Results for ' possessive pronoun'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Tertiumne datur? Possessive pronouns and the bipartition of the lexicon.T. E. Zimmerman - 2004 - In Hans Kamp & Barbara Hall Partee (eds.), Context-dependence in the analysis of linguistic meaning. Boston: Elsevier. pp. 319--332.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  2.  14
    Effects of ownership expressed by the first-person possessive pronoun.Zhan Shi, Aibao Zhou, Wei Han & Peiru Liu - 2011 - Consciousness and Cognition 20 (3):951-955.
    The present study examined the behavioral effects of the first-person possessive pronoun. In each trial, a noun was presented to participants after visual presentation of a possessive pronoun “wo de” or “ta de” , which formed ownership. Half participants were assigned to contextual encoding condition in which they were required to judge whether they liked the item expressed by a noun from the first or third-person perspective. The rest were assigned to perceptual encoding condition in which (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  3.  7
    The Position of the Possessive Pronoun in Cicero's Orations. (A dissertation submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy of the Graduate College of the State University of Iowa.) By Edgar Allen Menk. Pp. 71. Grand Forks, North Dakota: Normanden Publishing Company, 1925. [REVIEW]J. B. Poynton - 1926 - The Classical Review 40 (06):219-.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  1
    Aristotle and individual forms: The grammar of the possessive pronouns at metaphysicsλ.5, 1071a27–9.David Konstan & Ilaria Ramelli - 2006 - Classical Quarterly 56 (1):105-112.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  5
    The So-Called "Third"-Person Possessive Pronoun jue 氒 in Classical ChineseThe So-Called "Third"-Person Possessive Pronoun jue in Classical Chinese.Ken-Ichi Takashima - 1999 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 119 (3):404.
  6. Comments on Kaplan's “Demonstratives” and Zimmermann's “Tertiumne datur? Possessive Pronouns and the Bipartition of the Lexicon”.H. Kamp & A. Roßdeutscher - 2004 - In Hans Kamp & Barbara Hall Partee (eds.), Context-dependence in the analysis of linguistic meaning. Boston: Elsevier. pp. 431--458.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  7.  7
    Aristotle and individual forms: The grammar of the possessive pronouns at metaphysics. 5, 1071a27–91.Métaphysique D’Aristote - 2006 - Classical Quarterly 56:105-112.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  6
    Aristotle and individual forms: The grammar of the possessive pronouns at metaphysics λ.5, 1071a27–9.David Konstan & Ilaria Ramelli - 2006 - Classical Quarterly 56 (01):105-.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  1
    On an Idiomatic use of Possessive Pronouns in Latin.D. R. Shackleton Bailey - 1954 - The Classical Review 4 (01):8-9.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  5
    Pronoun in Ortonese.Emiliana Tucci - 2022 - Human Review. International Humanities Review / Revista Internacional de Humanidades 11 (1):1-12.
    In this article we will study the pronominal system in Ortonese, which belongs to the central-southern Italo-Romance languages. The analysis we propose is contrastive: we will compare the data with the Italian to highlight their differences in terms of some morphosyntactic aspects. We will examine, the stressed and unstressed personal pronouns, emphasizing the placement of the combined pronouns with the compound tenses. Then, we will focus on the rest of the pronouns, such as demonstratives, possessives, quantifiers and indefinites, also pointing (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  15
    Knowing Other Minds: A Scorekeeping Model.Patrizio Lo Presti - 2023 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 14 (4):1279-1308.
    The prepositional ‘in’ and possessive pronouns, e.g., ‘my’ and ‘mine,’ in the context of attributions of mental states, such as “in my mind” or “in your mind,” threaten to confuse attempts to account for knowledge of other minds. This paper distinguishes proper from improper uses of such expressions. I will argue that proper use of the prepositional ‘in’ and possessive pronouns in the context of mental state attributions presupposes capacities to properly track and attribute what are really, in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  1
    The Psychology of “Mine”.Leon Litwinski - 1947 - Philosophy 22 (83):240-251.
