Results for 'duty to inform'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  27
    Duty to Inform and Informed Consent in Diagnostic Radiology: How Ethics and Law can Better Guide Practice.Victoria Doudenkova & Jean-Christophe Bélisle Pipon - 2016 - HEC Forum 28 (1):75-94.
    Although there is consensus on the fact that ionizing radiation used in radiological examinations can affect health, the stochastic nature of risk makes it difficult to anticipate and assess specific health implications for patients. The issue of radiation protection is peculiar as any dosage received in life is cumulative, the sensitivity to radiation is highly variable from one person to another, and between 20 % and 50 % of radiological examinations appear not to be necessary. In this context, one might (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  13
    Duty to Inform vs. Confidentiality.Arthur A. Fleisher - 1987 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 15 (4):254-254.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  13
    Doctors’ duty to inform patients.Loane Skene - 1993 - Monash Bioethics Review 12 (3):46-48.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. The Subjective Moral Duty to Inform Oneself before Acting.Holly M. Smith - 2014 - Ethics 125 (1):11-38.
    The requirement that moral theories be usable for making decisions runs afoul of the fact that decision makers often lack sufficient information about their options to derive any accurate prescriptions from the standard theories. Many theorists attempt to solve this problem by adopting subjective moral theories—ones that ground obligations on the agent’s beliefs about the features of her options, rather than on the options’ actual features. I argue that subjective deontological theories suffer a fatal flaw, since they cannot appropriately require (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  5.  5
    Duty to Inform vs. Confidentiality.Arthur A. Fleisher - 1987 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 15 (4):254-254.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  14
    Clinicians’ Perspectives on the Duty to Inform Patients About Medical Aid-in-Dying.Elizabeth R. Brassfield & Mara Buchbinder - 2020 - AJOB Empirical Bioethics 11 (1):53-62.
    As of 2019, ten jurisdictions in the United States—Oregon, Washington, Montana, Vermont, California, Colorado, the District of Columbia, Hawaii, New Jersey, and Maine—have authorized physicians to...
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  39
    Aid-in-dying laws and the physician's duty to inform.Mara Buchbinder - 2017 - Journal of Medical Ethics 43 (10):666-669.
    On 19 July 2016, three medical organisations filed a federal lawsuit against representatives from several Vermont agencies over the Patient Choice and Control at End of Life Act. The law is similar to aid-in-dying laws in four other US states, but the lawsuit hinges on a distinctive aspect of Vermont's law pertaining to patients' rights to information. The lawsuit raises questions about whether, and under what circumstances, there is an ethical obligation to inform terminally ill patients about AID as (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  8.  36
    Is genetic information family property? Expanding on the argument of confidentiality breach and duty to inform persons at risk.Yordanis Enríquez Canto & Barbara Osimani - 2015 - Persona y Bioética 19 (1).
    A current trend in bioethics considers genetic information as family property. This paper uses a logical approach to critically examine Matthew Liao’s proposal on the familial nature of genetic information as grounds for the duty to share it with relatives and for breach of confidentiality by the geneticist. The authors expand on the topic by examining the relationship between the arguments of probability and the familial nature of genetic information, as well as the concept of harm in the context (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Liability and the legal duty to inform in research.Ma'N. H. Zawati - 2014 - In Yann Joly & Bartha Maria Knoppers (eds.), Routledge Handbook of Medical Law and Ethics. New York, NY: Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  18
    The duty to be Well-informed: The case of depression.Charlotte Blease - 2014 - Journal of Medical Ethics 40 (4):225-229.
    It is now an ethical dictum that patients should be informed by physicians about their diagnosis, prognosis and treatment options. In this paper, I ask: ‘How informed are the ‘informers’ in clinical practice?’ Physicians have a duty to be ‘well-informed’: patient well-being depends not just in conveying adequate information to patients, it also depends on physicians keeping up-to-date about: popular misunderstandings of illnesses and treatments; and the importance of patient psychology in affecting prognosis. Taking the case of depression as (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  11.  13
    Currents in Contemporary Bioethics: Physicians' Duty to Inform Patients of New Medical Discoveries: The Effect of Health Information Technology.Mark A. Rothstein - 2011 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 39 (4):690-693.
