Results for 'Andrew D. Digh'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  9
    Machine Writing, Learning, and the Disappearance of the Pen.Andrew D. Digh & Kevin Cummings - forthcoming - Semiotics:189-203.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  4
    Beyond Behavior: Linguistic Evidence of Cultural Variation in Parental Ethnotheories of Children’s Prosocial Helping.Andrew D. Coppens, Anna I. Corwin & Lucía Alcalá - 2020 - Frontiers in Psychology 11.
    This study examined linguistic patterns in mothers’ reports about their toddlers’ involvement in everyday household work, as a way to understand the parental ethnotheories that may guide children’s prosocial helping and development. Mothers from two cultural groups – US Mexican-heritage families with backgrounds in indigenous American communities and middle-class European American families – were interviewed regarding how their 2- to 3-year-old toddler gets involved in help with everyday household work. The study’s analytic focus was mothers’ responses to interview questions asking (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Anger: Discovering Your Spiritual Ally.Andrew D. Lester - 2007
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  12
    To Swab or Not to Swab: Waiver of Consent to Collect Perianal Specimens from Incapacitated Patients With Severe Burn Injury.Liza Dawson, Andrew D. Ray, Benjamin S. Wilfond & Liza-Marie Johnson - 2024 - American Journal of Bioethics 24 (4):108-109.
    This case is about a study of burn patients that included a request to the IRB for a waiver of consent for perianal specimen collection–a request which ultimately was not approved by a reviewing IR...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  5. Functions in Basic Formal Ontology.Andrew D. Spear, Werner Ceusters & Barry Smith - 2016 - Applied ontology 11 (2):103-128.
    The notion of function is indispensable to our understanding of distinctions such as that between being broken and being in working order (for artifacts) and between being diseased and being healthy (for organisms). A clear account of the ontology of functions and functioning is thus an important desideratum for any top-level ontology intended for application to domains such as engineering or medicine. The benefit of using top-level ontologies in applied ontology can only be realized when each of the categories identified (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  6. The epistemic regress problem.Andrew D. Cling - 2008 - Philosophical Studies 140 (3):401 - 421.
    The best extant statement of the epistemic regress problem makes assumptions that are too strong. An improved version assumes only that that reasons require support, that no proposition is supported only by endless regresses of reasons, and that some proposition is supported. These assumptions are individually plausible but jointly inconsistent. Attempts to explain support by means of unconceptualized sensations, contextually immunized propositions, endless regresses, and holistic coherence all require either additional reasons or an external condition on support that is arbitrary (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  7. Embodied Cognition is Not What you Think it is.Andrew D. Wilson & Sabrina Golonka - 2013 - Frontiers in Psychology 4.
  8.  61
    Epistemic dimensions of gaslighting: peer-disagreement, self-trust, and epistemic injustice.Andrew D. Spear - 2023 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 66 (1):68-91.
    ABSTRACT Miranda Fricker has characterized epistemic injustice as “a kind of injustice in which someone is wronged specifically in her capacity as a knower” (2007, Epistemic injustice: Power & the ethics of knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 20). Gaslighting, where one agent seeks to gain control over another by undermining the other’s conception of herself as an independent locus of judgment and deliberation, would thus seem to be a paradigm example. Yet, in the most thorough analysis of gaslighting to date (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  9. Epistemic dimensions of gaslighting: peer-disagreement, self-trust, and epistemic injustice.Andrew D. Spear - 2018 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 62:1-24.
    ABSTRACTMiranda Fricker has characterized epistemic injustice as “a kind of injustice in which someone is wronged specifically in her capacity as a knower” (2007, Epistemic injustice: Power & the e...
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  10.  5
    Consumer Ethics in a Global Economy: How Buying Here Causes Injustice There. [REVIEW]Andrew D. Bowyer - 2019 - Studies in Christian Ethics 34 (3):387-390.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. The trouble with infinitism.Andrew D. Cling - 2004 - Synthese 138 (1):101 - 123.
    One way to solve the epistemic regress problem would be to show that we can acquire justification by means of an infinite regress. This is infinitism. This view has not been popular, but Peter Klein has developed a sophisticated version of infinitism according to which all justified beliefs depend upon an infinite regress of reasons. Klein's argument for infinitism is unpersuasive, but he successfully responds to the most compelling extant objections to the view. A key component of his position is (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  12. Gaslighting, Confabulation, and Epistemic Innocence.Andrew D. Spear - 2020 - Topoi 39 (1):229-241.