    Summary Property a psychic link. W. James on self and mine. Acquisition and conservation in the light of expectation. Expectation in philosophy and psychology. Baldwin and property. Bentham. Why acquisitions are conserved. Property as the basis of expectation and as witness of foresight. Possessive pronouns. Animals and children. Property viewed objectively by Petrucci and subjectively by Bentham.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  4
    “Me” means more than “good”: stimuli’s self-relevance matters more than valence in shaping evaluative learning via the self.Simone Mattavelli, Juliette Richetin & Marco Perugini - 2023 - Cognition and Emotion 37 (3):544-558.
    Stimuli that relate to the self tend to be better liked. The Self-Referencing (SR) task is a paradigm whereby one target categorised through the same action as self-stimuli (i.e. possessive pronoun...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  20
    The Processing Domain of Dcope Interaction.Oliver Bott & Fabian Schlotterbeck - 2015 - Journal of Semantics 32 (1):fft015.
    The present study investigates whether quantifier scope is computed incrementally during online sentence processing. We exploited the free word order in German to manipulate whether the verbal predicate preceded or followed the second quantifier in doubly quantified sentences that required the computation of inverse scope. A possessive pronoun in the first quantifier that had to be bound by the second quantifier was used to enforce scope inversion. We tested whether scope inversion causes difficulty and whether this difficulty emerges (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  15.  8
    A New Acrostic and Telestic at Lavs Pisonis 227–30?Gary P. Vos - 2023 - Classical Quarterly 73 (2):949-952.
    This article proposes a new acrostic (SAPI) and telestic (SOIS) at Laus Pisonis 227–30. Their position opposite one another is an indication that they are to be read as a single sentence and an admonition to both dedicatee and reader that poet and patron need each other to gain eternal fame. The telestic allows us to reconstruct the poet's usus scribendi of the reflexive possessive pronoun suus.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  2
    The Psychology of "Mine".Leon Litwinski - 1947 - Philosophy 22 (83):240 - 251.
    Summary Property a psychic link. W. James on self and mine. Acquisition and conservation in the light of expectation. Expectation in philosophy and psychology. Baldwin and property. Bentham. Why acquisitions are conserved. Property as the basis of expectation and as witness of foresight. Possessive pronouns. Animals and children. Property viewed objectively by Petrucci and subjectively by Bentham.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. How to give someone Horns. Paradoxes of Presupposition in Antiquity.Susanne Bobzien - 2012 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 15:159-84.
    ABSTRACT: This paper discusses ancient versions of paradoxes today classified as paradoxes of presupposition and how their ancient solutions compare with contemporary ones. Sections 1-4 air ancient evidence for the Fallacy of Complex Question and suggested solutions, introduce the Horn Paradox, consider its authorship and contemporary solutions. Section 5 reconstructs the Stoic solution, suggesting the Stoics produced a Russellian-type solution based on a hidden scope ambiguity of negation. The difference to Russell's explanation of definite descriptions is that in the Horn (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  18.  1
    What Do We Refer to When We Say “I”?Peter van Inwagen - 2002 - In Richard M. Gale (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Metaphysics. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 175–189.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  19.  4
    Pragmalinguistic aspect of the political discourse as means of formation values of the nation.L. S. Chikileva - 2017 - Liberal Arts in Russia 6 (1):82-94.
    The political media discourse and its pragmalinguistic peculiarities are analyzed in the paper. The choice of the subject matter for the analysis is determined by the interest to media communication. It is noted that the political discourse is one of the effective means of influence on the collective consciousness. Various definitions of the concept ‘discourse‘ are given; special attention is paid to the presidential discourse. Discourse as a communicative event taking place in a social context is based on pragmatic situations (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. '내'의 공손한 표현으로서의 '우리' [The Korean determiner 'uri [our]' as a polite form of 'nae [my]'].Joongol Kim - 2020 - 철학적 분석 [Philosophical Analysis] 43:91-114.