    Physicians' duties to their patients traditionally have been construed narrowly in time and scope to focus on the specific episode of care or clinical encounter. Physicians generally have had no ethical or legal duty to notify patients about new medical information discovered after a visit, notwithstanding the health care benefits to patients that might flow from receiving the information. The rule was based on the relatively high burdens that notification would impose on physicians compared with the likelihood of benefits (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  29
    The Double Helix: Applying an Ethic of Care to the Duty to Warn Genetic Relatives of Genetic Information.Meaghann Weaver - 2015 - Bioethics 30 (3):181-187.
    Genetic testing reveals information about a patient's health status and predictions about the patient's future wellness, while also potentially disclosing health information relevant to other family members. With the increasing availability and affordability of genetic testing and the integration of genetics into mainstream medicine, the importance of clarifying the scope of confidentiality and the rules regarding disclosure of genetic findings to genetic relatives is prime. The United Nations International Declaration on Human Genetic Data urges an appreciation for principles of equality, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  13. Subjective Deontology and the Duty to Gather Information.Philip Swenson - 2016 - Ethics 127 (1):257-271.
    Holly Smith has recently argued that Subjective Deontological Moral Theories (SDM theories) cannot adequately account for agents’ duties to gather information. I defend SDM theories against this charge and argue that they can account for agents’ duties to inform themselves. Along the way, I develop some principles governing how SDM theories, and deontological moral theories in general, should assign ‘deontic value’ or ‘deontic weight’ to particular actions.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  14.  30
    Speak No Evil? Conscience and the Duty to Inform, Refer or Transfer Care.Mark P. Aulisio & Kavita Shah Arora - 2014 - HEC Forum 26 (3):257-266.
    This paper argues that the type of conscience claims made in last decade’s spate of cases involving pharmacists’ objections to filling birth control prescriptions and cases such as Ms. Means and Mercy Health Partners of Michigan, and even the Affordable Care Act and the Little Sisters of the Poor, as different as they appear to be from each other, share a common element that ties them together and makes them fundamentally different in kind from traditional claims of conscience about which (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  15.  28
    An ethical duty to protect one's own information privacy?Anita L. Allen - 2013 - Alabama Law Review 64 (4):845-866.
    People freely disclose vast quantities of personal and personally identifiable information. The central question of this Meador Lecture in Morality is whether they have a moral (or ethical) obligation (or duty) to withhold information about themselves or otherwise to protect information about themselves from disclosure. Moreover, could protecting one’s own information privacy be called for by important moral virtues, as well as obligations or duties? Safeguarding others’ privacy is widely understood to be a responsibility of government, business, and individuals. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  16.  36
    Environmental Footprint of Foods: The Duty to Inform[REVIEW]Lorenzo Del Savio & Bettina Schmietow - 2013 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 26 (4):787-796.
    In this paper we argue that there is a duty to inform consumers about the environmental impact of foods, and discuss what this duty entails and to whom it falls. We analyze previous proposals that justify ethical traceability with arguments from sustainability and the respect for the autonomy of consumers, showing that they cannot ground a duty to inform. We argue instead that the duty rests on the right of consumers not to be harmed, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  31
    Primary care physicians and the duty to inform about genetic discrimination.Anita Silvers - 2001 - American Journal of Bioethics 1 (3):1 – 2.
  18.  11
    Duty to Family: Ethical Considerations in the Resuscitation Bay.Ashley Pavlic, Arthur R. Derse, Nancy Jacobson, Christopher Calciano & Colin Liphart - 2024 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 35 (1):54-58.
