Results for 'Geometric morphism'

987 found
Order:
  1.  49
    A characterization theorem for geometric logic.Olivia Caramello - 2011 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 162 (4):318-321.
    We establish a criterion for deciding whether a class of structures is the class of models of a geometric theory inside Grothendieck toposes; then we specialize this result to obtain a characterization of the infinitary first-order theories which are geometric in terms of their models in Grothendieck toposes, solving a problem posed by Ieke Moerdijk in 1989.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  23
    What do Freyd’s Toposes Classify?Peter Johnstone - 2013 - Logica Universalis 7 (3):335-340.
    We describe a method for presenting (a topos closely related to) either of Freyd’s topos-theoretic models for the independence of the axiom of choice as the classifying topos for a geometric theory. As an application, we show that no such topos can admit a geometric morphism from a two-valued topos satisfying countable dependent choice.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  13
    Complemented sublocales and open maps.Peter T. Johnstone - 2006 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 137 (1-3):240-255.
    We show that a morphism of locales is open if and only if all its pullbacks are skeletal in the sense of [P.T. Johnstone, Factorization theorems for geometric morphisms, II, in: Categorical Aspects of Topology and Analysis, in: Lecture Notes in Math., vol. 915, Springer-Verlag, 1982, pp. 216–233], i.e. pulling back along them preserves denseness of sublocales . This result may be viewed as the ‘dual’ of the well-known characterization of proper maps as those which are stably closed. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Extended memory evolutive systems in a hyperstructure context.Nils A. Baas - 2009 - Axiomathes 19 (2):215-221.
    This paper is just a comment to the impressive work by A. C. Ehresmann and J.-P. Vanbremeersch on the theory of Memory Evolutive Systems (MES). MES are truly higher order systems. Hyperstructures represent a new concept which I introduced in order to capture the essence of what a higher order structure is—encompassing hierarchies and emergence. Hyperstructures are motivated by cobordism theory in topology and higher category theory. The morphism concept is replaced by the concept of a bond. In the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Polyhedral Completeness of Intermediate Logics: The Nerve Criterion.Sam Adam-day, Nick Bezhanishvili, David Gabelaia & Vincenzo Marra - 2024 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 89 (1):342-382.
    We investigate a recently devised polyhedral semantics for intermediate logics, in which formulas are interpreted in n-dimensional polyhedra. An intermediate logic is polyhedrally complete if it is complete with respect to some class of polyhedra. The first main result of this paper is a necessary and sufficient condition for the polyhedral completeness of a logic. This condition, which we call the Nerve Criterion, is expressed in terms of Alexandrov’s notion of the nerve of a poset. It affords a purely combinatorial (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  43
    State-morphism MV-algebras.Antonio Di Nola & Anatolij Dvurečenskij - 2010 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (2):161-173.
    We present a stronger variation of state MV-algebras, recently presented by T. Flaminio and F. Montagna, which we call state-morphism MV-algebras. Such structures are MV-algebras with an internal notion, a state-morphism operator. We describe the categorical equivalences of such state MV-algebras with the category of unital Abelian ℓ-groups with a fixed state operator and present their basic properties. In addition, in contrast to state MV-algebras, we are able to describe all subdirectly irreducible state-morphism MV-algebras.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  7.  21
    Subdirectly irreducible state-morphism BL-algebras.Anatolij Dvurečenskij - 2011 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 50 (1-2):145-160.
    Recently Flaminio and Montagna (Proceedings of the 5th EUSFLAT Conference, II: 201–206. Ostrava, 2007), (Inter. J. Approx. Reason. 50:138–152, 2009) introduced the notion of a state MV-algebra as an MV-algebra with internal state. We have two kinds: state MV-algebras and state-morphism MV-algebras. These notions were also extended for state BL-algebras in (Soft Comput. doi:10.1007/s00500-010-0571-5). In this paper, we completely describe subdirectly irreducible state-morphism BL-algebras and this generalizes an analogous result for state-morphism MV-algebras presented in (Ann. Pure Appl. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  8.  89
    Geometric Possibility.Gordon Belot - 2011 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    Gordon Belot investigates the distinctive notion of geometric possibility that relationalists rely upon. He examines the prospects for adapting to the geometric case the standard philosophical accounts of the related notion of physical possibility, with particular emphasis on Humean, primitivist, and necessitarian accounts of physical and geometric possibility. This contribution to the debate concerning the nature of space will be of interest not only to philosophers and metaphysicians concerned with space and time, but also to those interested (...)
