Sultanova - 2012 - Liberal Arts in Russiaроссийский Гуманитарный Журналrossijskij Gumanitarnyj Žurnalrossijskij Gumanitaryj Zhurnalrossiiskii Gumanitarnyi Zhurnal 1 (1):30.
    The article deals with historical dynamics of implicit and intuitive elements of mathematical knowledge. The author describes historical dynamics of implicit and intuitive elements and discloses a historical and evolutionary mechanism of building up mathematical knowledge. Each requirement to increase the level of theoretical rigor in mathematics is historically realized as a three-stage process. The first stage considers some general conditions of valid mathematical knowledge recognized by the mathematical community. The second one reveals (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  13
    Systematicity: The Nature of Science.Paul Hoyningen-Huene - 2013 - New York, US: Oxford University Press.
    In Systematicity, Paul Hoyningen-Huene answers the question "What is science?" by proposing that scientific knowledge is primarily distinguished from other forms of knowledge, especially everyday knowledge, by being more systematic. "Science" is here understood in the broadest possible sense, encompassing not only the natural sciences but also mathematics, the social sciences, and the humanities. The author develops his thesis in nine dimensions in which it is claimed that science is more systematic than other forms of knowledge: (...)
    No categories
  35.  95
    Systematicity: The Nature of Science.Paul Hoyningen-Huene - 2013 - New York, US: Oxford University Press USA.
    In Systematicity, Paul Hoyningen-Huene answers the question "What is science?" by proposing that scientific knowledge is primarily distinguished from other forms of knowledge, especially everyday knowledge, by being more systematic. "Science" is here understood in the broadest possible sense, encompassing not only the natural sciences but also mathematics, the social sciences, and the humanities. The author develops his thesis in nine dimensions in which it is claimed that science is more systematic than other forms of knowledge: (...)
  36. A new view of mathematical knowledge.Emily Grosholz - 1985 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 36 (1):71-78.
  37.  36
    The Nature of Mathematical Knowledge.Mary Tiles - 2009 - Philosophical Books 26 (1):40-43.
  38.  2
    The Nature of Mathematical Knowledge.Mary Tiles - 1985 - Philosophical Books 26 (1):40-43.
  39.  44
    Godel, Wittgenstein and the Nature of Mathematical Knowledge.Thomas Tymoczko - 1984 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1984:449-468.
    The nature of mathematical knowledge can be understood only by locating the knowing mathematician in an epistemic community. This claim is defended by extending Kripke's version of the Private Language Argument to include informal rules and using Godelian results to argue that such rules rules necessary in mathematics. A committed formalist might evade Kripke's original argument by positing internal mechanisms that determine rule -governed behavior. However, in the presence of informal rules, the formalist position collapses into the extreme (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. The Philosophical Importance of Mathematical Knowledge.B. Russell - 1914 - Philosophical Review 23:104.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  42
    The Nature of Mathematical Knowledge by Philip Kitcher. [REVIEW]Mark Steiner - 1984 - Journal of Philosophy 81 (8):449-456.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  42. Review of The Autonomy of Mathematical Knowledge.Juliette Kennedy - 2011 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 17 (1):119-122.
  43.  17
    Analogy and the growth of mathematical knowledge.Eberhard Knobloch - 2000 - In Emily Grosholz & Herbert Breger (eds.), The growth of mathematical knowledge. Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 295--314.
  44.  36
    The growth of mathematical knowledge—Introduction of convex bodies.Tinne Hoff Kjeldsen & Jessica Carter - 2012 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 43 (2):359-365.
  45.  41
    Linearity and Reflexivity in the Growth of Mathematical Knowledge.Leo Corry - 1989 - Science in Context 3 (2):409-440.
    The ArgumentRecent studies in the philosophy of mathematics have increasingly stressed the social and historical dimensions of mathematical practice. Although this new emphasis has fathered interesting new perspectives, it has also blurred the distinction between mathematics and other scientific fields. This distinction can be clarified by examining the special interaction of thebodyandimagesof mathematics.Mathematics has an objective, ever-expanding hard core, the growth of which is conditioned by socially and historically determined images of mathematics. Mathematics also has reflexive capacities unlike those (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  46.  49
    Hume on the social construction of mathematical knowledge.Tamás Demeter - unknown - Synthese 196 (9):3615-3631.
    Mathematics for Hume is the exemplary field of demonstrative knowledge. Ideally, this knowledge is a priori as it arises only from the comparison of ideas without any further empirical input; it is certain because demonstration consist of steps that are intuitively evident and infallible; and it is also necessary because the possibility of its falsity is inconceivable as it would imply a contradiction. But this is only the ideal, because demonstrative sciences are human enterprises and as such they (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  47.  11
    Against Fideistic Misinterpretations of the Genesis of Scientific Knowledge.A. Iu Grigorenko - 1978 - Russian Studies in Philosophy 17 (3):93-101.
    Much attention was devoted, at the Twenty-fifth Congress of the CPSU, to the ideological struggle now in progress and to the need for prompt and decisive refutation of bourgeois ideology. The problem of the genesis of science is now central to fierce ideological debates.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  31
    Mathematical Knowledge, Objects and Applications: Essays in Memory of Mark Steiner.Carl Posy & Yemima Ben-Menahem (eds.) - 2023 - Springer.
    This book provides a survey of the major issues in the philosophy of mathematics, such as ontological questions regarding the nature of mathematical objects, epistemic questions about the acquisition of mathematical knowledge, and the intriguing riddle of the applicability of mathematics to the physical world. Some of these issues go back to the nascent years of mathematics itself, others are just beginning to draw the attention of scholars. In addressing these questions, some of the papers in this (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  63
    Curtis Franks The Autonomy of Mathematical Knowledge: Hilbert's Program Revisited.W. W. Tait - 2011 - History and Philosophy of Logic 32 (2):177 - 183.
    History and Philosophy of Logic, Volume 32, Issue 2, Page 177-183, May 2011.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  18
    The Nature of Mathematical Knowledge According to Descartes.Elie Denissoff - 1952 - Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 26:179-184.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000