    To examine the ethical duty to patients and families in the setting of the resuscitation bay, we address a case with a focus on providing optimal care and communication to family members. We present a case of nonsurvivable traumatic injury in a minor, focusing on how allowing family more time at the bedside impacts the quality of death and what duty exists to maintain an emotionally optimal environment for family grieving and acceptance. Our analysis proposes tenets for patient (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  81
    Is there a duty to share genetic information?S. Matthew Liao - 2009 - Journal of Medical Ethics 35 (5):306-309.
    A number of prominent bioethicists such as Mike Parker, Anneke Lucassen, and Bartha Maria Knoppers have called for the adoption of a system in which by default, genetic information is shared among family members. In this paper, I suggest that a main reason given in support of this call to share genetic information among family members is the idea that genetic information is essentially familial in nature. Upon examining this ‘familial nature of genetics’ argument, I show that most genetic information (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  20.  7
    Is there a legal and ethical duty on doctors to inform patients of the likely co-payment costs should they be treated by practitioners who have contracted out of medical scheme rates?D. McQuoid-Mason - 2023 - South African Journal of Bioethics and Law 16 (3):84-87.
    A hypothetical scenario is presented in which a female patient is admitted to a private hospital to undergo a mastectomy and breast reconstruction. The surgeons and anaesthetists conducting the different procedures charge three times the medical aid rates. When the patient asks what the co-payments are likely to be, she is informed by the doctors’ accounts section that they can only provide this information after each procedure. The patient’s medical scheme also advises her that it cannot determine the likely co-payments (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. A Duty to Resist: When Disobedience Should Be Uncivil.Candice Delmas - 2018 - New York, USA: Oxford University Press.
    What are our responsibilities in the face of injustice? How far should we go to fight it? Many would argue that as long as a state is nearly just, citizens have a moral duty to obey the law. Proponents of civil disobedience generally hold that, given this moral duty, a person needs a solid justification to break the law. But activists from Henry David Thoreau and Mohandas Gandhi to the Movement for Black Lives have long recognized that there (...)
  22.  20
    Rights of and duties to non‐consenting patients–informed refusal in the developing world.Louis-Jacques van Bogaert - 2006 - Developing World Bioethics 6 (1):13-22.
    ABSTRACTThe principle of informed refusal poses a specific problem when it is invoked by a pregnant woman who, in spite of having accepted her pregnancy, refuses the diagnostic and/or therapeutic measures that would ensure the well‐being of her endangered fetus. Guidelines issued by professional bodies in the developed world are conflicting: either they allow autonomy and informed consent to be overruled to the benefit of the fetus, or they recommend the full respect of these principles. A number of medical ethicists (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  23
    Physicians, battery, and the duty to give informed consent.Mark Strasser - 1987 - Journal of Medical Humanities and Bioethics 8 (1):40-48.
    This essay discusses the issue of informed consent as it relates not only to physician duty but also to patient duty. The author is particularly concerned with the possibility of battery charges against the physician unless a clear patient duty is articulated. In summary, the author concludes that we can prevent doctors from being forced to commit battery in a way which allows them to make reasonable choices for their patients without being open to the charge of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  10
    Rights of and Duties to Non‐Consenting Patients – Informed Refusal in the Developing World.Louis-Jacques van Bogaert - 2006 - Developing World Bioethics 6 (1):13-22.
    ABSTRACT The principle of informed refusal poses a specific problem when it is invoked by a pregnant woman who, in spite of having accepted her pregnancy, refuses the diagnostic and/or therapeutic measures that would ensure the well‐being of her endangered fetus. Guidelines issued by professional bodies in the developed world are conflicting: either they allow autonomy and informed consent to be overruled to the benefit of the fetus, or they recommend the full respect of these principles. A number of medical (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. The Duty to Disclose Adverse Clinical Trial Results.S. Matthew Liao, Mark Sheehan & Steve Clarke - 2009 - American Journal of Bioethics 9 (8):24-32.
