Results for ' proof size'

995 found
Order:
  1.  7
    Ramsey’s theorem for pairs, collection, and proof size.Leszek Aleksander Kołodziejczyk, Tin Lok Wong & Keita Yokoyama - 2023 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 24 (2).
    We prove that any proof of a [Formula: see text] sentence in the theory [Formula: see text] can be translated into a proof in [Formula: see text] at the cost of a polynomial increase in size. In fact, the proof in [Formula: see text] can be obtained by a polynomial-time algorithm. On the other hand, [Formula: see text] has nonelementary speedup over the weaker base theory [Formula: see text] for proofs of [Formula: see text] sentences. We (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  38
    Polynomial size proofs of the propositional pigeonhole principle.Samuel R. Buss - 1987 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 52 (4):916-927.
    Cook and Reckhow defined a propositional formulation of the pigeonhole principle. This paper shows that there are Frege proofs of this propositional pigeonhole principle of polynomial size. This together with a result of Haken gives another proof of Urquhart's theorem that Frege systems have an exponential speedup over resolution. We also discuss connections to provability in theories of bounded arithmetic.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  3. Lower Bounds to the size of constant-depth propositional proofs.Jan Krajíček - 1994 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 59 (1):73-86.
    LK is a natural modification of Gentzen sequent calculus for propositional logic with connectives ¬ and $\bigwedge, \bigvee$. Then for every d ≥ 0 and n ≥ 2, there is a set Td n of depth d sequents of total size O which are refutable in LK by depth d + 1 proof of size exp) but such that every depth d refutation must have the size at least exp). The sets Td n express a weaker (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  4.  30
    Quasipolynomial size Frege proofs of frankl’s theorem on the trace of sets.James Aisenberg, Maria Luisa Bonet & Sam Buss - 2016 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 81 (2):687-710.
    We extend results of Bonet, Buss and Pitassi on Bondy’s Theorem and of Nozaki, Arai and Arai on Bollobás’ Theorem by proving that Frankl’s Theorem on the trace of sets has quasipolynomial size Frege proofs. For constant values of the parametert, we prove that Frankl’s Theorem has polynomial size AC0-Frege proofs from instances of the pigeonhole principle.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  24
    Separation results for the size of constant-depth propositional proofs.Arnold Beckmann & Samuel R. Buss - 2005 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 136 (1-2):30-55.
    This paper proves exponential separations between depth d-LK and depth -LK for every utilizing the order induction principle. As a consequence, we obtain an exponential separation between depth d-LK and depth -LK for . We investigate the relationship between the sequence-size, tree-size and height of depth d-LK-derivations for , and describe transformations between them. We define a general method to lift principles requiring exponential tree-size -LK-refutations for to principles requiring exponential sequence-size d-LK-refutations, which will be described (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  6.  32
    The number of proof lines and the size of proofs in first order logic.Jan Krajíček & Pavel Pudlák - 1988 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 27 (1):69-84.
  7.  10
    Proof Systems for Two-Way Modal Mu-Calculus.Bahareh Afshari, Sebastian Enqvist, Graham E. Leigh, Johannes Marti & Yde Venema - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-50.
    We present sound and complete sequent calculi for the modal mu-calculus with converse modalities, aka two-way modal mu-calculus. Notably, we introduce a cyclic proof system wherein proofs can be represented as finite trees with back-edges, i.e., finite graphs. The sequent calculi incorporate ordinal annotations and structural rules for managing them. Soundness is proved with relative ease as is the case for the modal mu-calculus with explicit ordinals. The main ingredients in the proof of completeness are isolating a class (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. Consistency proof of a fragment of pv with substitution in bounded arithmetic.Yoriyuki Yamagata - 2018 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 83 (3):1063-1090.
