Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Conscientious Objection in Healthcare: The Requirement of Justification, the Moral Threshold, and Military Refusals.Tomasz Żuradzki - 2023 - Journal of Religious Ethics 52 (1):133-155.
    A dogma accepted in many ethical, religious, and legal frameworks is that the reasons behind conscientious objection (CO) in healthcare cannot be evaluated or judged by any institution because conscience is individual and autonomous. This paper shows that this background view is mistaken: the requirement to reveal and explain the reasons for conscientious objection in healthcare is ethically justified and legally desirable. Referring to real healthcare cases and legal regulations, this paper argues that these reasons should be evaluated either ex (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Moral disagreement and providing emergency contraception: A pluralistic alternative.Noam Zohar - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (6):35 – 36.
  • Reasons and healthcare professionals' claims of conscience.Mark R. Wicclair - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (6):21 – 22.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Preventing conscientious objection in medicine from running amok: a defense of reasonable accommodation.Mark R. Wicclair - 2019 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 40 (6):539-564.
    A US Department of Health and Human Services Final Rule, Protecting Statutory Conscience Rights in Health Care, and a proposed bill in the British House of Lords, the Conscientious Objection Bill, may well warrant a concern that—to borrow a phrase Daniel Callahan applied to self-determination—conscientious objection in health care has “run amok.” Insofar as there are no significant constraints or limitations on accommodation, both rules endorse an approach that is aptly designated “conscience absolutism.” There are two common strategies to counter (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Managing Conscientious Objection in Health Care Institutions.Mark R. Wicclair - 2014 - HEC Forum 26 (3):267-283.
    It is argued that the primary aim of institutional management is to protect the moral integrity of health professionals without significantly compromising other important values and interests. Institutional policies are recommended as a means to promote fair, consistent, and transparent management of conscience-based refusals. It is further recommended that those policies include the following four requirements: (1) Conscience-based refusals will be accommodated only if a requested accommodation will not impede a patient’s/surrogate’s timely access to information, counseling, and referral. (2) Conscience-based (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Conscientious Objection by Health Care Professionals.Gry Wester - 2015 - Philosophy Compass 10 (7):427-437.
    Certain health care services and goods, although legal and often generally accepted in a society, are by some considered morally problematic. Debates on conscientious objection in health care try to resolve whether and when physicians, nurses and pharmacists should be allowed to refuse to provide medical services and goods because of their ethical or religious beliefs. These debates have most often focused on issues such as how to balance the interests of patients and health care professionals, and the compatibility of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Uzasadnienie sprzeciwu sumienia: lekarze, poborowi i żołnierze.Tomasz Żuradzki - 2016 - Diametros 47:98-128.
    I will argue that physicians have an ethical obligation to justify their conscientious objection and the most reliable interpretation of the Polish legal framework claims that conscientious objection is permissible only when the justification shows the genuineness of the judgment of conscience that is not based on false beliefs and arises from a moral norm that has a high rank. I will demonstrate that the dogma accepted in the Polish doctrine that the reasons that lie behind conscientious objection in medicine (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • In Pursuit of a Balance: the Regulation of Conscience and Access to Sexual Reproductive Health Care.Diya Uberoi & Beatriz Galli - 2017 - Human Rights Review 18 (3):283-304.
    In any given society, rights are said to co-exist. When rights, however, begin to conflict, a balance must be sought. In few fields has the ability of governments to accommodate two conflicting sets of rights been so controversial as it has in the case of conscientious objection in reproductive health care. Today, states have an obligation under international law to protect the right to the freedom of thought, conscience, and religion of medical providers. They also, however, have an obligation to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Are there different spheres of conscience?Erica J. Sutton & Ross E. G. Upshur - 2010 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 16 (2):338-343.
  • Conscientious objection the morning after.Carson Strong - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (6):32 – 34.
  • Pharmacists and the social contract.Kenneth A. Richman - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (6):15 – 16.
  • The Reasonableness Standard for Conscientious Objection in Healthcare.Massimo Reichlin - 2022 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 19 (2):255-264.
