78 found
Order:
Disambiguations
Emily Grosholz [53]Emily R. Grosholz [25]Emily Rolfe Grosholz [2]Emily / R. Grosholz [1]
See also
  1.  43
    Representation and productive ambiguity in mathematics and the sciences.Emily Grosholz - 2007 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Viewed this way, the texts yield striking examples of language and notation that are irreducibly ambiguous and productive because they are ambiguous.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  2. Representation and Productive Ambiguity in Mathematics and the Sciences.Emily R. Grosholz - 2006 - Studia Leibnitiana 38 (2):244-246.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  3.  77
    The growth of mathematical knowledge.Emily Grosholz & Herbert Breger (eds.) - 2000 - Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    This book draws its inspiration from Hilbert, Wittgenstein, Cavaillès and Lakatos and is designed to reconfigure contemporary philosophy of mathematics by making the growth of knowledge rather than its foundations central to the study of mathematical rationality, and by analyzing the notion of growth in historical as well as logical terms. Not a mere compendium of opinions, it is organised in dialogical forms, with each philosophical thesis answered by one or more historical case studies designed to support, complicate or question (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  4.  21
    The partial unification of domains, hybrids, and the growth of mathematical knowledge.Emily R. Grosholz - 2000 - In Emily Grosholz & Herbert Breger (eds.), The growth of mathematical knowledge. Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 81--91.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  5.  99
    Black Sexual Politics: African Americans, Gender, and the New Racism. Patricia Hill Collins. New York: Routledge, 2005.Emily Grosholz - 2007 - Hypatia 22 (4):209-212.
  6. Cartesian method and the problem of reduction.Emily R. Grosholz - 1994 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 184 (1):119-121.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  7.  92
    Cartesian method and the problem of reduction.Emily Grosholz - 1991 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    The Cartesian method, construed as a way of organizing domains of knowledge according to the "order of reasons," was a powerful reductive tool. Descartes made significant strides in mathematics, physics, and metaphysics by relating certain complex items and problems back to more simple elements that served as starting points for his inquiries. But his reductive method also impoverished these domains in important ways, for it tended to restrict geometry to the study of straight line segments, physics to the study of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  8.  7
    Leibniz's Science of the Rational.Emily Grosholz & Elhanan Yakira - 1998 - Franz Steiner Verlag.
    This book explicates Leibnizian analysis as a search for conditions of intelligibility, and reconsiders his use of principles and methods as well as his account of truth in this way. Via careful reading of well-known, lesser known, and previously unedited texts, it gives a more accurate picture of his philosophical intentions, as well as the relevance of his project to contemporary debate. Two case studies are included, one concerning logic and the other arithmetic; they illustrate a theory of intelligibility that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  9.  9
    Starry Reckoning: Reference and Analysis in Mathematics and Cosmology.Emily Rolfe Grosholz - 2016 - Cham: Springer Verlag.
    This book deals with a topic that has been largely neglected by philosophers of science to date: the ability to refer and analyze in tandem. On the basis of a set of philosophical case studies involving both problems in number theory and issues concerning time and cosmology from the era of Galileo, Newton and Leibniz up through the present day, the author argues that scientific knowledge is a combination of accurate reference and analytical interpretation. In order to think well, we (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10.  29
    How Symbolic and Iconic Languages Bridge the Two Worlds of the Chemist.Emily Grosholz & Roald Hoffmann - 2000 - In Nalini Bhushan & Stuart Rosenfeld (eds.), Of Minds and Molecules: New Philosophical Perspectives on Chemistry. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 230.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  11.  16
    The Freestone Wall and the Walled Garden.Emily Grosholz - 2001 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 25 (1):2-3.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  12. Descartes' unification of algebra and geometry.Emily R. Grosholz - 1980 - In Stephen Gaukroger (ed.), Descartes: Philosophy, Mathematics and Physics. Barnes & Noble. pp. 156--68.
  13.  30
    Some uses of proportion in Newton's principia, book I: A case study in applied mathematics.Emily Grosholz - 1987 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 18 (2):209.
  14. Leibniz's metaphysics of time and space (review).Emily Grosholz - 2010 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 48 (2):pp. 246-247.