    [Author's note: although this paper is written in Korean, it is archived here in the hope of bringing it to the attention of a wider audience including scholars of pragmatics and of Korean linguistics.] Recently, Korean linguists and philosophers of language have engaged in discussions on the meaning and usage of the Korean determiner ‘uri’ as in such phrases as ‘uri manura [our wife]’ which might seem strange given the monogamous marital institution of Korea. The aim of this paper is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  4
    What Do We Refer to When We Say “I”?Peter van Inwagen - 2002 - In Richard M. Gale (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Metaphysics. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 175-189.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  22. Definiteness and Indefiniteness.Barbara Abbott - 2004 - In Laurence R. Horn & Gregory Ward (eds.), Handbook of Pragmatics. Blackwell.
    The prototypes of definiteness and indefiniteness in English are the definite article the and the indefinite article a/an, and singular noun phrases (NPs)1 determined by them. That being the case it is not to be predicted that the concepts, whatever their content, will extend satisfactorily to other determiners or NP types. However it has become standard to extend these notions. Of the two categories definites have received rather more attention, and more than one researcher has characterized the category of definite (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  23.  19
    Temporal semantics in a superficially tenseless language.Lisa Matthewson - 2006 - Linguistics and Philosophy 29 (6):673 - 713.
    This paper contributes to the debate about ‘tenseless languages’ by defending a tensed analysis of a superficially tenseless language. The language investigated is St’át’imcets (Lillooet Salish). I argue that although St’át’imcets lacks overt tense morphology, every finite clause in the language possesses a phonologically covert tense morpheme; this tense morpheme restricts the reference time to being non-future. Future interpretations, as well as ‘past future’ would-readings, are obtained by the combination of covert tense with an operator analogous to Abusch’s (1985) WOLL. (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  24.  82
    The semantic basis of externalism.Michael McKinsey - 2015 - In Sorin Costreie & Mircea Dumitru (eds.), Meaning and Truth. Pro Universitaria.
    1. The primary evidence and motivation for externalism in the philosophy of mind is provided by the semantic facts that support direct reference theories of names, indexi- cal pronouns, and natural kind terms. But many externalists have forgotten their sem- antic roots, or so I shall contend here. I have become convinced of this by a common reaction among externalists to the main argument of my 1991 paper AAnti-Individual- ism and Privileged Access.@ In that argument, I concluded that externalism is (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  25.  18
    Précis of how children learn the meanings of words.Paul Bloom - 2001 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24 (6):1095-1103.
    Normal children learn tens of thousands of words, and do so quickly and efficiently, often in highly impoverished environments. In How Children Learn the Meanings of Words, I argue that word learning is the product of certain cognitive and linguistic abilities that include the ability to acquire concepts, an appreciation of syntactic cues to meaning, and a rich understanding of the mental states of other people. These capacities are powerful, early emerging, and to some extent uniquely human, but they are (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  26.  10
    Anaphoric Conservativity.R. Zuber - 2022 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 31 (1):113-128.
    The notion of anaphoric conservativity, that is a property of specific functions taking sets and binary relations as arguments is studied. Such functions are denotations of anaphoric determiners forming nominal anaphors. It is shown that anaphoric conservativity is strictly stronger that ordinary conservativity of this type of functions. In consequence some novel semantic descriptions of reflexive and reciprocal pronouns are provided and a semantic universal stating that reflexive and reciprocal non-possessive determiners denote anaphorically conservative functions is proposed.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  2
    The Hungarian Nominal Functional Sequence.Éva Dékány - 2021 - Springer Verlag.
    The Hungarian Nominal Functional Sequence combines the methods of syntactic cartography with evidence from compositional semantics in a comprehensive exploration of the structure of Noun Phrases. Proceeding from the lexical core to the top of DP, it uses Hungarian as a window on the underlying universal functional hierarchy of Noun Phrases, but it also regularly complements and supports the analysis with cross-linguistic evidence. The book works out a minimal map of the extended NP in the sense that the proposed hierarchy (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  4
    Between Earth and Sky.Jean-Paul Martinon - 2016 - Journal of French and Francophone Philosophy 24 (1):25-44.