    Participants in some clinical trials are at risk of being harmed and sometimes are seriously harmed as a result of not being provided with available, relevant risk information. We argue that this situation is unacceptable and that there is a moral duty to disclose all adverse clinical trial results to participants in clinical trials. This duty is grounded in the human right not to be placed at risk of harm without informed consent. We consider objections to disclosure grounded (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  26.  27
    Rights of and duties to non-consenting patients – informed refusal in the developing world.Louis-jacquesvan Bogaert - 2006 - Developing World Bioethics 6 (1):13–22.
  27.  32
    Treating Minors and the Duty to Disclose Information to Parents.Benjamin J. Capps - 2013 - Asian Bioethics Review 5 (3):255-261.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  66
    Should the Lawyer's Duty to Keep Confidences Override the Duty to Disclose Material Information to a Client?Selene E. Mize - 2009 - Legal Ethics 12 (2):171.
  29.  21
    Technological competence and the duty to safeguard confidential information in the USA.Benjamin P. Cooper - 2017 - Legal Ethics 20 (2):268-270.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Duties to Others.Courtney Campbell & B. Andrew Lustig - 1994 - Springer.
    Despite reservoirs of moral discourse about duties in religious communities, professional caregiving traditions, and philosophical perspectives, the dominant moral language in contemporary biomedical ethics is that of `rights'. Duties to Others begins to correct this imbalance in our ethical language through theoretical expositions of the ideas of duty and of the `other', and by applied exemplifications of particular duties to identified others that arise in the context of health care. A pronounced multidisciplinary orientation informs this analysis of our moral (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Democracy within, justice without: The duties of informal political representatives.Wendy Salkin - 2022 - Noûs 56 (4):940-971.
    Informal political representation can be a political lifeline, particularly for oppressed and marginalized groups. Such representation can give these groups some say, however mediate, partial, and imperfect, in how things go for them. Coeval with the political goods such representation offers these groups are its particular dangers to them. Mindful of these dangers, skeptics challenge the practice for being, inter alia, unaccountable, unauthorized, inegalitarian, and oppressive. These challenges provide strong pro tanto reasons to think the practice morally impermissible. This paper (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  32.  10
    When Does Catholic Social Teaching Imply a Duty to be Vaccinated for the Common Good?Steven M. A. Bow - 2023 - The New Bioethics 29 (4):304-321.
    In 2017, Carson and Flood outlined a general duty to be vaccinated, arguing from Catholic social teaching on justice, love, solidarity and the common good. This necessarily relied on assumptions about the typical nature of vaccination, assumptions which do not always hold true in concrete situations. I identify twelve criteria that, where they hold, strengthen the particular duty to be vaccinated, and, if not met, weaken or reverse it. These pertain to the biological agent which vaccination aims to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33. Open-Mindedness and the Duty to Gather Evidence.Neil Levy - 2006 - Public Affairs Quarterly 20 (1):55-66.
    Most people believe that we have a duty to gather evidence on both sides of central moral and political controversies, in order to fulfil our epistemic responsibilities and come to hold justified cognitive attitudes on these matters. I argue, on the contrary, that to the extent to which these controversies require special expertise, we have no such duty. We are far more likely to worsen than to improve our epistemic situation by becoming better informed on these questions. I (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  34.  20
    Researchers' Duty to Share Pre-publication Data: From the Prima Facie Duty to Practice.Christoph Schickhardt, Nelson Hosley & Eva C. Winkler - 2016 - In Mittelstadt Brent & Floridi Luciano (eds.), The ethics of biomedical big data. Springer. pp. 309-337.
    The purpose of this chapter is to offer an ethical investigation into whether researchers have a duty to share pre-published bio-medical data with the scientific community. The central questions of the chapter are the following: do researchers have a prima facie duty to share pre-published data? And if so, what stakes and aspects of a concrete situation need to be taken into consideration in order to assess whether and to what extent researchers’ prima facie duty to share (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  77
    Is there a duty to remain in ignorance?Iain Brassington - 2011 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 32 (2):101-115.