    Most discussions of Leibniz's metaphysics of time and space begin and end with the correspondence between Leibniz and Samuel Clarke, Newton's friend and defender. But Leibniz's ideas about time and space are far richer than this exchange suggests, and Michael Futch shows that the study of those investigations will enhance current discussion among philosophers and cosmologists. Futch's scholarly attention to a wide range of texts is matched by his philosophical acuity. His detailed expositions of texts are not tedious or pedantic (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Of the association for symbolic logic.Janet Folina, Douglas Jesseph, Dirk Schlimm, Emily Grosholz, Kenneth Manders, Sun-Joo Shin, Saul Kripke & William Ewald - 2009 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 15 (2):229.
  16.  31
    The Marriott Hotel Philadelphia, Pennsylvania December 27–30, 2008.Janet Folina, Douglas Jesseph, Dirk Schlimm, Emily Grosholz, Kenneth Manders, Sun-Joo Shin, Saul Kripke & William Ewald - 2009 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 15 (2).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  12
    Two English Translations of Simone de Beauvoir's The Second Sex.Emily R. Grosholz - 2017 - In Laura Hengehold & Nancy Bauer (eds.), A Companion to Simone de Beauvoir. Chichester, UK: Wiley. pp. 59–70.
    This chapter treats the reception and assessment of the two English translations of Simone de Beauvoir's Le deuxième sexe, the first by Howard M. Parshley in 1953 and the second by Constance Borde and Sheila Malovany‐Chevallier in 2009. We examine both the criticisms and the appreciations, concluding that the second is superior in many ways to the first. On that basis, we propose a digital edition of the original book and its earlier drafts en face the 2009 English translation, which (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. The Legacy of Simone de Beauvoir.Emily R. Grosholz - 2005 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 195 (3):384-386.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  9
    W.E.B. Du Bois on Race and Culture: Philosophy, Politics, and Poetics.Bernard W. Bell, Emily Grosholz & James Benjamin Stewart - 1996
    W. E. B. Du Bois was one of the most profound and influential African-American intellectuals of the twentieth century. This volume addresses the complexities of Du Bois' legacy, showing how his work gets to the heart of today's theorizing about the color line.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  18
    Logic and Knowledge.Carlo Cellucci, Emily Grosholz & Emiliano Ippoliti (eds.) - 2011 - Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publications.
    The problematic relation between logic and knowledge has given rise to some of the most important works in the history of philosophy, from Books VIVII of Platos Republic and Aristotles Prior and Posterior Analytics, to Kants Critique of Pure Reason and Mills A System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive. It provides the title of an important collection of papers by Bertrand Russell. However, it has remained an underdeveloped theme in the last century, because logic has been treated as separate from (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  38
    Plato and Leibniz against the Materialists.Emily Grosholz - 1996 - Journal of the History of Ideas 57 (2):255-276.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Plato and Leibniz against the MaterialistsEmily GrosholzImportant parallels hold between Leibniz’s attitude towards materialism and that of Plato. Both philosophers were interested in and hostile to materialism, and their qualified rejection of materialism became crucial to the systems of their maturity. Leibniz’s attachment to Plato began very early: in a text of 1664 Leibniz quoted the Timaeus, 1 and in another of 1670 he claimed that the Timaeus, along (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  63
    A Case Study in the Application of Mathematics to Physics: Descartes' Principles of Philosophy, Part II.Emily R. Grosholz - 1986 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1986:116 - 124.
    The question of how and why mathematics can be applied to physical reality should be approached through the history of science, as a series of case studies which may reveal both generalizable patterns and salient differences in the grounds and nature of that application from era to era. The present examination of Descartes' Principles of Philosophy Part II, reveals a deep ambiguity in the relation of Euclidean geometry to res extensa, and a tension between geometrical form and 'common motion of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  7
    A Case Study in the Applioation of Mathematics to Physics: Descartes’ Principles Of Philosophy, Part II.Emily R. Grosholz - 1986 - PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1986 (1):116-124.
    The question of how and why the application of mathematics to physical reality is possible has occupied philosophers for many centuries. In contemporary discussions, Philip Kitcher’s attack on a priorist approaches to the question is particularly interesting, for it suggests that there is no global answer (Kitcher 1983, Chapters 1-4). In this essay, I would like to develop his insight by arguing, first, that the problem of how mathematics relates to physical reality should be addressed by an appeal to the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  95
    A new view of mathematical knowledge.Emily Grosholz - 1985 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 36 (1):71-78.