    Recent literature on epistemic innocence develops the idea that a defective cognitive process may nevertheless merit special consideration insofar as it confers an epistemic benefit that would not otherwise be available. For example, confabulation may be epistemically innocent when it makes a subject more likely to form future true beliefs or helps her maintain a coherent self-concept. I consider the role of confabulation in typical cases of interpersonal gaslighting, and argue that confabulation will not be epistemically innocent in such cases (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  13.  27
    Gaslighting, Confabulation, and Epistemic Innocence.Andrew D. Spear - 2020 - Topoi 39 (1):229-241.
    Recent literature on epistemic innocence develops the idea that a defective cognitive process may nevertheless merit special consideration insofar as it confers an epistemic benefit that would not otherwise be available. For example, confabulation may be epistemically innocent when it makes a subject more likely to form future true beliefs or helps her maintain a coherent self-concept. I consider the role of confabulation in typical cases of interpersonal gaslighting, and argue that confabulation will not be epistemically innocent in such cases (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  14. Global health ethics for students.Andrew D. Pinto & Ross E. G. Upshur - 2007 - Developing World Bioethics 9 (1):1-10.
    As a result of increased interest in global health, more and more medical students and trainees from the.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  15. Posing the problem of the criterion.Andrew D. Cling - 1994 - Philosophical Studies 75 (3):261 - 292.
    Although it has been largely neglected in contemporary philosophy , the problem of the criterion raises questions which must be addressed by any complete account of knowledge . But the problem of the criterion suffers not onl.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  16. Counterfactual Similarity, Nomic Indiscernibility, and the Paradox of Quidditism.Andrew D. Bassford & C. Daniel Dolson - 2024 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 67 (1):230-261.
    Aristotle is essentially human; that is, for all possible worlds metaphysically consistent with our own, if Aristotle exists, then he is human. This is a claim about the essential property of an object. The claim that objects have essential properties has been hotly disputed, but for present purposes, we can bracket that issue. In this essay, we are interested, rather, in the question of whether properties themselves have essential properties (or features) for their existence. We call those who suppose they (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  17.  87
    Autonomy, liberalism and state neutrality.Andrew D. Mason - 1990 - Philosophical Quarterly 40 (161):433-452.
  18. Extended Modal Realism — a New Solution to the Problem of Intentional Inexistence.Andrew D. Thomas - 2020 - Philosophia 48 (3):1197-1208.
    Kriegel described the problem of intentional inexistence as one of the ‘perennial problems of philosophy’, 307–340, 2007: 307). In the same paper, Kriegel alluded to a modal realist solution to the problem of intentional inexistence. However, Kriegel does not state by name who defends the kind of modal realist solution he has in mind. Kriegel also points out that even what he believes to be the strongest version of modal realism does not pass the ‘principle of representation’ and thus modal (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  19. Epistemic levels and the problem of the criterion.Andrew D. Cling - 1997 - Philosophical Studies 88 (2):109-140.
    The problem of the criterion says that we can know a proposition only if we first know a criterion of truth and vice versa, hence, we cannot know any proposition or any criterion of truth. The epistemic levels response says that since knowledge does not require knowledge about knowledge, we can know a proposition without knowing a criterion of truth. This response (advocated by Chisholm and Van Cleve) presupposes that criteria of truth are epistemic principles. In general, however, criteria of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  20. The Epistemic Regress Problem, the Problem of the Criterion, and the Value of Reasons.Andrew D. Cling - 2014 - Metaphilosophy 45 (2):161-171.
    There are important similarities between the epistemic regress problem and the problem of the criterion. Each turns on plausible principles stating that epistemic reasons must be supported by epistemic reasons but that having reasons is impossible if that requires having endless regresses of reasons. These principles are incompatible with the possibility of reasons, so each problem is a paradox. Whether there can be an antiskeptical solution to these paradoxes depends upon the kinds of reasons that we need in order to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  21.  83
    The Revisionist Difference Principle.Andrew D. Williams - 1995 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 25 (2):257 - 281.
    John Rawls's famous difference principle is capable of at least four distinct statements, each of which occurs in A Theory of Justice. According to what I shall term the Crude Principle it is a necessary and sufficient condition for the justice of an institutional scheme which expands social and economic inequality that, subject to the satisfaction of more weighty principles, it increases the level of advantage of the least advantaged. Expressing this principle Rawls writes that,Assuming the framework of institutions required (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  22. Justification-affording circular arguments.Andrew D. Cling - 2002 - Philosophical Studies 111 (3):251 - 275.