    This paper presents proof that Buss's S22 can prove the consistency of a fragment of Cook and Urquhart's PV from which induction has been removed but substitution has been retained. This result improves Beckmann's result, which proves the consistency of such a system without substitution in bounded arithmetic S12. Our proof relies on the notion of "computation" of the terms of PV. In our work, we first prove that, in the system under consideration, if an equation is proved (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  59
    Proof complexity of propositional default logic.Olaf Beyersdorff, Arne Meier, Sebastian Müller, Michael Thomas & Heribert Vollmer - 2011 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 50 (7-8):727-742.
    Default logic is one of the most popular and successful formalisms for non-monotonic reasoning. In 2002, Bonatti and Olivetti introduced several sequent calculi for credulous and skeptical reasoning in propositional default logic. In this paper we examine these calculi from a proof-complexity perspective. In particular, we show that the calculus for credulous reasoning obeys almost the same bounds on the proof size as Gentzen’s system LK. Hence proving lower bounds for credulous reasoning will be as hard as (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10.  55
    Proof Compression and NP Versus PSPACE.L. Gordeev & E. H. Haeusler - 2019 - Studia Logica 107 (1):53-83.
    We show that arbitrary tautologies of Johansson’s minimal propositional logic are provable by “small” polynomial-size dag-like natural deductions in Prawitz’s system for minimal propositional logic. These “small” deductions arise from standard “large” tree-like inputs by horizontal dag-like compression that is obtained by merging distinct nodes labeled with identical formulas occurring in horizontal sections of deductions involved. The underlying geometric idea: if the height, h(∂), and the total number of distinct formulas, ϕ(∂), of a given tree-like deduction ∂ of a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  11.  20
    Jan Krajíček and Pavel Pudlák. The number of proof lines and the size of proofs in first order logic. Archive for mathematical logic, vol. 27 , pp. 69–84. [REVIEW]William M. Farmer - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (3):1107-1108.
  12.  27
    Proof Compression and NP Versus PSPACE II.Lew Gordeev & Edward Hermann Haeusler - 2020 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 49 (3):213-230.
    We upgrade [3] to a complete proof of the conjecture NP = PSPACE that is known as one of the fundamental open problems in the mathematical theory of computational complexity; this proof is based on [2]. Since minimal propositional logic is known to be PSPACE complete, while PSPACE to include NP, it suffices to show that every valid purely implicational formula ρ has a proof whose weight and time complexity of the provability involved are both polynomial in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  9
    Monotone Proofs of the Pigeon Hole Principle.R. Gavalda, A. Atserias & N. Galesi - 2001 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 47 (4):461-474.
    We study the complexity of proving the Pigeon Hole Principle in a monotone variant of the Gentzen Calculus, also known as Geometric Logic. We prove a size-depth trade-off upper bound for monotone proofs of the standard encoding of the PHP as a monotone sequent. At one extreme of the trade-off we get quasipolynomia -size monotone proofs, and at the other extreme we get subexponential-size bounded-depth monotone proofs. This result is a consequence of deriving the basic properties of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14. The complexity of propositional proofs.Alasdair Urquhart - 1995 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 1 (4):425-467.
    Propositional proof complexity is the study of the sizes of propositional proofs, and more generally, the resources necessary to certify propositional tautologies. Questions about proof sizes have connections with computational complexity, theories of arithmetic, and satisfiability algorithms. This is article includes a broad survey of the field, and a technical exposition of some recently developed techniques for proving lower bounds on proof sizes.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  15.  75
    Parity Proofs of the Bell-Kochen-Specker Theorem Based on the 600-cell.Mordecai Waegell, P. K. Aravind, Norman D. Megill & Mladen Pavičić - 2011 - Foundations of Physics 41 (5):883-904.
    The set of 60 real rays in four dimensions derived from the vertices of a 600-cell is shown to possess numerous subsets of rays and bases that provide basis-critical parity proofs of the Bell-Kochen-Specker (BKS) theorem (a basis-critical proof is one that fails if even a single basis is deleted from it). The proofs vary considerably in size, with the smallest having 26 rays and 13 bases and the largest 60 rays and 41 bases. There are at least (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  16.  71
    The complexity of propositional proofs.Nathan Segerlind - 2007 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 13 (4):417-481.