  25.  56
    Aristotle, Shakespeare, and the Problem of Character.Emily Grosholz - 2009 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 33 (1):198-208.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  22
    Berzelian formulas as generative paper tools.Emily R. Grosholz - 2005 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 36 (2):411-417.
  27.  98
    Critical studies / book reviews.Emily Grosholz - 2004 - Philosophia Mathematica 12 (1):79-80.
  28.  75
    Critical studies/book reviews.Emily R. Grosholz - 2001 - Philosophia Mathematica 9 (2):79-80.
  29. Descartes and Galileo : the quantificatin of time and force.Emily Grosholz - 1991 - In Jules Vuillemin & Rushdī Rāshid (eds.), Mathématiques et philosophie de l'antiquité à l'age classique: hommage à Jules Vuillemin. Diffusion, Presses du CNRS.
  30. Frege and the surprising history of logic: Introduction to Claude Imbert, "Gottlob Frege, one more time".Emily Grosholz - 2000 - Hypatia 15 (4):151-155.
    Convinced that logic has a history and that its history always manages to surprise the philosophers, Claude Imbert has devoted much of her work to the study of the Stoic school and of the late-nineteenth-century German logician Gottlob Frege. In the fifth chapter of her book Pour une histoire de la logique, she examines the trajectory of Frege's awareness of what his new logic entails, in particular the way it subverts the project of Kant.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  19
    Frege and the Surprising History of Logic: Introduction to Claude Imbert, “Gottlob Frege, One More Time”.Emily Grosholz - 2000 - Hypatia 15 (4):151-155.
    Convinced that logic has a history and that its history always manages to surprise the philosophers, Claude Imbert has devoted much of her work to the study of the Stoic school and of the late-nineteenth-century German logician Gottlob Frege. In the fifth chapter of her book Pour une histoire de la logique, she examines the trajectory of Frege's awareness of what his new logic entails, in particular the way it subverts the project of Kant.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  31
    Frege and the Surprising History of Logic: Introduction to Claude Imbert, "Gottlob Frege, One More Time".Emily Grosholz - 2000 - Hypatia 15 (4):151-155.
    Convinced that logic has a history and that its history always manages to surprise the philosophers, Claude Imbert has devoted much of her work to the study of the Stoic school and of the late-nineteenth-century German logician Gottlob Frege. In the fifth chapter of her book Pour une histoire de la logique, she examines the trajectory of Frege's awareness of what his new logic entails, in particular the way it subverts the project of Kant.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. G.W. Leibniz, Interrelations Between Mathematics and Philosophy.Emily R. Grosholz (ed.) - 2015 - Springer Verlag.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  44
    Geometry, Time and Force in the Diagrams of Descartes, Galileo, Torricelli and Newton.Emily R. Grosholz - 1988 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1988:237 - 248.
    Cartesian method both organizes and impoverishes the domains to which Descartes applies it. It adjusts geometry so that it can be better integrated with algebra, and yet deflects a full-scale investigation of curves. It provides a comprehensive conceptual framework for physics, and yet interferes with the exploitation of its dynamical and temporal aspects. Most significantly, it bars a fuller unification of mathematics and physics, despite Descartes' claims to quantify nature. The work of his contemporaries Galileo and Torricelli, and of his (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35. How symbolic and iconic languages bridge the two worlds of the chemist: a case study from contemporary bioorganic chemistry.Emily R. Grosholz & Roald Hoffmann - 2012 - In Roald Hoffmann (ed.), Roald Hoffmann on the philosophy, art, and science of chemistry. Oxford University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  5
    Introduction to special issue on ‘Cosmology and Time’ for SHPMP.Emily Grosholz - 2015 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 52 (Part B):1-7.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  23
    La dynamique de Leibniz.Emily Grosholz - 1997 - The Leibniz Review 7:110-115.
    The significance of Leibniz’s work as a physical scientist has long been underestimated or misunderstood. This stems in part from the great success of Newton’s physics on the one hand and the influence of Kant’s account of scientific knowledge on the other, both of which tend to obscure Leibniz’s successes and intentions. It is also due to the unavailability or scholarly neglect of key texts which, if properly assessed, illuminate the work of Leibniz in dynamics. In La dynamique de Leibniz, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  8
    Leibniz et la Méthode de la Science.Emily Grosholz - 1997 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 35 (2):305-307.
  39.  7
    Leibniz, Locke, and Cassirer: Abstraction, and Analysis.Emily Grosholz - 2013 - Studia Leibnitiana 45 (1):97-108.
  40. Leibniz’s Mathematical and Philosophical Analysis of Time.Emily R. Grosholz - 2015 - In Norma B. Goethe, Philip Beeley & David Rabouin (eds.), G.W. Leibniz, Interrelations Between Mathematics and Philosophy. Springer Verlag.
  41.  7
    Leibniz’s Metaphysics of Time and His Practice as Historian and Physicist.Emily Grosholz - 2012 - Studia Leibnitiana 44 (1):1-13.
  42. Models of the Skies.Emily Grosholz - 2016 - In Emiliano Ippoliti, Fabio Sterpetti & Thomas Nickles (eds.), Models and Inferences in Science. Cham: Springer.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  5
    Objects and Structures in the Formal Sciences.Emily Grosholz - 1992 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1992:251 - 260.
    Mathematics, and mechanics conceived as a formal science, have their own proper subject matters, their own proper unities, which ground the characteristic way of constituting problems and solutions in each domain, the discoveries that expand and integrate domains with each other, and so in particular allow them, in the end, to be connected in a partial way with empirical fact. Criticizing both empiricist and structuralist accounts of mathematics, I argue that only an account of the formal sciences which attributes to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  9
    On the plains and prairies of Minnesota: The role of mathematical statistics in biological explanation.Emily R. Grosholz - 2021 - Synthese 199 (1-2):5377-5393.
    In this essay, I consider the use of mathematical statistics in the study of biological systems in the field, using as case studies the work of Ruth Geyer Shaw and her colleagues at the University of Minnesota. To address practical issues, like how to enhance prairie restoration, and how to prepare for (and perhaps prevent) the effect of rapid climate change, she and her colleagues combine mathematical modeling and intensive data collection in the field. Using ANOVA and the more versatile (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  21
    Problematic Objects between Mathematics and Mechanics.Emily R. Grosholz - 1990 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1990:385 - 395.
    The existence of mathematical objects may be explained in terms of their occurrence in problems. Especially interesting problems arise at the overlap of domains, and the items that intervene in them are hybrids sharing the characteristics of both domains in an ambiguous way. Euclid's geometry, and Leibniz' work at the intersection of geometry, algebra and mechanics in the late seventeenth century, provide instructive examples of such problems and items. The complex and yet still formal unity of these items calls into (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  7
    Problematic Objects between Mathematics and Mechanics.Emily R. Grosholz - 1990 - PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1990 (2):385-395.
    The relationship between the objects of mathematics and physics has been a recurrent source of philosophical debate. Rationalist philosophers can minimize the distance between mathematical and physical domains by appealing to transcendental categories, but then are left with the problem of where to locate those categories ontologically. Empiricists can locate their objects in the material realm, but then have difficulty explaining certain peculiar “transcendental” features of mathematics like the timelessness of its objects and the unfalsifiability of (at least some of) (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  27
    Reference and Analysis: The Representation of Time in Galileo, Newton, and Leibniz.Emily Grosholz - 2011 - Journal of the History of Ideas 72 (3):333-350.
  48. Rene Descartes, Meditations on First Philosophy (1641).Emily R. Grosholz - 2003 - In Jorge J. E. Gracia, Gregory M. Reichberg & Bernard N. Schumacher (eds.), The Classics of Western Philosophy: A Reader's Guide. Blackwell. pp. 217.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  12
    Robert G. Price, 1934-2002.Emily Grosholz - 2003 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 76 (5):166 -.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  13
    Space and Time.Emily Grosholz - 2011 - In Desmond M. Clarke & Catherine Wilson (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy in Early Modern Europe. Oxford University Press.
    This article describes the debate about space and time in the early modern period focusing on the exchange between Gottfried Leibniz and Isaac Newton. It provides a brief account of Galileo's critique of medieval cosmology, the finite, two-sphere cosmos with fixed places as well as a beginning and an end in time, the related account of motion as finite and in need of an external agent, and the too-limited use of geometry in mechanics. The article reviews in some detail the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 78