    Questions about information inform many debates in bioethics. One of the reasons for this is that at least some level of information is taken by many to be a prerequisite of valid consent. For others, autonomy in the widest sense presupposes information, because one cannot be in control of one’s life without at least some insight into what it could turn out to contain. Yet not everyone shares this view, and there is a debate about whether or not there (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  36.  28
    Right or duty of information.Sofia R. T. Nunes, Guilhermina Rego & Rui Nunes - 2016 - Nursing Ethics 23 (1):36-47.
    Background:The theoretical framework of Jϋrgen Habermas suggests that effective communication requires competent participants with an objective attitude that complies with the rules and worlds designated as objective, social and subjective. This situation determines communicative action, which stimulates the search for mutual understanding and results in a process of interaction that promotes self-determination.Objectives:In this study, the discharge letters of patients with myocardial infarction were explored regarding the provision of information. The patient’s right to information and the duty of informing were (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. On Satisfying Duties to Assist.Christian Barry & Holly Lawford-Smith - 2019 - In Hilary Greaves & Theron Pummer (eds.), Effective Altruism: Philosophical Issues. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    In this paper, we take up the question of whether there comes a point at which one is no longer morally obliged to do further good, even at very low cost to oneself. More specifically, they ask: under precisely what conditions is it plausible to say that that “point” has been reached? A crude account might focus only on, say, the amount of good the agent has already done, but a moment’s reflection shows that this is indeed too crude. We (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  27
    When Information Can Save Lives: The Duty to Warn Relatives about Sudden Cardiac Death and Environmental Risks.Bernice Elger, Katarzyna Michaud & Patrice Mangin - 2010 - Hastings Center Report 40 (3):39-45.
    In certain cases of sudden death, forensic experts may discover during an investigation or autopsy that family members of the deceased are also at risk of harm—from genetic disease, for instance. But do they have a duty to warn them? Looking at similar duties of physicians and researchers to warn third parties of risk suggests they do.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  74
    Diminishing returns? Risk and the duty to care in the Sars epidemic.Lynette Reid - 2005 - Bioethics 19 (4):348–361.
    The seriousness of the risk that healthcare workers faced during SARS, and their response of service in the face of this risk, brings to light unrealistic assumptions about duty and risk that informed the debate on duty to care in the early years of HIV/AIDS. Duty to care is not based upon particular virtues of the health professions, but arises from social reflection on what response to an epidemic would be consistent with our values and our needs, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  40. On citizens' right to information: Justification and analysis of the democratic right to be well informed.Rubén Marciel - 2023 - Journal of Political Philosophy 31 (3):358-384.
    The idea that citizens have a right to receive information that is relevant for their suitable exercise of political rights and liberties is well established in democratic societies. However, this right has never been systematically analyzed, thus remaining a blurry concept. This article tackles this conceptual gap by conceptualizing citizens’ right to information. After reviewing previous approaches to this idea, I locate citizens’ right to information on the map of communication rights, and put forward a systematic framework for both justifying (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. Consent and the ethical duty to participate in health data research.Angela Ballantyne & G. Owen Schaefer - 2018 - Journal of Medical Ethics 44 (6):392-396.
    The predominant view is that a study using health data is observational research and should require individual consent unless it can be shown that gaining consent is impractical. But recent arguments have been made that citizens have an ethical obligation to share their health information for research purposes. In our view, this obligation is sufficient ground to expand the circumstances where secondary use research with identifiable health information is permitted without explicit subject consent. As such, for some studies the Institutional (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  42.  28
    Environmental health research on hazards in the home and the duty to warn.David B. Resnik & Darryl C. Zeldin - 2008 - Bioethics 22 (4):209–217.
    When environmental health researchers study hazards in the home, they often discover information that may be relevant to protecting the health and safety of the research subjects and occupants. This article describes the ethical and legal basis for a duty to warn research subjects and occupants about hazards in the home and explores the extent of this duty. Investigators should inform research subjects and occupants about the results of tests conducted as part of the research protocol only (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  43.  34
    Genetic Privacy: Might There Be a Moral Duty to Share One's Genetic Information?Heidi Malm - 2009 - American Journal of Bioethics 9 (6-7):52-54.