    Propositional proof complexity is the study of the sizes of propositional proofs, and more generally, the resources necessary to certify propositional tautologies. Questions about proof sizes have connections with computational complexity, theories of arithmetic, and satisfiability algorithms. This is article includes a broad survey of the field, and a technical exposition of some recently developed techniques for proving lower bounds on proof sizes.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  17.  18
    Propositional proof compressions and DNF logic.L. Gordeev, E. Haeusler & L. Pereira - 2011 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 19 (1):62-86.
    This paper is a continuation of dag-like proof compression research initiated in [9]. We investigate proof compression phenomenon in a particular, most transparent case of propositional DNF Logic. We define and analyze a very efficient semi-analytic sequent calculus SEQ*0 for propositional DNF. The efficiency is achieved by adding two special rules CQ and CS; the latter rule is a variant of the weakened substitution rule WS from [9], while the former one being specially designed for DNF sequents. We (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18.  86
    Granularity Analysis for Mathematical Proofs.Marvin R. G. Schiller - 2013 - Topics in Cognitive Science 5 (2):251-269.
    Mathematical proofs generally allow for various levels of detail and conciseness, such that they can be adapted for a particular audience or purpose. Using automated reasoning approaches for teaching proof construction in mathematics presupposes that the step size of proofs in such a system is appropriate within the teaching context. This work proposes a framework that supports the granularity analysis of mathematical proofs, to be used in the automated assessment of students' proof attempts and for the presentation (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  38
    Ontological Proof and the Critique of Religious Experience.Florin Lobont - 2010 - Journal for the Study of Religions and Ideologies 9 (27):157-174.
    Normal 0 false false false MicrosoftInternetExplorer4 /* Style Definitions */ table.MsoNormalTable {mso-style-name:"Table Normal"; mso-tstyle-rowband-size:0; mso-tstyle-colband-size:0; mso-style-noshow:yes; mso-style-parent:""; mso-padding-alt:0in 5.4pt 0in 5.4pt; mso-para-margin:0in; mso-para-margin-bottom:.0001pt; mso-pagination:widow-orphan; font-size:10.0pt; font-family:"Times New Roman"; mso-ansi-language:#0400; mso-fareast-language:#0400; mso-bidi-language:#0400;} Focusing mainly on a number of unpublished texts by Collingwood, especially his “Lectures on the Ontological Proof of the Existence of God,” the study examines the English philosopher’s innovative interpretation of the Anselm’s main contribution to the philosophical-theological tradition. Collingwood insightfully shows how the ontological argument (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  46
    Implicit Proofs.Jan Krajíček - 2004 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 69 (2):387 - 397.
    We describe a general method how to construct from a propositional proof system P a possibly much stronger proof system iP. The system iP operates with exponentially long P-proofs described "implicitly" by polynomial size circuits. As an example we prove that proof system iEF, implicit EF, corresponds to bounded arithmetic theory $V_{2}^{1}$ and hence, in particular, polynomially simulates the quantified propositional calculus G and the $\pi_{1}^{b}-consequences$ of $S_{2}^{1}$ proved with one use of exponentiation. Furthermore, the soundness (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  21. A tough nut for proof procedures.John McCarthy - unknown
    Here's the article which was a 1964 Stanford AI Memo. After the original memo, several people offered different proofs of the theorem including Shmuel Winograd, Marvin Minsky and Dimitri Stefanyuk - none published, to my knowledge. Winograd claimed that his proof was non-creative, because it didn't use an extraneous idea like the colors of the squares. This set off a contest to see who could produce the most non-creative proof. Minsky's idea was to start with the diagonal next (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22.  42
    A note on propositional proof complexity of some Ramsey-type statements.Jan Krajíček - 2011 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 50 (1-2):245-255.
    A Ramsey statement denoted \documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${n \longrightarrow (k)^2_2}$$\end{document} says that every undirected graph on n vertices contains either a clique or an independent set of size k. Any such valid statement can be encoded into a valid DNF formula RAM(n, k) of size O(nk) and with terms of size \documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\left(\begin{smallmatrix}k\\2\end{smallmatrix}\right)}$$\end{document}. Let rk be the minimal n for which the statement holds. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. How to think about informal proofs.Brendan Larvor - 2012 - Synthese 187 (2):715-730.
    It is argued in this study that (i) progress in the philosophy of mathematical practice requires a general positive account of informal proof; (ii) the best candidate is to think of informal proofs as arguments that depend on their matter as well as their logical form; (iii) articulating the dependency of informal inferences on their content requires a redefinition of logic as the general study of inferential actions; (iv) it is a decisive advantage of this conception of logic that (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  24.  30
    Propositional consistency proofs.Samuel R. Buss - 1991 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 52 (1-2):3-29.
    Partial consistency statements can be expressed as polynomial-size propositional formulas. Frege proof systems have polynomial-size partial self-consistency proofs. Frege proof systems have polynomial-size proofs of partial consistency of extended Frege proof systems if and only if Frege proof systems polynomially simulate extended Frege proof systems. We give a new proof of Reckhow's theorem that any two Frege proof systems p-simulate each other. The proofs depend on polynomial size propositional formulas (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  25.  23
    Forcing Complexity: Minimum Sizes of Forcing Conditions.Toshio Suzuki - 2001 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 42 (2):117-120.
    This note is a continuation of our former paper ''Complexity of the r-query tautologies in the presence of a generic oracle.'' We give a very short direct proof of the nonexistence of t-generic oracles, a result obtained first by Dowd. We also reconstitute a proof of Dowd's result that the class of all r-generic oracles in his sense has Lebesgue measure one.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26.  17
    A parity-based Frege proof for the symmetric pigeonhole principle.Steve Firebaugh - 1993 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 34 (4):597-601.
    Sam Buss produced the first polynomial size Frege proof of thepigeonhole principle. We introduce a variation of that problem and producea simpler proof based on parity. The proof appearing here has an upperbound that is quadratic in the size of the input formula.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  9
    Information in propositional proofs and algorithmic proof search.Jan Krajíček - 2022 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 87 (2):852-869.
    We study from the proof complexity perspective the proof search problem : •Is there an optimal way to search for propositional proofs?We note that, as a consequence of Levin’s universal search, for any fixed proof system there exists a time-optimal proof search algorithm. Using classical proof complexity results about reflection principles we prove that a time-optimal proof search algorithm exists without restricting proof systems iff a p-optimal proof system exists.To characterize precisely the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  11
    The Complexity of Propositional Proofs with the Substitution Rule.Alasdair Urquhart - 2005 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 13 (3):287-291.
    We prove that for sufficiently large N, there are tautologies of size O that require proofs containing Ω lines in axiomatic systems of propositional logic based on axioms and the rule of substitution for single variables. These tautologies have proofs with O lines in systems with the multiple substitution rule.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  25
    On the proof complexity of the nisan–wigderson generator based on a hard np ∩ conp function.Jan Krajíček - 2011 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 11 (1):11-27.
    Let g be a map defined as the Nisan–Wigderson generator but based on an NP ∩ coNP -function f. Any string b outside the range of g determines a propositional tautology τb expressing this fact. Razborov [27] has conjectured that if f is hard on average for P/poly then these tautologies have no polynomial size proofs in the Extended Frege system EF. We consider a more general Statement that the tautologies have no polynomial size proofs in any propositional (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  30.  61
    Do Reichenbachian Common Cause Systems of Arbitrary Finite Size Exist?Claudio Mazzola & Peter W. Evans - 2017 - Foundations of Physics 47 (12):1543-1558.
    The principle of common cause asserts that positive correlations between causally unrelated events ought to be explained through the action of some shared causal factors. Reichenbachian common cause systems are probabilistic structures aimed at accounting for cases where correlations of the aforesaid sort cannot be explained through the action of a single common cause. The existence of Reichenbachian common cause systems of arbitrary finite size for each pair of non-causally correlated events was allegedly demonstrated by Hofer-Szabó and Rédei in (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  31.  41
    Planar and braided proof-nets for multiplicative linear logic with mix.G. Bellin & A. Fleury - 1998 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 37 (5-6):309-325.
    We consider a class of graphs embedded in $R^2$ as noncommutative proof-nets with an explicit exchange rule. We give two characterization of such proof-nets, one representing proof-nets as CW-complexes in a two-dimensional disc, the other extending a characterization by Asperti. As a corollary, we obtain that the test of correctness in the case of planar graphs is linear in the size of the data. Braided proof-nets are proof-nets for multiplicative linear logic with Mix embedded (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32. Interpolation theorems, lower Bounds for proof systems, and independence results for bounded arithmetic.Jan Krajíček - 1997 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 62 (2):457-486.
    A proof of the (propositional) Craig interpolation theorem for cut-free sequent calculus yields that a sequent with a cut-free proof (or with a proof with cut-formulas of restricted form; in particular, with only analytic cuts) with k inferences has an interpolant whose circuit-size is at most k. We give a new proof of the interpolation theorem based on a communication complexity approach which allows a similar estimate for a larger class of proofs. We derive from (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  33.  11
    On the Existence of Strong Proof Complexity Generators.Jan Krajíček - 2024 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 30 (1):20-40.
    Cook and Reckhow [5] pointed out that $\mathcal {N}\mathcal {P} \neq co\mathcal {N}\mathcal {P}$ iff there is no propositional proof system that admits polynomial size proofs of all tautologies. The theory of proof complexity generators aims at constructing sets of tautologies hard for strong and possibly for all proof systems. We focus on a conjecture from [16] in foundations of the theory that there is a proof complexity generator hard for all proof systems. This (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  7
    Formal Methods for Nonmonotonic and Related Logics: Vol I: Preference and Size.Karl Schlechta - 2018 - Cham: Springer Verlag.
    The two volumes in this advanced textbook present results, proof methods, and translations of motivational and philosophical considerations to formal constructions. In this Vol. I the author explains preferential structures and abstract size. In the associated Vol. II he presents chapters on theory revision and sums, defeasible inheritance theory, interpolation, neighbourhood semantics and deontic logic, abstract independence, and various aspects of nonmonotonic and other logics. In both volumes the text contains many exercises and some solutions, and the author (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  23
    An exponential lower bound for a constraint propagation proof system based on ordered binary decision diagrams.Jan Krajíček - 2008 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 73 (1):227-237.
    We prove an exponential lower bound on the size of proofs in the proof system operating with ordered binary decision diagrams introduced by Atserias, Kolaitis and Vardi [2]. In fact, the lower bound applies to semantic derivations operating with sets defined by OBDDs. We do not assume any particular format of proofs or ordering of variables, the hard formulas are in CNF. We utilize (somewhat indirectly) feasible interpolation. We define a proof system combining resolution and the OBDD (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  36.  19
    Combinatorics of first order structures and propositional proof systems.Jan Krajíček - 2004 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 43 (4):427-441.
    We define the notion of a combinatorics of a first order structure, and a relation of covering between first order structures and propositional proof systems. Namely, a first order structure M combinatorially satisfies an L-sentence Φ iff Φ holds in all L-structures definable in M. The combinatorics Comb(M) of M is the set of all sentences combinatorially satisfied in M. Structure M covers a propositional proof system P iff M combinatorially satisfies all Φ for which the associated sequence (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  37.  33
    On the computational content of intuitionistic propositional proofs.Samuel R. Buss & Pavel Pudlák - 2001 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 109 (1-2):49-64.
    The paper proves refined feasibility properties for the disjunction property of intuitionistic propositional logic. We prove that it is possible to eliminate all cuts from an intuitionistic proof, propositional or first-order, without increasing the Horn closure of the proof. We obtain a polynomial time, interactive, realizability algorithm for propositional intuitionistic proofs. The feasibility of the disjunction property is proved for sequents containing Harrop formulas. Under hardness assumptions for NP and for factoring, it is shown that the intuitionistic propositional (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  38.  10
    On obdd-based algorithms and proof systems that dynamically change the order of variables.Dmitry Itsykson, Alexander Knop, Andrei Romashchenko & Dmitry Sokolov - 2020 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 85 (2):632-670.
    In 2004 Atserias, Kolaitis, and Vardi proposed $\text {OBDD}$ -based propositional proof systems that prove unsatisfiability of a CNF formula by deduction of an identically false $\text {OBDD}$ from $\text {OBDD}$ s representing clauses of the initial formula. All $\text {OBDD}$ s in such proofs have the same order of variables. We initiate the study of $\text {OBDD}$ based proof systems that additionally contain a rule that allows changing the order in $\text {OBDD}$ s. At first we consider (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  25
    Structural reflection, shrewd cardinals and the size of the continuum.Philipp Lücke - 2022 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 22 (2).
    Journal of Mathematical Logic, Volume 22, Issue 02, August 2022. Motivated by results of Bagaria, Magidor and Väänänen, we study characterizations of large cardinal properties through reflection principles for classes of structures. More specifically, we aim to characterize notions from the lower end of the large cardinal hierarchy through the principle [math] introduced by Bagaria and Väänänen. Our results isolate a narrow interval in the large cardinal hierarchy that is bounded from below by total indescribability and from above by subtleness, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  23
    The number of lines in Frege proofs with substitution.Alasdair Urquhart - 1997 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 37 (1):15-19.
    We prove that for sufficiently large \documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document} $n$\end{document}, there are tautologies of size \documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document} $O(n)$\end{document} that require proofs containing \documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document} $\Omega( n / \log n )$\end{document} lines in axiomatic systems of propositional logic based on the rules of substitution and detachment.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  30
    Duplication of directed graphs and exponential blow up of proofs.A. Carbone - 1999 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 100 (1-3):1-67.
    We develop a combinatorial model to study the evolution of graphs underlying proofs during the process of cut elimination. Proofs are two-dimensional objects and differences in the behavior of their cut elimination can often be accounted for by differences in their two-dimensional structure. Our purpose is to determine geometrical conditions on the graphs of proofs to explain the expansion of the size of proofs after cut elimination. We will be concerned with exponential expansion and we give upper and lower (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  42.  30
    Discretely ordered modules as a first-order extension of the cutting planes proof system.Jan Krajíček - 1998 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 63 (4):1582-1596.
    We define a first-order extension LK(CP) of the cutting planes proof system CP as the first-order sequent calculus LK whose atomic formulas are CP-inequalities ∑ i a i · x i ≥ b (x i 's variables, a i 's and b constants). We prove an interpolation theorem for LK(CP) yielding as a corollary a conditional lower bound for LK(CP)-proofs. For a subsystem R(CP) of LK(CP), essentially resolution working with clauses formed by CP- inequalities, we prove a monotone interpolation (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  43.  24
    Resolution over linear equations and multilinear proofs.Ran Raz & Iddo Tzameret - 2008 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 155 (3):194-224.