  9.  72
    Solving Geometric Analogy Problems Through Two‐Stage Analogical Mapping.Andrew Lovett, Emmett Tomai, Kenneth Forbus & Jeffrey Usher - 2009 - Cognitive Science 33 (7):1192-1231.
    Evans’ 1968 ANALOGY system was the first computer model of analogy. This paper demonstrates that the structure mapping model of analogy, when combined with high‐level visual processing and qualitative representations, can solve the same kinds of geometric analogy problems as were solved by ANALOGY. Importantly, the bulk of the computations are not particular to the model of this task but are general purpose: We use our existing sketch understanding system, CogSketch, to compute visual structure that is used by our (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  10.  17
    Geometric Averaging in Consequentialist Ethics.Alfred Harwood - manuscript
    When faced with uncertainty, consequentialists often advocate choosing the option with the largest expected utility, as calculated using the arithmetic average. I provide some arguments to suggest that instead, one should consider choosing the option with the largest geometric average of utility. I explore the difference between these two approaches in a variety of ethical dilemmas and argue that geometric averaging has some appealing properties as a normative decision-making tool.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  28
    Categorial subsystem independence as morphism co-possibility.Zalán Gyenis & Miklós Rédei - 2017 - Communications in Mathematical Physics.
    This paper formulates a notion of independence of subobjects of an object in a general (i.e. not necessarily concrete) category. Subobject independence is the categorial generalization of what is known as subsystem independence in the context of algebraic relativistic quantum field theory. The content of subobject independence formulated in this paper is morphism co-possibility: two subobjects of an object will be defined to be independent if any two morphisms on the two subobjects of an object are jointly implementable by (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  90
    Geometrical Objects as Properties of Sensibles: Aristotle’s Philosophy of Geometry.Emily Katz - 2019 - Phronesis 64 (4):465-513.
    There is little agreement about Aristotle’s philosophy of geometry, partly due to the textual evidence and partly part to disagreement over what constitutes a plausible view. I keep separate the questions ‘What is Aristotle’s philosophy of geometry?’ and ‘Is Aristotle right?’, and consider the textual evidence in the context of Greek geometrical practice, and show that, for Aristotle, plane geometry is about properties of certain sensible objects—specifically, dimensional continuity—and certain properties possessed by actual and potential compass-and-straightedge drawings qua quantitative and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  13.  9
    Geometric Rules in Infinitary Logic.Sara Negri - 2021 - In Ofer Arieli & Anna Zamansky (eds.), Arnon Avron on Semantics and Proof Theory of Non-Classical Logics. Springer Verlag. pp. 265-293.
    Large portions of mathematics such as algebra and geometry can be formalized using first-order axiomatizations. In many cases it is even possible to use a very well-behaved class of first-order axioms, namely, what are called coherent or geometric implications. Such class of axioms can be translated to inference rules that can be added to a sequent calculus while preserving its structural properties. In this work, this fundamental result is extended to their infinitary generalizations as extensions of sequent calculi for (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  14. Geometrical premisses in Aristotle’s Incessu animalium and kind-crossing.Lucas Angioni - 2018 - Anais de Filosofia Clássica 24 (12):53-71.
    At some point in the Incessu Animalium, Aristotle appeals to some geometrical claims in order to explain why animal progression necessarily involves the bending (of the limbs), and this appeal to geometrical claims might be taking as violating the recommendation to avoid “kind-crossing” (as found in the Posterior Analytic). But a very unclear notion of kind-crossing has been assumed in most debates. I will argue that kind-crossing in the Posterior Analytics does not mean any employment of premises from a discipline (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  15.  50
    Geometrical Constructivism and Modal Relationalism: Further Aspects of the Dynamical/Geometrical Debate.James Read - 2020 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 33 (1):23-41.
    I draw together some recent literature on the debate between dynamical versus geometrical approaches to spacetime theories, in order to argue that there exist defensible versions of the geometr...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  16. Geometric foundations of classical yang–mills theory.Gabriel Catren - 2008 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 39 (3):511-531.
    We analyze the geometric foundations of classical Yang-Mills theory by studying the relationships between internal relativity, locality, global/local invariance, and background independence. We argue that internal relativity and background independence are the two independent defining principles of Yang-Mills theory. We show that local gauge invariance -heuristically implemented by means of the gauge argument- is a direct consequence of internal relativity. Finally, we analyze the conceptual meaning of BRST symmetry in terms of the invariance of the gauge fixed theory under (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  17.  14
    On geometric mean fitness: a reply to Takacs and Bourrat.Bengt Autzen & Samir Okasha - 2022 - Biology and Philosophy 37 (5):1-7.
    In a recent paper, Takacs and Bourrat (Biol Philos 37:12, 2022) examine the use of geometric mean reproductive output as a measure of biological fitness. We welcome Takacs and Bourrat’s scrutiny of a fitness definition that some philosophers have adopted uncritically. We also welcome Takacs and Bourrat’s attempt to marry the philosophical literature on fitness with the biological literature on mathematical measures of fitness. However, some of the main claims made by Takacs and Bourrat are not correct, while others (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18. Geometrical objects and figures in practical, pure, and applied geometry.Mario Bacelar Valente - 2020 - Disputatio. Philosophical Research Bulletin 9 (15):33-51.
    The purpose of this work is to address what notion of geometrical object and geometrical figure we have in different kinds of geometry: practical, pure, and applied. Also, we address the relation between geometrical objects and figures when this is possible, which is the case of pure and applied geometry. In practical geometry it turns out that there is no conception of geometrical object.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  64
    Geometrical Method and Aristotle's Account of First Principles.H. D. P. Lee - 1935 - Classical Quarterly 29 (02):113-.
    The object of this paper is to show the predominance of the influence of geometrical ideas in Aristotle's account of first principles in the Posterior Analytics— to show that his analysis of first principles is in its essentials an analysis of the first principles of geometry as he conceived them. My proof of this falls into two parts. I. A consideration of the parallel between Aristotle's and Euclid's account of first principles. II. A comparison between the general movement of thought (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  20. On geometric objects, the non-existence of a gravitational stress-energy tensor, and the uniqueness of the Einstein field equation.Erik Curiel - 2009 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 66:90-102.
    The question of the existence of gravitational stress-energy in general relativity has exercised investigators in the field since the inception of the theory. Folklore has it that no adequate definition of a localized gravitational stress-energetic quantity can be given. Most arguments to that effect invoke one version or another of the Principle of Equivalence. I argue that not only are such arguments of necessity vague and hand-waving but, worse, are beside the point and do not address the heart of the (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  21. Support for Geometric Pooling.Jean Baccelli & Rush T. Stewart - 2023 - Review of Symbolic Logic 16 (1):298-337.
    Supra-Bayesianism is the Bayesian response to learning the opinions of others. Probability pooling constitutes an alternative response. One natural question is whether there are cases where probability pooling gives the supra-Bayesian result. This has been called the problem of Bayes-compatibility for pooling functions. It is known that in a common prior setting, under standard assumptions, linear pooling cannot be nontrivially Bayes-compatible. We show by contrast that geometric pooling can be nontrivially Bayes-compatible. Indeed, we show that, under certain assumptions, (...) and Bayes-compatible pooling are equivalent. Granting supra-Bayesianism its usual normative status, one upshot of our study is thus that, in a certain class of epistemic contexts, geometric pooling enjoys a normative advantage over linear pooling as a social learning mechanism. We discuss the philosophical ramifications of this advantage, which we show to be robust to variations in our statement of the Bayes-compatibility problem. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  22.  47
    Geometric Representations for Minimalist Grammars.Peter Beim Graben & Sabrina Gerth - 2012 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 21 (4):393-432.
    We reformulate minimalist grammars as partial functions on term algebras for strings and trees. Using filler/role bindings and tensor product representations, we construct homomorphisms for these data structures into geometric vector spaces. We prove that the structure-building functions as well as simple processors for minimalist languages can be realized by piecewise linear operators in representation space. We also propose harmony, i.e. the distance of an intermediate processing step from the final well-formed state in representation space, as a measure of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  12
    Geometrical Method and Aristotle's Account of First Principles.H. D. P. Lee - 1935 - Classical Quarterly 29 (2):113-124.
    The object of this paper is to show the predominance of the influence of geometrical ideas in Aristotle's account of first principles in the Posterior Analytics— to show that his analysis of first principles is in its essentials an analysis of the first principles of geometry as he conceived them. My proof of this falls into two parts. I. A consideration of the parallel between Aristotle's and Euclid's account of first principles. II. A comparison between the general movement of thought (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  24. Constructive geometrical reasoning and diagrams.John Mumma - 2012 - Synthese 186 (1):103-119.
    Modern formal accounts of the constructive nature of elementary geometry do not aim to capture the intuitive or concrete character of geometrical construction. In line with the general abstract approach of modern axiomatics, nothing is presumed of the objects that a geometric construction produces. This study explores the possibility of a formal account of geometric construction where the basic geometric objects are understood from the outset to possess certain spatial properties. The discussion is centered around Eu , (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  25.  60
    A geometric introduction to forking and thorn-forking.Hans Adler - 2009 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 9 (1):1-20.
    A ternary relation [Formula: see text] between subsets of the big model of a complete first-order theory T is called an independence relation if it satisfies a certain set of axioms. The primary example is forking in a simple theory, but o-minimal theories are also known to have an interesting independence relation. Our approach in this paper is to treat independence relations as mathematical objects worth studying. The main application is a better understanding of thorn-forking, which turns out to be (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  26. Geometric Pooling: A User's Guide.Richard Pettigrew & Jonathan Weisberg - forthcoming - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.
    Much of our information comes to us indirectly, in the form of conclusions others have drawn from evidence they gathered. When we hear these conclusions, how can we modify our own opinions so as to gain the benefit of their evidence? In this paper we study the method known as geometric pooling. We consider two arguments in its favour, raising several objections to one, and proposing an amendment to the other.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  9
    Geometric Models for Relevant Logics.Greg Restall - 2021 - In Ivo Düntsch & Edwin Mares (eds.), Alasdair Urquhart on Nonclassical and Algebraic Logic and Complexity of Proofs. Springer Verlag. pp. 225-242.
    Alasdair Urquhart’s work on models for relevant logics is distinctive in a number of different ways. One key theme, present in both his undecidability proof for the relevant logic R and his proof of the failure of interpolation in R, is the use of techniques from geometry. In this paper, inspired by Urquhart’s work, I explore ways to generate natural models of R+\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$^+$$\end{document} from geometries, and different constraints that an accessibility relation (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28. Geometrical Axiomatization for Model Complete Theories of Differential Topological Fields.Nicolas Guzy & Cédric Rivière - 2006 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 47 (3):331-341.
    In this paper we give a differential lifting principle which provides a general method to geometrically axiomatize the model companion (if it exists) of some theories of differential topological fields. The topological fields we consider here are in fact topological systems in the sense of van den Dries, and the lifting principle we develop is a generalization of the geometric axiomatization of the theory DCF₀ given by Pierce and Pillay. Moreover, it provides a geometric alternative to the axiomatizations (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29.  22
    Erratum to “State-morphism MV-algebras” [Ann. Pure Appl. Logic 161 (2009) 161–173].Antonio Di Nola, A. Dvurečenskij & Ada Lettieri - 2010 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (12):1605-1607.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  61
    A geometric proof of the completeness of the łukasiewicz calculus.Giovanni Panti - 1995 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 60 (2):563-578.
    We give a self-contained geometric proof of the completeness theorem for the infinite-valued sentential calculus of Łukasiewicz.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  31.  26
    Geometric Objects and Perspectivalism.James Read - 2022 - In James Read & Nicholas J. Teh (eds.), The Philosophy and Physics of Noether's Theorems. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 257-273.
  32. A Geometrical Characterization of the Twin Paradox and its Variants.Gergely Székely - 2010 - Studia Logica 95 (1-2):161 - 182.
    The aim of this paper is to provide a logic-based conceptual analysis of the twin paradox (TwP) theorem within a first-order logic framework. A geometrical characterization of TwP and its variants is given. It is shown that TwP is not logically equivalent to the assumption of the slowing down of moving clocks, and the lack of TwP is not logically equivalent to the Newtonian assumption of absolute time. The logical connection between TwP and a symmetry axiom of special relativity is (...)
    Direct download (13 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  33.  26
    Geometrical approximations to the structure of musical pitch.Roger N. Shepard - 1982 - Psychological Review 89 (4):305-333.
  34.  93
    A geometric approach to quantum mechanics.J. Anandan - 1991 - Foundations of Physics 21 (11):1265-1284.
    It is argued that quantum mechanics is fundamentally a geometric theory. This is illustrated by means of the connection and symplectic structures associated with the projective Hilbert space, using which the geometric phase can be understood. A prescription is given for obtaining the geometric phase from the motion of a time dependent invariant along a closed curve in a parameter space, which may be finite dimensional even for nonadiabatic cyclic evolutions in an infinite dimensional Hilbert space. Using (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  35. Geometrical Method.Ursula Goldenbaum - 2015
    The Geometrical Method The Geometrical Method is the style of proof that was used in Euclid’s proofs in geometry, and that was used in philosophy in Spinoza’s proofs in his Ethics. The term appeared first in 16th century Europe when mathematics was on an upswing due to the new science of mechanics. … Continue reading Geometrical Method →.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  20
    A geometrical interpretation of the Pauli exclusion principle in classical field theory.Antonio F. Rañada - 1985 - Foundations of Physics 15 (1):89-100.
    It is shown that classical Dirac fields with the same couplings obey the Pauli exclusion principle in the following sense: If at a certain time two Dirac fields are in different states, they can never reach the same one. This is geometrically interpreted as analogous to the impossibility of crossing of trajectories in the phase space of a dynamical system. An application is made to a model in which extended particles are represented as solitary waves of a set of several (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  30
    A geometric interpretation of logical formulae.Helena Rasiowa & Andrze Mostowski - 1953 - Studia Logica 1 (1):273-275.
    The aim of this paper is to give a geometric interpretation of quantifiers in the intutionistic predicate calculus. We obtain it treating formulae withn free variables as functions withn arguments which run over an abstract set whereas the values of functions are open subsets of a suitable topological space.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  63
    The Geometrization of Motion: Galileo’s Triangle of Speed and its Various Transformations.Carla Rita Palmerino - 2010 - Early Science and Medicine 15 (4-5):410-447.
    This article analyzes Galileo's mathematization of motion, focusing in particular on his use of geometrical diagrams. It argues that Galileo regarded his diagrams of acceleration not just as a complement to his mathematical demonstrations, but as a powerful heuristic tool. Galileo probably abandoned the wrong assumption of the proportionality between the degree of velocity and the space traversed in accelerated motion when he realized that it was impossible, on the basis of that hypothesis, to build a diagram of the law (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  39.  25
    Greek Geometrical Analysis.Norman Gulley - 1958 - Phronesis 3 (1):1-14.
  40.  39
    A geometric principle of indifference.Lieven Decock, Igor Douven & Marta Sznajder - 2016 - Journal of Applied Logic 19 (2):54-70.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  41.  54
    Geometrical First Principles in Proclus’ Commentary on the First Book of Euclid’s Elements.D. Gregory MacIsaac - 2014 - Phronesis 59 (1):44-98.
    In his commentary on Euclid, Proclus says both that the first principle of geometry are self-evident and that they are hypotheses received from the single, highest, unhypothetical science, which is probably dialectic. The implication of this seems to be that a geometer both does and does not know geometrical truths. This dilemma only exists if we assume that Proclus follows Aristotle in his understanding of these terms. This paper shows that this is not the case, and explains what Proclus himself (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  42.  38
    Geometrization of the physics with teleparallelism. I. The classical interactions.José G. Vargas - 1992 - Foundations of Physics 22 (4):507-526.
    A connection viewed from the perspective of integration has the Bianchi identities as constraints. It is shown that the removal of these constraints admits a natural solution on manifolds endowed with a metric and teleparallelism. In the process, the equations of structure and the Bianchi identities take standard forms of field equations and conservation laws.The Levi-Civita (part of the) connection ends up as the potential for the gravity sector, where the source is geometric and tensorial and contains an explicit (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  43.  16
    Geometric Modal Logic.Brice Halimi - 2023 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 64 (3):377-406.
    The purpose of this paper is to generalize Kripke semantics for propositional modal logic by geometrizing it, that is, by considering the space underlying the collection of all possible worlds as an important semantic feature in its own right, so as to take the idea of accessibility seriously. The resulting new modal semantics is worked out in a setting coming from Riemannian geometry, where Kripke semantics is shown to correspond to a particular case, namely, the discrete one. Several correspondence results, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  6
    Geometric axioms for existentially closed Hasse fields.Piotr Kowalski - 2005 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 135 (1-3):286-302.
    We give geometric axioms for existentially closed Hasse fields. We prove a quantifier elimination result for existentially closed n-truncated Hasse fields and characterize them as reducts of existentially closed Hasse fields.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45. Geometric cardinal invariants, maximal functions and a measure theoretic pigeonhole principle.Juris Steprāns - 2005 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 11 (4):517-525.
    It is shown to be consistent with set theory that every set of reals of size ℵ1 is null yet there are ℵ1 planes in Euclidean 3-space whose union is not null. Similar results will be obtained for other geometric objects. The proof relies on results from harmonic analysis about the boundedness of certain harmonic functions and a measure theoretic pigeonhole principle.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  9
    On Geometric Implications.Amirhossein Akbar Tabatabai - forthcoming - Studia Logica:1-30.
    It is a well-known fact that although the poset of open sets of a topological space is a Heyting algebra, its Heyting implication is not necessarily stable under the inverse image of continuous functions and hence is not a geometric concept. This leaves us wondering if there is any stable family of implications that can be safely called geometric. In this paper, we will first recall the abstract notion of implication as a binary modality introduced in Akbar Tabatabai (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  13
    Joannes Geometres und das Metaphrasieren der Oden.Marc De Groote - 2005 - Byzantinische Zeitschrift 97 (1):95-111.
    Joannes Geometres gehörte als einer der führenden Rhetoriker und Dichter seiner Zeit und als Offizier in der byzantinischen Armee – ϰαί σοφίη θάλλων ϰαί τόλμη ϰϱαδίης – zur politischen und literarischen Elite Konstantinopels. Nicht lange vor dem Jahr 986 wurde er aus dem Militärdienst entlassen; wie er selbst zu verstehen gibt, lag seine Tätigkeit als Soldat und Dichter, die bei seinen Zeitgenossen Neid ausgelöst hätte, diesem Ereignis zugrunde; die wirkliche Ursache war aller Wahrscheinlichkeit nach jedoch seine Sympathie für Basileios Nothos, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  20
    Geometrical Changes: Change and Motion in Aristotle’s Philosophy of Geometry.Chiara Martini - 2023 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (3):385-394.
    Graduate Papers from the 2022 Joint Session. It is often said that Aristotle takes geometrical objects to be absolutely unmovable and unchangeable. However, Greek geometrical practice does appeal to motion and change, and geometers seem to consider their objects apt to be manipulated. In this paper, I examine if and how Aristotle’s philosophy of geometry can account for the geometers’ practices and way of talking. First, I illustrate three different ways in which Greek geometry appeals to change. Second, I examine (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Geometrical Leitmotifs in Carnap’s Early Philosophy.Thomas Mormann - 2007 - In Richard Creath & Michael Friedman (eds.), Cambridge Companion to Rudolf Carnap. Cambridge University Press.
  50.  40
    A geometric foundation for a unified field theory.Nathan Rosen & Gerald E. Tauber - 1984 - Foundations of Physics 14 (2):171-186.
    Generalizing the work of Einstein and Mayer, it is assumed that at each point of space-time there exists an N-dimensional linear vector space with N≥5. This space is decomposed into a four-dimensional tangent space and an (N - 4)-dimensional internal space. On the basis of geometric considerations, one arrives at a number of fields, the field equations being derived from a variational principle. Among the fields obtained there are the electromagnetic field, Yang-Mills gauge fields, and fields that can be (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
1 — 50 / 987