    In complex, pluralistic societies, different views concerning the moral duties of healthcare professionals inevitably exist: according to some accounts, doctors can and should cooperate in performing abortion or physician-assisted suicide, while according to others they should always defend human life and protect their patients’ health. It is argued that the very plurality of responses presently given to questions such as these provides a liberal argument in favour of conscientious objection, as an attempt to deal with moral diversity by protecting both (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • When 'Emergency Contraception' is Neither.Timothy F. Murphy - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (8):7-7.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conscientious Objection, Complicity in Wrongdoing, and a Not-So-Moderate Approach.Francesca Minerva - 2017 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 26 (1):109-119.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Conscientious objection in Italy: Table 1.Francesca Minerva - 2015 - Journal of Medical Ethics 41 (2):170-173.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Conscientious objection? Yes, but make sure it is genuine.Christopher Meyers & Robert D. Woods - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (6):19 – 20.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Harm or Mere Inconvenience? Denying Women Emergency Contraception.Carolyn McLeod - 2010 - Hypatia 25 (1):11-30.
    This paper addresses the likely impact on women of being denied emergency contraception (EC) by pharmacists who conscientiously refuse to provide it. A common view—defended by Elizabeth Fenton and Loren Lomasky, among others—is that these refusals inconvenience rather than harm women so long as the women can easily get EC somewhere else nearby. I argue from a feminist perspective that the refusals harm women even when they can easily get EC somewhere else nearby.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Conscientious objection to abortion, the law and its implementation in Victoria, Australia: perspectives of abortion service providers.Lynn Gillam Louise Anne Keogh, Kathleen McNamee Marie Bismark, Christine Bayly Amy Webster & Danielle Newton - 2019 - BMC Medical Ethics 20 (1):11.
    In Victoria, Australia, the law regulating abortion was reformed in 2008, and a clause was introduced requiring doctors with a conscientious objection to abortion to refer women to another provid...
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Conscientious objection: Does the zero-probability argument work?Greg Loeben & Michelle A. Chui - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (6):28 – 30.
  • When to grant conscientious objector status.Ronald A. Lindsay - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (6):25 – 26.
  • Emergency Contraception and Conscientious Objection.J. Paul Kelleher - 2010 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 27 (3):290-304.
    Emergency contraception — also known as the morning after pill — is marketed and sold, under various brand names, in over one hundred countries around the world. In some countries, customers can purchase the drug without a prescription. In others, a prescription must be presented to a licensed pharmacist. In virtually all of these countries, pharmacists are the last link in the chain of delivery. This article examines and ultimately rejects several standard moves in the bioethics literature on the right (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Ethicists conscientiously objecting: an ontological dejustification.M. A. Kekewich & T. C. Foreman - 2012 - Clinical Ethics 7 (2):101-104.
    Much has been written about the rights of health-care professionals to conscientiously object. Ironically, there has been no formal discussion as to whether clinical ethicists have the same right. Given that ethicists routinely deal with the same situations and questions that other health-care professionals find morally discomforting, the question as to whether they have the same right is a critical one. We conclude that ethicists should not have the same right to conscientious objection. The role of an ethicist is to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conscientious objection in healthcare: why tribunals might be the answer.Jonathan A. Hughes - 2016 - Journal of Medical Ethics 43 (4):213-217.
    A recent focus of the debate on conscientious objection in healthcare is the question of whether practitioners should have to justify their refusal to perform certain functions. A recent article by Cowley addresses a practical aspect of this controversy, namely the question of whether doctors claiming conscientious objector status in relation to abortion should be required, like their counterparts claiming exemption from military conscription, to defend their claim before a tribunal. Cowley argues against the use of tribunals in the medical (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Gatekeeping and personal values: Misuses of professional roles.D. Micah Hester, Toby Schonfeld & Jean Amoura - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (6):27 – 28.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The necessity of conscience and the unspoken ends of medicine.John J. Hardt - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (6):18 – 19.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Conscience, Courage, and “Consent”.Mark A. Hall & Nancy M. P. King - 2016 - Hastings Center Report 46 (2):30-32.
    On September 8, 2015, the Department of Health and Human Services issued a Notice of Proposed Rule Making to revise the Federal Policy for the Protection of Human Subjects, widely known as the “Common Rule.” The NPRM proposes several changes to the current system, including a dramatic shift in the approach to secondary research using biospecimens and data. Under the current rules, it is relatively easy to use biospecimens and data for secondary research. This approach systematically facilitates secondary research with (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Paradox of Conscientious Objection and the Anemic Concept of 'Conscience': Downplaying the Role of Moral Integrity in Health Care.Alberto Giubilini - 2014 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 24 (2):159-185.