    In discussions about direct-to-consumer availability of genetic testing, much attention has been given to identifying the various risks and benefits that individuals might incur. For example, upon...
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44.  36
    Calvin and the Duty to Respect a Patient's Trust.D. T. Ball - 2014 - Christian Bioethics 20 (1):112-122.
    Contemporary bioethical theory relies upon the concept of informed consent to protect against abuses of patient autonomy. Due to the complexity of the informed consent process, however, many patients rely more on their trust in their health care providers than they do upon their own ability to decide whether or not to give informed consent. Reformation theologian John Calvin placed a strong emphasis on the decision-maker's duty to respect the trust that others repose in the decision-maker. In keeping with (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  22
    Is There a Duty to Use Moral Neurointerventions?Michelle Ciurria - 2019 - Topoi 38 (1):37-47.
    Do we have a duty to use moral neurointerventions to correct deficits in our moral psychology? On their surface, these technologies appear to pose worrisome risks to valuable dimensions of the self, and these risks could conceivably weigh against any prima facie moral duty we have to use these technologies. Focquaert and Schermer :139–151, 2015) argue that neurointerventions pose special risks to the self because they operate passively on the subject’s brain, without her active participation, unlike ‘active’ interventions. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  4
    Access to Information is (Not) a Universal Right in Higher Education: Librarian Ethics and Advocacy.Laurie M. Bridges & Kelly McElroy - 2015 - International Review of Information Ethics 23.
    As a profession, librarians have proclaimed an ethical duty to ensure access to information for all people. However, many barriers exist to fulfilling this duty, including varying levels of education and technology around the globe, the cost of obtaining research information, and the concentration of scholarly publishing in English. This article outlines these barriers, concluding with a call to action for librarians to advocate for multilingual Open Access, to foster international scholarly communities, and to champion Internet access for (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Expanding the Duty to Rescue to Climate Migration.David N. Hoffman, Anne Zimmerman, Camille Castelyn & Srajana Kaikini - 2022 - Voices in Bioethics 8.
    Photo by Jonathan Ford on Unsplash ABSTRACT Since 2008, an average of twenty million people per year have been displaced by weather events. Climate migration creates a special setting for a duty to rescue. A duty to rescue is a moral rather than legal duty and imposes on a bystander to take an active role in preventing serious harm to someone else. This paper analyzes the idea of expanding a duty to rescue to climate migration. We (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Do we have moral duties towards information objects?Philip Brey - 2008 - Ethics and Information Technology 10 (2-3):109-114.
    In this paper, a critique will be developed and an alternative proposed to Luciano Floridi’s approach to Information Ethics (IE). IE is a macroethical theory that is to both serve as a foundation for computer ethics and to guide our overall moral attitude towards the world. The central claims of IE are that everything that exists can be described as an information object, and that all information objects, qua information objects, have intrinsic value and are therefore deserving of moral respect. (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  49.  36
    Precision Livestock Farming and Farmers’ Duties to Livestock.Ian Werkheiser - 2018 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 31 (2):181-195.
    Precision livestock farming promises to allow modern, large-scale farms to replicate, at scale, caring farmers who know their animals. PLF refers to a suite of technologies, some only speculative. The goal is to use networked devices to continuously monitor individual animals on large farms, to compare this information to expected norms, and to use algorithms to manage individual animals automatically. Supporters say this could not only create an artificial version of the partially mythologized image of the good steward caring for (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50. Kant on ‘Good’, the Good, and the Duty to Promote the Highest Good.Pauline Kleingeld - 2016 - In Thomas Höwing (ed.), The Highest Good in Kant’s Philosophy. Boston: De Gruyter. pp. 33-50.
    Many regard Kant’s account of the highest good as a failure. His inclusion of happiness in the highest good, in combination with his claim that it is a duty to promote the highest good, is widely seen as inconsistent. In this essay, I argue that there is a valid argument, based on premises Kant clearly endorses, in defense of his thesis that it is a duty to promote the highest good. I first examine why Kant includes happiness in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000