    Africa. Who are you? I deliberately don’t say here, “What are you?” As we know, the interrogative pronoun “what” is an attempt to grab the essence of something. As Heidegger says: “whatness [ Wassein ], comprises what one commonly calls… the idea or mental representation by means of which we propose to… grasp what a thing is.” As such, questions starting with the interrogative pronoun “what” are eminently violent because they reduce the object of inquiry to a thing (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  6
    The value of ownership.Meir Dan-Cohen - 2001 - Journal of Political Philosophy 9 (4):404–434.
    To understand private property, it is generally assumed, we must recognize the contribution objects make to human life. On the prevailing view, ownership is valuable only insofar as its subject matter is of value. In the order of valuation, objects come first, owning them comes second. But despite its air of obviousness, the assumption does not suit our ordinary concept of ownership. Ownership can be valuable quite apart from the value of the owned object, and it can be the source (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  30.  5
    From the Streets to the White House.Matjaž Ezgeta - 2012 - Croatian Journal of Philosophy 12 (1):13-37.
    Most linguists have defined African-American Vernacular English (AAVE) as a regular and systematic form of vernacular language which contains distinctive grammatical and phonological features. AAVE is considered a social dialect or a non-standard variety of American English, which is spoken by the majority of African Americans. This article explores variability of the selected AAVE features in the interviews with ten African-American public figures, ranging from Hip Hop artists and blues musicians (Redman, Chuck D, Prodigy, MC Lyte, B.B. King) to talk (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  3
    A semantic solution to the problem of Hungarian object agreement.Elizabeth Coppock - 2013 - Natural Language Semantics 21 (4):345-371.
    This paper offers a semantically-based solution to the problem of predicting whether a verb will display the subjective conjugation or the objective conjugation in Hungarian. This alternation correlates with the definiteness of the object, but definiteness is not a completely reliable indicator of the subjective/objective alternation, nor is specificity. A prominent view is that the subjective/objective alternation is conditioned by the syntactic category of the object, but this view has also been shown to be untenable. This paper offers a semantic (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Lisa Green/Aspectual be–type Constructions and Coercion in African American English Yoad Winter/Distributivity and Dependency Instructions for Authors.Pauline Jacobson, Paycheck Pronouns, Bach-Peters Sentences, Inflectional Head, Thomas Ede Zimmermann, Free Choice Disjunction, Epistemic Possibility, Sigrid Beck & Uli Sauerland - 2000 - Natural Language Semantics 8 (373).
  33. Jj Christie.Possessive Locative & Existential In Swahili - forthcoming - Foundations of Language.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. title: N 345. anicce pawae ruppe bhuyagassa taha maha-samudde ya ee khalu ahigara ajjhayanammi vimuttie a: a sloka pdda. Impermanence, a mountain, silver, a snake and the ocean—these one.Consider This Supreme, A. Wise Man, Should Give, Once Stop Killing & Acquiring Possessions - 1990 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 18:29.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Pronouns and Gender.Cameron Domenico Kirk-Giannini & Michael Glanzberg - 2024 - In Ernest Lepore & Luvell Anderson (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Applied Philosophy of Language. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. pp. 265–292.
    This chapter introduces readers to the empirical questions at issue in debates over gendered pronouns and assesses the plausibility of various possible answers to these questions. It has two parts. The first is a general introduction to the linguistics and psychology of grammatical gender. The second focuses on the meanings of gendered pronouns in English. It begins with a discussion of some methodological limitations of empirical approaches to the topic and the normative implications of those limitations. It then argues against (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  56
    Descriptions, pronouns, and uniqueness.Karen S. Lewis - 2022 - Linguistics and Philosophy 45 (3):559-617.
    Both definite descriptions and pronouns are often anaphoric; that is, part of their interpretation in context depends on prior linguistic material in the discourse. For example: A student walked in. The student sat down. A student walked in. She sat down. One popular view of anaphoric pronouns, the d-type view, is that pronouns like ‘she’ go proxy for definite descriptions like ‘the student who walked in’, which are in turn treated in a classical Russellian or Fregean fashion. I argue for (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  37. People’s Beliefs About Pronouns Reflect Both the Language They Speak and Their Ideologies.April Bailey, Robin Dembroff, Daniel Wodak, Elif Ikizer & Andrei Cimpian - forthcoming - Journal of Experimental Psychology: General.
    Pronouns often convey information about a person’s social identity (e.g., gender). Consequently, pronouns have become a focal point in academic and public debates about whether pronouns should be changed to be more inclusive, such as for people whose identities do not fit current pronoun conventions (e.g., gender non-binary individuals). Here, we make an empirical contribution to these debates by investigating which social identities lay speakers think that pronouns should encode and why. Across four studies, participants were asked to evaluate (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  8
    Producing Pronouns and Definite Noun Phrases: Do Speakers Use the Addressee’s Discourse Model?Kumiko Fukumura & Roger P. G. van Gompel - 2012 - Cognitive Science 36 (7):1289-1311.
    We report two experiments that investigated the widely held assumption that speakers use the addressee’s discourse model when choosing referring expressions (e.g., Ariel, 1990; Chafe, 1994; Givón, 1983; Prince, 1985), by manipulating whether the addressee could hear the immediately preceding linguistic context. Experiment 1 showed that speakers increased pronoun use (and decreased noun phrase use) when the referent was mentioned in the immediately preceding sentence compared to when it was not, even though the addressee did not hear the preceding (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  39.  20
    Pronouns, Quantifiers, and Relative Clauses (I).Gareth Evans - 1977 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7 (3):467--536.
    Some philosophers, notably Professors Quine and Geach, have stressed the analogies they see between pronouns of the vernacular and the bound variables of quantification theory. Geach, indeed, once maintained that ‘for a philosophical theory of reference, then, it is all one whether we consider bound variables or pronouns of the vernacular'. This slightly overstates Geach's positition since he recognizes that some pronouns of ordinary language do function differently from bound variables; he calls such pronouns ‘pronouns of laziness'. Geach's characterisation of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   130 citations  
  40.  53
    Pronouns Beyond the Binary: The Change of Attitudes and Use Over Time.Anna Lindqvist, Emma Renström & Marie Gustafsson Sendén - 2021 - Gender and Society 35 (4):588-615.
    Gender-inclusive language, such as the Swedish pronoun hen, may aid in breaking a binary notion of gender and avoid sexism. The present study followed the implementation of a gender-inclusive third-person pronoun singular in Swedish in two surveys with representative samples in 2015 and in 2018. The surveys comprised measures of attitudes toward, and use of, hen as well as possible predictors such as area of residence, age, preferred pronoun, political orientation, and interest in gender issues. Results showed (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  41.  12
    Personal pronoun revisionism - asking the right question.Harold Noonan - 2012 - Analysis 72 (2):316-318.
    Personal pronoun revisionism (so-called by Olson, E. 2007. What are We? A Study in Personal Ontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press) is a response to the problem of the thinking animal on behalf of the neo-Lockean theorist. Many worry about this response. The worry rests on asking the wrong question, namely: how can two thinkers that are so alike differ in this way in their cognitive capacities? This is the wrong question because they don't. The right question is: how can (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  42.  46
    XI*—Pronouns and Propositional Attitudes.Scott Soames - 1990 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 90 (1):191-212.
    Scott Soames; XI*—Pronouns and Propositional Attitudes, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 90, Issue 1, 1 June 1990, Pages 191–212, https://doi.org.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  43. Pronouns as Demonstratives.Kyle Blumberg - 2021 - Philosophers' Imprint 21 (35).
    In this paper, I outline a novel approach to the semantics of natural language pronouns. On this account, which I call 'demonstrativism', pronouns are semantically equivalent to demonstratives. I begin by presenting some contrasts that provide support for demonstrativism. Then I try to explain these contrasts by developing a particular demonstrativist proposal. I build on the "hidden argument" theory of demonstratives. On this theory, demonstratives are semantically similar to definite descriptions, with one important difference: demonstratives take two arguments, rather than (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  19
    Pronouns and pronominal descriptions: A new semantical category.George M. Wilson - 1984 - Philosophical Studies 45 (1):1 - 30.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  45.  20
    Paycheck Pronouns, Bach-Peters Sentences, and Variable-Free Semantics.Pauline Jacobson - 2000 - Natural Language Semantics 8 (2):77-155.
    This paper argues for the hypothesis of direct compositionality (as in, e.g., Montague 1974), according to which the combinatory syntactic rules specify a set of well-formed expressions while the semantic combinatory rules work in tandem to directly supply a model-theoretic interpretation to each expression as it is "built" in the syntax. (This thus obviates the need for any level like LF and, concomitantly, for any rules mapping surface structures to such a level.) I focus here on one related group of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  46.  27
    Situation Pronouns in Determiner Phrases.Florian Schwarz - 2012 - Natural Language Semantics 20 (4):431-475.
    It is commonly argued that natural language has the expressive power of quantifying over intensional entities, such as times, worlds, or situations. A standard way of modelling this assumes that there are unpronounced but syntactically represented variables of the corresponding type. Not all that much as has been said, however, about the exact syntactic location of these variables. Meanwhile, recent work has highlighted a number of problems that arise because the interpretive options for situation pronouns seem to be subject to (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  47.  14
    Pronouns Are as Sensitive to Structural Constraints as Reflexives in Early Processing: Evidence From Visual World Paradigm Eye-Tracking.Chung-hye Han, Keir Moulton, Trevor Block, Holly Gendron & Sander Nederveen - 2021 - Frontiers in Psychology 12.
    A number of studies in the extant literature report findings that suggest asymmetry in the way reflexive and pronoun anaphors are interpreted in the early stages of processing: that pronouns are less sensitive to structural constraints, as formulated by Binding Theory, than reflexives, in the initial antecedent retrieval process. However, in previous visual world paradigm eye-tracking studies, these conclusions were based on sentences that placed the critical anaphors within picture noun phrases or prepositional phrases, which have independently been shown (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  17
    Indefinite Pronouns Optimize the Simplicity/Informativeness Trade‐Off.Milica Denić, Shane Steinert-Threlkeld & Jakub Szymanik - 2022 - Cognitive Science 46 (5):e13142.
    Cognitive Science, Volume 46, Issue 5, May 2022.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  49.  9
    On Dependent Pronouns and Dynamic Semantics.Rick Nouwen - 2007 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 36 (2):123-154.
    Within natural language semantics, pronouns are often thought to correspond to variables whose values are contributed by contextual assignment functions. This paper concerns the application of this idea to cases where the antecedent of a pronoun is a plural quantifiers. The paper discusses the modelling of accessibility patterns of quantifier antecedents in a dynamic theory of interpretation. The goal is to reach a semantics of quantificational dependency which yields a fully semantic notion of pronominal accessibility. I argue that certain (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  50. Discourse and logical form: pronouns, attention and coherence.Una Stojnić, Matthew Stone & Ernie Lepore - 2017 - Linguistics and Philosophy 40 (5):519-547.
    Traditionally, pronouns are treated as ambiguous between bound and demonstrative uses. Bound uses are non-referential and function as bound variables, and demonstrative uses are referential and take as a semantic value their referent, an object picked out jointly by linguistic meaning and a further cue—an accompanying demonstration, an appropriate and adequately transparent speaker’s intention, or both. In this paper, we challenge tradition and argue that both demonstrative and bound pronouns are dependent on, and co-vary with, antecedent expressions. Moreover, the semantic (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000