    Conscientious objection in health care is a form of compromise whereby health care practitioners can refuse to take part in safe, legal, and beneficial medical procedures to which they have a moral opposition (for instance abortion). Arguments in defense of conscientious objection in medicine are usually based on the value of respect for the moral integrity of practitioners. I will show that philosophical arguments in defense of conscientious objection based on respect for such moral integrity are extremely weak and, if (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Beyond Money: Conscientious Objection in Medicine as a Conflict of Interests.Alberto Giubilini & Julian Savulescu - 2020 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 17 (2):229-243.
    Conflict of interests in medicine are typically taken to be financial in nature: it is often assumed that a COI occurs when a healthcare practitioner’s financial interest conflicts with patients’ interests, public health interests, or professional obligations more generally. Even when non-financial COIs are acknowledged, ethical concerns are almost exclusively reserved for financial COIs. However, the notion of “interests” cannot be reduced to its financial component. Individuals in general, and medical professionals in particular, have different types of interests, many of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Emergency Contraception: Legal Consequences of Medical Classification.Elizabeth Gerber - 2008 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 36 (2):428-431.
    Pharmacists with religious or ethical objections to prescribing emergency contraception won the latest round in the fight over conscience clauses in a case that could have broader implications for attempts to restrict access to contraception. In Stormans, Inc. v. Selecky, a federal District Court in Washington State granted an injunction to block the enforcement of regulations that would have forbidden pharmacists to refuse to dispense emergency contraception on the grounds of religious or ethical objections. In its decision, the court applied (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The fox and the grapes: an Anglo-Irish perspective on conscientious objection to the supply of emergency hormonal contraception without prescription.Cathal T. Gallagher, Alice Holton, Lisa J. McDonald & Paul J. Gallagher - 2013 - Journal of Medical Ethics 39 (10):638-642.
    Emergency hormonal contraception (EHC) has been available from pharmacies in the UK without prescription for 11 years. In the Republic of Ireland this service was made available in 2011. In both jurisdictions the respective regulators have included ‘conscience clauses’, which allow pharmacists to opt out of providing EHC on religious or moral grounds providing certain criteria are met. In effect, conscientious objectors must refer patients to other providers who are willing to supply these medicines. Inclusion of such clauses leads to (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Unjustified Asymmetry: Positive Claims of Conscience and Heartbeat Bills.Kyle G. Fritz - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics 21 (8):46-59.
    In 2019, several US states passed “heartbeat” bills. Should such bills go into effect, they would outlaw abortion once an embryonic heartbeat can be detected, thereby severely limiting an individual’s access to abortion. Many states allow health care professionals to refuse to provide an abortion for reasons of conscience. Yet heartbeat bills do not include a positive conscience clause that would allow health care professionals to provide an abortion for reasons of conscience. I argue that this asymmetry is unjustified. The (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Protecting reasonable conscientious refusals in health care.Jason T. Eberl - 2019 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 40 (6):565-581.
    Recently, debate over whether health care providers should have a protected right to conscientiously refuse to offer legal health care services—such as abortion, elective sterilization, aid in dying, or treatments for transgender patients—has grown exponentially. I advance a modified compromise view that bases respect for claims of conscientious refusal to provide specific health care services on a publicly defensible rationale. This view requires health care providers who refuse such services to disclose their availability by other providers, as well as to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • For what we do, and fail to do.Christopher Dodsworth, Tihamer Toth-Fejel & Zach Stangebye - 2008 - American Journal of Bioethics 8 (7):29 – 31.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Should professional associations sanction conscientious refusals?Inmaculada de Melo-Martin - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (6):23 – 24.
  • Religion and Newborn Screening.Richard H. Dees & Jennifer M. Kwon - 2016 - American Journal of Bioethics 16 (1):20-21.
    Hom and colleagues (2016) argue in favor of allowing religious exemptions to congenital critical heart disease (CCHD) newborn screening, but the logic of their position is at odds with the moral ju...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Might a conscience clause be used for non-moral or prejudiced reasons?Zuzana Deans - 2016 - Journal of Medical Ethics 42 (2):76-77.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Caution: Conscience is the limb on which medical ethics sits.Farr A. Curlin - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (6):30 – 32.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Conscientious objection and healthcare in the UK: why tribunals are not the answer.Christopher Cowley - 2016 - Journal of Medical Ethics 42 (2):69-72.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Two Concepts of Conscience and their Implications for Conscience-Based Refusal in Healthcare.Steve Clarke - 2017 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 26 (1):97-108.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Conscientious objection in healthcare, referral and the military analogy.Steve Clarke - 2017 - Journal of Medical Ethics 43 (4):218-221.