    We develop and study the complexity of propositional proof systems of varying strength extending resolution by allowing it to operate with disjunctions of linear equations instead of clauses. We demonstrate polynomial-size refutations for hard tautologies like the pigeonhole principle, Tseitin graph tautologies and the clique-coloring tautologies in these proof systems. Using interpolation we establish an exponential-size lower bound on refutations in a certain, considerably strong, fragment of resolution over linear equations, as well as a general polynomial (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44.  44
    On meta complexity of propositional formulas and propositional proofs.Pavel Naumov - 2008 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 47 (1):35-52.
    A new approach to defining complexity of propositional formulas and proofs is suggested. Instead of measuring the size of these syntactical structures in the propositional language, the article suggests to define the complexity by the size of external descriptions of such constructions. The main result is a lower bound on proof complexity with respect to this new definition of complexity.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  59
    Upper bounds on complexity of Frege proofs with limited use of certain schemata.Pavel Naumov - 2006 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 45 (4):431-446.
    The paper considers a commonly used axiomatization of the classical propositional logic and studies how different axiom schemata in this system contribute to proof complexity of the logic. The existence of a polynomial bound on proof complexity of every statement provable in this logic is a well-known open question.The axiomatization consists of three schemata. We show that any statement provable using unrestricted number of axioms from the first of the three schemata and polynomially-bounded in size set of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  27
    On transformations of constant depth propositional proofs.Arnold Beckmann & Sam Buss - 2019 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 170 (10):1176-1187.
    This paper studies the complexity of constant depth propositional proofs in the cedent and sequent calculus. We discuss the relationships between the size of tree-like proofs, the size of dag-like proofs, and the heights of proofs. The main result is to correct a proof construction in an earlier paper about transformations from proofs with polylogarithmic height and constantly many formulas per cedent.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  71
    On the calibration of a size-structured population model from experimental data.Jorge P. Zubelli - 2010 - Acta Biotheoretica 58 (4):405-413.
    The aim of this work is twofold. First, we survey the techniques developed in Perthame and Zubelli (Inverse Probl 23(3):1037–1052, 2007 ), Doumic et al. (Inverse Probl 25, 2009 ) to reconstruct the division (birth) rate from the cell volume distribution data in certain structured population structured population models. Secondly, we implement such techniques on experimental cell volume distributions available in the literature so as to validate the theoretical and numerical results. As a proof of concept, we use the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. On the concept of proof in elementary geometry Pirmin stekeler-weithofer.Proof In Elementary - 1992 - In Michael Detlefsen (ed.), Proof and Knowledge in Mathematics. New York: Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  92
    Constructing a Reward-Related Quality of Life Statistic in Daily Life—a Proof of Concept Study Using Positive Affect.Simone J. W. Verhagen, Claudia J. P. Simons, Catherine van Zelst & Philippe A. E. G. Delespaul - 2017 - Frontiers in Psychology 8:294592.
    Background: Mental healthcare needs person-tailored interventions. Experience Sampling Method (ESM) can provide daily life monitoring of personal experiences. This study aims to operationalize and test a measure of momentary reward-related Quality of Life (rQoL). Intuitively, quality of life improves by spending more time on rewarding experiences. ESM clinical interventions can use this information to coach patients to find a realistic, optimal balance of positive experiences (maximize reward) in daily life. rQoL combines the frequency of engaging in a relevant context (a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  52
    John L. BELL. Set theory: Boolean-valued models and independence proofs. Oxford: Clarendon press, 2005. Oxford logic guides, no. 47. pp. XXII + 191. ISBN 0-19-856852-5, 987-0-19-856852-0 (pbk). [REVIEW]Patricia Marino - 2006 - Philosophia Mathematica 14 (3):392-394.
    This is the third edition of a book originally published in the 1970s; it provides a systematic and nicely organized presentation of the elegant method of using Boolean-valued models to prove independence results. Four things are new in the third edition: background material on Heyting algebras, a chapter on ‘Boolean-valued analysis’, one on using Heyting algebras to understand intuitionistic set theory, and an appendix explaining how Boolean and Heyting algebras look from the perspective of category theory. The book presents results (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 995