    An argument whose conclusion C is essential evidence for one of its premises can provide its target audience with justification for believing C. This is possible because we can enhance our justification for believing a proposition C by integrating it into an explanatory network of beliefs for which C itself provides essential evidence. I argue for this in light of relevant features of doxastic circularity, epistemic circularity, and explanatory inferences. Finally, I confirm my argument with an example and respond to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  23.  21
    Lessons from Everyday Lives: A Moral Justification for Acute Care Research.Andrew D. McRae & Charles Weijer - unknown
    Progress in emergency and critical care requires that clinical research be performed on patients who are incapable of granting consent for research participation. Analyses of the ethics of such research have left some questions incompletely answered. Why should we be permitted to expose vulnerable patients to research risks without their consent? In particular, how do we justify research interventions that have no potential benefit for participants (nontherapeutic interventions)? This article presents a moral justification for nontherapeutic interventions in emergency research. By (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  24.  35
    Hertz, Boltzmann and Wittgenstein Reconsidered.Andrew D. Wilson - 1989 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 20 (2):245.
  25. Eliminative materialism and self-referential inconsistency.Andrew D. Cling - 1989 - Philosophical Studies 56 (May):53-75.
  26. When is informed consent required in cluster randomized trials in health research?Andrew D. McRae, Ariella Binik, Charles Weijer, Angela White, Jeremy M. Grimshaw, Robert Boruch, Jamie C. Brehaut, Allan Donner, Martin P. Eccles, Raphael Saginur, Merrick Zwarenstein & Monica Taljaard - 2011 - Trials 1 (12):202.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  27.  70
    Frege on Number Properties.Andrew D. Irvine - 2010 - Studia Logica 96 (2):239-260.
    In the Grundlagen , Frege offers eight main arguments, together with a series of more minor supporting arguments, against Mill’s view that numbers are “properties of external things”. This paper reviews all eight of these arguments, arguing that none are conclusive.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  28. Managing a proactive progressive animal care and use program.Taylor Bennett & Andrew D. Cardon - 2015 - In Whitney Petrie & Sonja L. Wallace (eds.), The care and feeding of an IACUC: the organization and management of an institutional animal care and use committee. Boca Raton: CRC Press, Taylor & Francis Group.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Ambifictional Counterfactuals.Andrew D. Bassford - 2023 - Philosophies 8 (6):108.
    In this paper, I argue that David Lewis’s possible world semantics for counterfactual discourse and for fictional discourse are apparently inconsistent and in need of revision. The problem emerges for Lewis’s account once one considers how to evaluate ambifictional counterfactuals. Since this is likely not a concept familiar to most, and since it does not appear that the problem has been previously recognized in the critical literature, I will begin by rehearsing Lewis’s possible worlds semantics for counterfactuals and fiction. Then (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  12
    Interface Theory vs Gibson: An Ontological Defense of the Ecological Approach.Andrew D. Wilson - 2021 - Philosophical Psychology 34 (7):989-1010.
    Interface theory is the hypothesis that inferential, representational theories of perception entail that fitness, not truth, dictates the evolution of perceptual systems. They show, with simulations, that “veridical” perceptual mappings (ones that preserve at least some of the structure of the world) are routinely out-competed by “non-veridical” interfaces (ones that make no attempt to preserve that structure). They therefore take particular aim at the direct perception, ecological approach to perception and work to show that such a system, even if technically (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31. Self-supporting arguments.Andrew D. Cling - 2003 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 66 (2):279–303.
    Deductive and inductive logic confront this skeptical challenge: we can justify any logical principle only by means of an argument but we can acquire justification by means of an argument only if we are already justified in believing some logical principle. We could solve this problem if probative arguments do not require justified belief in their corresponding conditionals. For if not, then inferential justification would not require justified belief in any logical principle. So even arguments whose corresponding conditionals are epistemically (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  32.  16
    Face, eye, and body selective responses in fusiform gyrus and adjacent cortex: an intracranial EEG study.Andrew D. Engell & Gregory McCarthy - 2014 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 8.
  33.  10
    Toward a More Democratic Ethic of Technological Governance.Andrew D. Zimmerman - 1995 - Science, Technology and Human Values 20 (1):86-107.
    Recent scholarship in technology and society studies has given attention to the notion of technological citizenship. This article seeks to further integrate perspectives on this topic with theoretical contributions about the development of moral autonomy. The author challenges the presumption that the strategy of expanding opportunities for participation in technological decision making will in itself develop people's autonomy and citizenship. He argues that concurrent efforts must be made to democratize the political-economic structures of key technologies and to help people prepare (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  34.  37
    Steps to a neurochemistry of personality.Andrew D. Lawrence, Matthias J. Koepp, Roger N. Gunn, Vincent J. Cunningham & Paul M. Grasby - 1999 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (3):528-529.
    Depue & Collins's (D&C's) work relies on extrapolation from data obtained through studies in experimental animals, and needs support from studies of the role of dopamine (DA) neurotransmission in human behaviour. Here we review evidence from two sources: (1) studies of patients with Parkinson's disease and (2) positron emission tomography (PET) studies of DA neurotransmission, which we believe lend support to Depue & Collins's theory, and which can potentially form the basis for a true neurochemistry of personality.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Lucas, Lewis, and mechanism -- one more time.Andrew D. Irvine - 1983 - Analysis 43 (March):94-98.
  36.  29
    Ideas: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology. [REVIEW]Andrew D. Osborn - 1932 - Journal of Philosophy 29 (6):163-167.
  37.  20
    Harmless Naturalism: The Limits of Science and the Nature of Philosophy.Andrew D. Cling - 1998 - Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 62 (2):493-495.
  38.  41
    A Case for Criminal Negligence.Andrew D. Leipold - 2010 - Law and Philosophy 29 (4):455-468.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  48
    Harmonizing Leibniz’s Ontology.Andrew D. H. Stumpf - 2012 - Dialogue 51 (3):467-483.
    I propose a novel compatibilist interpretation of Leibniz’s mature views concerning what is metaphysically basic. Drawing on a compatibilist reading of Aristotle on primary substance in the Categories and Metaphysics Z, I argue that Leibniz is working with two complementary ways of being metaphysically basic—one applying to immaterial monads, the other to corporeal substances. Although corporeal substances derive their status as basic from their dominant monads, they are nevertheless fully real, unified, and genuinely capable of acting. This perspective respects Leibniz’s (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  23
    Harmonizing Leibniz’s Ontology.Andrew D. H. Stumpf - 2012 - Dialogue 51 (3):467-483.
    I propose a novel compatibilist interpretation of Leibniz’s mature views concerning what is metaphysically basic. Drawing on a compatibilist reading of Aristotle on primary substance in the Categories and Metaphysics Z, I argue that Leibniz is working with two complementary ways of being metaphysically basic—one applying to immaterial monads, the other to corporeal substances. Although corporeal substances derive their status as basic from their dominant monads, they are nevertheless fully real, unified, and genuinely capable of acting. This perspective respects Leibniz’s (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. The almighty God in the Lord Jesus Christ.Andrew D. Urshan - 1919 - In Donald W. Dayton, Andrew D. Urshan, Frank J. Ewart & G. T. Haywood (eds.), Seven "Jesus only" tracts. New York: Garland.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  46
    Breaking the epistemic pornography habit.Andrew D. Spear - 2019 - Journal of Information, Communication and Ethics in Society 18 (1):83-104.
    Purpose This paper aims to analyze some of the epistemically pernicious effects of the use of the internet and social media. In light of this analysis, it introduces the concept of epistemic pornography and argues that epistemic agents both can and should avoid consuming and sharing epistemic pornography. Design/methodology/approach The paper draws on research on epistemic virtue, cognitive biases, social media use and its epistemic consequences, fake news, paternalistic nudging, pornography, moral philosophy, moral elevation and moral exemplar theory to analyze (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  12
    Bertrand Russell's Logic.Andrew D. Irvine - 2009 - In Dov Gabbay (ed.), The Handbook of the History of Logic. Elsevier. pp. 5--1.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  16
    Remediation.Andrew D. Harding & Mark W. Connolly - 2012 - Jona’s Healthcare Law, Ethics, and Regulation 14 (2):48-52.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  26
    Nurses' Risk Without Using Smart Pumps.Andrew D. Harding, Mark W. Connolly & Timothy O. Wilkerson - 2011 - Jona's Healthcare Law, Ethics, and Regulation 13 (1):17-20.
  46. The doctrine of the new birth, or, the perfect way to eternal life.Andrew D. Urshan - 1919 - In Donald W. Dayton, Andrew D. Urshan, Frank J. Ewart & G. T. Haywood (eds.), Seven "Jesus only" tracts. New York: Garland.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  23
    Public Health Research, Deception, and Distrust.Andrew D. Plunk & Richard A. Grucza - 2013 - American Journal of Bioethics 13 (11):54-55.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48.  95
    Husserl on Intentionality and Intentional Content.Andrew D. Spear - 2011 - Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Edmund Husserl (1859—1938) was an influential thinker of the first half of the twentieth century. His philosophy was heavily influenced by the works of Franz Brentano and Bernard Bolzano, and was also influenced in various ways by interaction with contemporaries such as Alexius Meinong, Kasimir Twardowski, and Gottlob Frege. In his own right, Husserl is considered the founder of twentieth century Phenomenology with influence extending to thinkers such as Martin Heidegger, Jean-Paul Sartre, Maurice Merleau-Ponty, and to contemporary continental philosophy generally. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Tommaso Piazza, A Priori Knowledge: Toward a Phenomenological Explanation.Andrew D. Spear - 2009 - Philosophy in Review 29 (2):127.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  11
    Geschichte der Logik.Andrew D. Osborn - 1932 - Journal of Philosophy 29 (25):695.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000