    An analogy is sometimes drawn between the proper treatment of conscientious objectors in healthcare and in military contexts. In this paper, I consider an aspect of this analogy that has not, to my knowledge, been considered in debates about conscientious objection in healthcare. In the USA and elsewhere, tribunals have been tasked with the responsibility of recommending particular forms of alternative service for conscientious objectors. Military conscripts who have a conscientious objection to active military service, and whose objections are deemed (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Imposing Values and Enforcing Gender through Knowledge: Epistemic Oppression with the Morning-after Pill's Drug Label.Christopher ChoGlueck - 2022 - Hypatia 37 (2):315-342.
    Among feminist philosophers, there are two lines of argument that sexist values are illegitimate in science, focusing on epistemic or ethical problems. This article supports a third framework, elucidating how value-laden science can enable epistemic oppression. My analysis demonstrates how purported knowledge laden with sexist values can compromise epistemic autonomy and contribute to paternalism and misogyny. I exemplify these epistemic wrongs with a case study of the morning-after pill during its 2006 switch to over-the-counter availability and its new drug label (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Market View on conscientious objection: overvalued.Robert F. Card - 2019 - Journal of Medical Ethics 45 (3):168-172.
    Ancell and Sinnott-Armstrong argue that medical providers possess wide freedoms to determine the scope of their practice, and therefore, prohibiting almost any conscientious objections is a bad idea. They maintain that we could create an acceptable system on the whole which even grants accommodations to discriminatory refusals by healthcare professionals. Their argument is premised upon applying a free market mechanism to conscientious objections in medicine, yet I argue their Market View possesses a number of absurd and troubling implications. Furthermore, I (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Inevitability of Assessing Reasons in Debates about Conscientious Objection in Medicine.Robert F. Card - 2017 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 26 (1):82-96.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Scouring the scourge: Spontaneous abortion and morality.Robert F. Card - 2008 - American Journal of Bioethics 8 (7):27 – 29.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Response to commentators on "conscientious objection and emergency contraception": Sex, drugs and the rocky role of levonorgestrel.Robert F. Card - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (10):W4 – W6.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reasons, reasonability and establishing conscientious objector status in medicine.Robert F. Card - 2017 - Journal of Medical Ethics 43 (4):222-225.
    This paper builds upon previous work in which I argue that we should assess a provider's reasons for his or her objection before granting a conscientious exemption. For instance, if the medical professional's reasoned basis involves an empirical mistake, an accommodation is not warranted. This article poses and begins to address several deep questions about the workings of what I call a reason-giving view: What standard should we use to assess reasons? What policy should we adopt in order to evaluate (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Reasonability and Conscientious Objection in Medicine: A Reply to Marsh and an Elaboration of the Reason‐Giving Requirement.Robert F. Card - 2013 - Bioethics 28 (6):320-326.
    In this paper I defend the Reasonability View: the position that medical professionals seeking a conscientious exemption must state reasons in support of their objection and allow those reasons to be subject to evaluation. Recently, this view has been criticized by Jason Marsh as proposing a standard that is either too difficult to meet or too easy to satisfy. First, I defend the Reasonability View from this proposed dilemma. Then, I develop this view by presenting and explaining some of the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Is there no alternative? Conscientious objection by medical students.Robert F. Card - 2012 - Journal of Medical Ethics 38 (10):602-604.
    Recent survey data gathered from British medical students reveal widespread acceptance of conscientious objection in medicine, despite the existence of strict policies in the UK that discourage conscientious refusals by students to aspects of their medical training. This disconnect demonstrates a pressing need to thoughtfully examine policies that allow conscience objections by medical students; as it so happens, the USA is one country that has examples of such policies. After presenting some background on promulgated US conscience protections and reflecting on (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • In defence of medical tribunals and the reasonability standard for conscientious objection in medicine.Robert F. Card - 2016 - Journal of Medical Ethics 42 (2):73-75.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Federal provider conscience regulation: unconscionable.Robert F. Card - 2009 - Journal of Medical Ethics 35 (8):471-472.
    This paper argues that the provider conscience regulation recently put into place in the USA is misguided. The rule is too broad in the scope of protection it affords, and its conception of what constitutes assistance in the performance of an objectionable procedure reveals that it is unworkable in practice. Furthermore, the regulation wrongly treats refusal of other reproductive services as on a par with conscientious objection to participation in abortion. Finally, the rule allows providers to refuse even to discuss (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation