Results for 'Dignaga'

(not author) ( search as author name )
119 found
Order:
  1.  4
    Pramana samuccaya. Dignāga & H. R. Rangaswamy Iyengar - 1930 - Mysore,: Printed at the Govt. Branch Press. Edited by Rangaswamy Iyengar & R. H..
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Dignāga's Argument for the Awareness Principle: An Analytic Refinement.Uriah Kriegel - 2019 - Philosophy East and West 69:144-156.
    Contemporary theories of consciousness can be divided along several major fault lines, but one of the most prominent concerns the question of whether they accept the principle that a mental state's being conscious involves essentially its subject being aware of it. Call this the awareness principle: For any mental state M of a subject S, M is conscious only if S is aware of M. Although analytic philosophers divide sharply on whether to accept the principle, the philosophy-of-mind literature appears to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  3.  22
    Dignaga's Investigation of the Percept: A Philosophical Legacy in India and Tibet.Douglas Duckworth, Malcolm David Eckel, Jay L. Garfield, John Powers, Yeshes Thabkhas & Sonam Thakchoe (eds.) - 2016 - New York, NY: Oxford University Press UK.
    Investigation of the Percept is a short work that focuses on issues of perception and epistemology. Its author, Dignaga, was one of the most influential figures in the Indian Buddhist epistemological tradition, and his ideas had a profound and wide-ranging impact in India, Tibet, and China. The work inspired more than twenty commentaries throughout East Asia and three in Tibet, the most recent in 2014.This book is the first of its kind in Buddhist studies: a comprehensive history of a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  4. Dignāga and Dharmakīrti on Perception and Self-Awareness.Christian Coseru - 2016 - In John Powers (ed.), The Buddhist World. Routledge. pp. 526–537.
    Like many of their counterparts in the West, Buddhist philosophers realized a long time ago that our linguistic and conceptual practices are rooted in pre-predicative modes of apprehension that provide implicit access to whatever is immediately present to awareness. This paper examines Dignāga’s and Dharmakīrti’s contributions to what has come to be known as “Buddhist epistemology” (sometimes referred in the specialist literature by the Sanskrit neologism pramāṇavāda, lit. “doctrine of epistemic warrants”), focusing on the phenomenological and epistemic role of perception (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  5.  32
    Dignāga on Reflexive Awareness.Paul Bernier - 2015 - Philosophy East and West 65 (1):125-156.
  6.  77
    Dignāga, on Perception.Masaaki Hattori - 1970 - Philosophy East and West 20 (2):195-196.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  7. Dignaga and Sellars: Through the Lens of Privileged Access.Keya Maitra - 2019 - In Jay Garfield (ed.), Wilfrid Sellars and Buddhist Philosophy. New York, USA: Routledge. pp. 157-171.
    The chapter offers a sustained comparison between American philosopher Wilfrid Sellars and Buddhist philosopher Dignaga and argues that while their views are prima facie inconsistent with one another, there are important areas of agreement worthy of exploration.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  8
    Dignāga and Dharmakīrti on Fallacies of Inference: Some Reflections.Bhima Kumar Kukkamalla - 2020 - Journal of the Indian Council of Philosophical Research 37 (3):403-419.
    In Classical Indian philosophy, except Cārvākas all other schools unanimously recognize inference as an instrument of valid knowledge. However, the validity of an inference depends on the validity of hetu and its relation to pakṣa on the one hand and sādhya on the other. If the relation in question is dubious, the inference, which is based on it, turns out to be invalid. In Buddhist epistemology, inference is accepted as a legitimate valid source of knowledge along with perception and they (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  55
    Did dignāga accept four types of perception?Eli Franco - 1993 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 21 (3):295-299.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  10.  14
    Dignaga's Interpretation of the Perceptual Universe.Shyamali Sanyal - 2002 - Indian Philosophical Quarterly 29 (1):97-104.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  27
    Dignāga on the Causality of Object-Support (Ālambana) and Śubhagupta’s Refutation.Yufan Mao - 2019 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 47 (1):95-110.
    To answer the question about an internal object serving as a cause of cognition, in his Ālambanaparīkṣāvṛtti, Dignāga elaborates two types of causality in the significance of object-support : simultaneous causality and successive causality. Simultaneous causality is characterized as invariably concomitant, which refers to the inevitable co-existence of an object and its cognition. Successive causality is characterized as resemblance, which refers to a definite causal relationship between the immediate previous consciousness and its subsequent consciousness. That is, the preceding consciousness remains (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  20
    Reevaluating Dignāga’s Apoha Theory: As Revealed by Bhāviveka’s Critique.Long Yin Sin - 2023 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 51 (4):391-407.
    Pramāṇavādins are antirealists on the problem of universals by virtue of the fact that they deny the existence of real universals. Dignāga, therefore, offered apoha theory to explain how the denotation of objects is possible without postulating real universals. According to Apohavāda, a word, for instance “cow”, denotes a cow not by referring to a real universal “cowness,” but by excluding it from those which are non-cows, such as horses. In recent years, there is a discussion about what the genuine (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  63
    Dignāga, On Perception, being the Pratyakṣapariccheda of Dignāga's Pramāṇasamuccaya from the Sanskrit fragments and the Tibetan versionsDignaga, On Perception, being the Pratyaksapariccheda of Dignaga's Pramanasamuccaya from the Sanskrit fragments and the Tibetan versions.Alex Wayman & Masaaki Hattori - 1969 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 89 (2):434.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Self-Awareness in Dignāga’s Pramāṇasamuccaya and -vṛtti: A Close Reading.Birgit Kellner - 2010 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 38 (3):203-231.
    The concept of “self-awareness” ( svasaṃvedana ) enters Buddhist epistemological discourse in the Pramāṇasamuccaya and - vṛtti by Dignāga (ca. 480–540), the founder of the Buddhist logico-epistemological tradition. Though some of the key passages have already been dealt with in various publications, no attempt has been made to comprehensively examine all of them as a whole. A close reading is here proposed to make up for this deficit. In connection with a particularly difficult passage (PS(V) 1.8cd-10) that presents the means (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  15.  25
    Did Dignaga and Mallavadin Know the Old Vakyapadiya-Vrtti Attributed to Bhartrhari?Ole Holten Pind - 2003 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 31 (1/3):257-270.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  16.  40
    Dignāga, Kumārila and Dharmakīrti on the Potential Problem of pramāṇa and phala Having Different Objects.Kei Kataoka - 2016 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 44 (2):229-239.
    Following Dharmakīrti’s interpretation, PS I 9ab has been understood as stating a view common to both Sautrāntikas and Yogācāras, i.e. a view that self-awareness is the result of a means of valid cognition. It has also been understood that Dignāga accepts two different views attributed to Sautrāntikas with regard to pramāṇaphala: in PS ad I 8cd he regards the cognition of an external object as the result; in PS ad I 9ab–cd he alternatively presents another view that self-awareness is the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. A Mathematical Model of Dignāga’s Hetu-cakra.Aditya Kumar Jha - 2020 - Journal of the Indian Council of Philosophical Research 37 (3):471-479.
    A reasoned argument or tarka is essential for a wholesome vāda that aims at establishing the truth. A strong tarka constitutes of a number of elements including an anumāna based on a valid hetu. Several scholars, such as Dharmakīrti, Vasubandhu and Dignāga, have worked on theories for the establishment of a valid hetu to distinguish it from an invalid one. This paper aims to interpret Dignāga’s hetu-cakra, called the wheel of grounds, from a modern philosophical perspective by deconstructing it into (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  42
    On the Coherence of Dignāga’s Epistemology: Evaluating the Critiques of Candrakīrti and Jayarāśi.Ethan Mills - 2015 - Asian Philosophy 25 (4):339-357.
    I discuss two critiques of Dignāga’s epistemology, one from Candrakīrti and another from Jayarāśi. I argue that they are two versions of what I call the core problem: if the content of Dignāga’s epistemology were correct, two fundamental beliefs within this epistemological theory could not be established or known to be true, as Dignāga claims they are. In response to objections found within the classical Indian tradition as well as several plausible contemporary objections, I then argue that the core problem (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19.  11
    A Critical Analysis of Dignāga’s Refutation of Non-Buddhist Schools Theory of Perception.Bhima Kumar Kukkamalla - 2024 - Journal of the Indian Council of Philosophical Research 41 (1):1-16.
    Among the means of valid cognition, the one which appears first in every enumeration, which was considered as being the basis of all other means of knowledge and which was considered as a legitimate method of knowledge by all schools of Indian thought is perception (pratyakṣa). With regard to perception, we can naturally expect such questions as ‘what is it to perceive’ or ‘what do we mean when we say that something is perceived’. It is generally believed that the philosophical (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  25
    Horns in Dignāga’s Theory of apoha.Kei Kataoka - 2016 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 44 (5):867-882.
    According to Dignāga, the word “cow” makes one understand all cows in a general form by excluding non-cows. However, how does one understand the non-cows to be excluded? Hattori answers as follows: “On perceiving the particular which is endowed with dewlap, horns, a hump on the back, and so forth, one understands that it is not a non-cow, because one knows that a non-cow is not endowed with these attributes.” Hattori regards observation of a dewlap, etc. as the cause of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  2
    Dignāga’s Critical Issues against the Sāṃkhya Definition of Perception.Seung Suk Jung - 2016 - The Journal of Indian Philosophy 48:5-39.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  23
    Dignäga, On Perception. [REVIEW]J. H. P. - 1971 - Review of Metaphysics 24 (4):747-747.
    This is the best book to date on Buddhist theory of perception as found in the Pramänasamuccaya of Dignäga, 480 to 540 A.D. The book offers seventy pages of translation, copious notes, and two Tibetan editions in transliteration of Dignäga's chapter on perception. The translation is strikingly good with the necessary additions carefully bracketed to allow as much as possible a fluent reading if one disregarded the brackets. The translation is a presentation of the theory of perception, an examination of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. The anti-abstractionism of dignāga and Berkeley.Ewing Y. Chinn - 1994 - Philosophy East and West 44 (1):55-77.
  24. Self-Awareness (svasaṃvitti) and Related Doctrines of Buddhists Following Dignāga: Philosophical Characterizations of Some of the Main Issues.Dan Arnold - 2010 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 38 (3):323-378.
    Framed as a consideration of the other contributions to the present volume of the Journal of Indian Philosophy, this essay attempts to scout and characterize several of the interrelated doctrines and issues that come into play in thinking philosophically about the doctrine of svasaṃvitti, particularly as that was elaborated by Dignāga and Dharmakīrti. Among the issues thus considered are the question of how mānasapratyakṣa (which is akin to manovijñāna) might relate to svasaṃvitti; how those related doctrines might be brought to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  25. Empty subject terms in buddhist logic: Dignāga and his chinese commentators.Zhihua Yao - 2009 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 37 (4):383-398.
    The problem of empty terms is one of the focal issues in analytic philosophy. Russell’s theory of descriptions, a proposal attempting to solve this problem, attracted much attention and is considered a hallmark of the analytic tradition. Scholars of Indian and Buddhist philosophy, e.g., McDermott, Matilal, Shaw and Perszyk, have studied discussions of empty terms in Indian and Buddhist philosophy. But most of these studies rely heavily on the Nyāya or Navya-Nyāya sources, in which Buddhists are portrayed as opponents to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  26.  33
    How to Refer to a Thing by a Word: Another Difference Between Dignāga’s and Kumārila’s Theories of Denotation.Kiyotaka Yoshimizu - 2011 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 39 (4-5):571-587.
    In studies of Indian theories of meaning it has been standard procedure to examine their relevance to the ontological issues between Brahmin realism about universals and Buddhist nominalism. It is true that Kumārila makes efforts to secure the real existence of a generic property denoted by a word by criticizing Dignāga, who declares that the real world consists of absolutely unique individuals. The present paper, however, concentrates on the linguistic approaches Dignāga and Kumārila adopt to deny or to prove the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  27. Dignāga's ālambanaparīk $\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{\smash{\scriptscriptstyle\cdot}$}}{s}$}}{s} " />āv $\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{\smash{\scriptscriptstyle\cdot}$}}{r}$}}{r} " />tti. [REVIEW]Fernando Tola & Carmen Dragonetti - 1982 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 10 (2).
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  28
    The concept of svasaṃvedana in Dignāga and Candrakīrti.Tsering Nurboo - 2022 - Asian Philosophy 32 (4):448-465.
    The concept of reflexive awareness (Sanskrit svasaṃvedana or svasaṃvitti, Tibetan rang rig) is considered an important epistemological notion in the Dignāga tradition of Buddhist pramāṇa theory. The traditionally accepted view is that Dignāga advocates Yogācāra’s notion of reflexive awareness in the Pramāṇasamuccaya and Candrakīrti rejects it altogether. By contrast, the present paper revisits Dignāga and Candrakīrti in the context of svasaṃvedana and argues that Dignāga endorses the antarjñeyavādic notion of svasaṃvedana and Candrakīrti does not negate it at the conventional level. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Richard Hayes, Dignaga on the Interpretation of Signs Reviewed by.Debabrata Sinha - 1989 - Philosophy in Review 9 (8):310-312.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  27
    How Can the Word “Cow” Exclude Non-cows? Description of Meaning in Dignāga’s Theory of Apoha.Kiyotaka Yoshimizu - 2017 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 45 (5):973-1012.
    Dignāga’s theory of semantics called the “theory of apoha ” has been criticized by those who state that it may lead to a circular argument wherein “exclusion of others” is understood as mere double negation. Dignāga, however, does not intend mere double negation by anyāpoha. In his view, the word “cow” for instance, excludes those that do not have the set of features such as a dewlap, horns, and so on, by applying the semantic method called componential analysis. The present (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31. Self-awareness (svasaṃvedana) and Infinite Regresses: A Comparison of Arguments by Dignāga and Dharmakīrti.Birgit Kellner - 2011 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 39 (4-5):411-426.
    This paper compares and contrasts two infinite regress arguments against higher-order theories of consciousness that were put forward by the Buddhist epistemologists Dignāga (ca. 480–540 CE) and Dharmakīrti (ca. 600–660). The two arguments differ considerably from each other, and they also differ from the infinite regress argument that scholars usually attribute to Dignāga or his followers. The analysis shows that the two philosophers, in these arguments, work with different assumptions for why an object-cognition must be cognised: for Dignāga it must (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  32. Who's Afraid of Non-Conceptuality? Rehabilitating Dignaga's Distinction Between Perception and Thought.Sonam Kachru - 2019 - In Jay Garfield (ed.), Wilfrid Sellars and Buddhist Philosophy. New York, USA: Routledge. pp. 172-199.
    This chapter looks at Dignaga's insistence on the non--conceptuality of perceptual experience in the light of Sellars' critique of the myth of the given as well as his other philosophical committments.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  6
    Buddhist Formal Logic. A study of Dignaga's Hetucakra and K'uei-chi's Great Commentary on the Nyayapravesa. R.S.Y. Chi.Alban Cooke - 1986 - Buddhist Studies Review 3 (1):79-81.
    Buddhist Formal Logic. A study of Dignaga's Hetucakra and K'uei-chi's Great Commentary on the Nyayapravesa. R.S.Y. Chi. Royal Asiatic Society, London 1969; revised edition, Motilal Banarsidass, Delhi 1984. lxxxii + 222 pp. Rs. 100.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  16
    The Buddhist Pramāṇa-Epistemology, Logic, and Language: with Reference to Vasubandhu, Dignāga, and Dharmakīrti.Hari Shankar Prasad - 2023 - Studia Humana 12 (1-2):21-52.
    As the title of the present article shows, it highlights the three philosophically integrated areas – (1) pramāṇa-epistemology (theory of comprehensive knowledge involving both perception and inference), (2) logic (although a part of pramāṇa-epistemology, it has two modes, namely, inductive reasoning and deductive reasoning), and (3) language (or semantics, i.e. the double negation theory of meaning, which falls under inference). These are interconnected as well as overlapping within the Buddhist mainstream tradition of the process philosophy as opposed to the substantialist (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Once Again on Dharmakirti's Deviation from "Dignaga" on Pratyaks'bhasa".Eli Franco - 1986 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 14:79.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  36.  11
    Knowing the Real: Nonduality and Idealism in Dignāga, Dharmakīrti, and Lonergan.Matthew Z. Vale - 2022 - Buddhist-Christian Studies 42 (1):217-236.
    Abstractabstract:A desideratum for Buddhist-Christian exchange is more first-order philosophical engagement—engagement that brings our traditions into direct conversation on genuinely shared first-order questions. To converse in that way, we have to identify shared philosophical loci, areas where our systems are—as much as this is possible—reflecting on the same problem, or the same data. This essay identifies one such shared locus, so that the Christian philosopher Bernard Lonergan (1904–1984) can philosophize together with the broadly Yogācārin authors Dignāga (ca. 480–540 ce) and Dharmakīrti (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Richard Hayes, Dignaga on the Interpretation of Signs. [REVIEW]Debabrata Sinha - 1989 - Philosophy in Review 9:310-312.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  57
    Buddhist Formal Logic: A Study of Dignāga's Hetucakra and K'uei-chi's Great Commentary on the NyāyapraveśaBuddhist Formal Logic: A Study of Dignaga's Hetucakra and K'uei-chi's Great Commentary on the Nyayapravesa.Richard P. Hayes & R. S. Y. Chi - 1987 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 107 (3):496.
  39.  14
    The Significance of Xiong Shili's Interpretation of Dignāga's Ālambana‐parīkṢā.John Makeham - 2013 - Journal of Chinese Philosophy 40 (S1):205-225.
    This essay is an exercise in intellectual archaeology in which I seek to show that already in Xiong Shili's first account of Yogācāra, Weishixue Gailun , we are able to find the first indications of a critical attitude to Yogācāra that would grow in intensity over the following two decades. These critiques served the rhetorical purpose of bolstering the authority of Xuanzang . Before long, however, Xiong even rejected that authority.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  11
    The Significance of Xiong Shili’s Interpretation of Dignāga’s Ālambana-Parīkṣā.John Makeham - 2013 - Journal of Chinese Philosophy 40 (5):205-225.
    This essay is an exercise in intellectual archaeology in which I seek to show that already in Xiong Shili’s first account of Yogācāra, Weishixue Gailun, we are able to find the first indications of a critical attitude to Yogācāra that would grow in intensity over the following two decades. These critiques served the rhetorical purpose of bolstering the authority of Xuanzang. Before long, however, Xiong even rejected that authority.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  25
    Critique of Indian Realism: A Study of the Conflict between the Nyaya-Vaisesika & the Buddhist Dignaga School.Karl H. Potter - 1966 - Philosophy East and West 16 (1):97-99.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Once again on dharmakīrti's deviation from dignāga on pratyak $\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{\smash{\scriptscriptstyle\cdot}$}}{s}$}}{s} " />âbhāsa. [REVIEW]Eli Franco - 1986 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 14 (1).
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  43. Self-awareness and mental perception.Hisayasu Kobayashi - 2010 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 38 (3):233-245.
    The purpose of this paper is to clarify Prajñākaragupta’s view of mental perception ( mānasapratyakṣa ), with special emphasis on the relationship between mental perception and self-awareness. Dignāga, in his PS 1.6ab, says: “mental [perception] ( mānasa ) is [of two kinds:] a cognition of an [external] object and awareness of one’s own mental states such as passion.” According to his commentator Jinendrabuddhi, a cognition of an external object and awareness of an internal object such as passion are here equally (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  44. Consciousness and Self-awareness.Chien-Hsing Ho - 2007 - Asian Philosophy 17 (3):213–230.
    In this paper I propose to inquire into the theory of self-awareness propounded by the two Buddhist epistemologists, Dignaga and Dharmakirti. I first give an outline of the Buddhist notion of consciousness, then deal with the notion of objectual appearance, and finally dwell on the theory itself together with certain arguments in its favor. It is shown that the Buddhists subscribed themselves to the following self-awareness thesis: that our waking consciousness is always pre-reflectively and nonconceptually aware of itself. Adopting (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  45.  34
    Remarks on the Origin of All-Inclusive Pervasion.Kiyokuni Shiga - 2011 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 39 (4-5):521-534.
    Previous studies have claimed that the term ‘all-inclusive pervasion’ ( sarvopasaṃhāravyāpti ) appeared for the first time in the Hetubindu , and that it was Dharmakīrti who created this theory. This article attempts to modify this view and to show that the prototype of this theory can already be found in Dignāga’s system of logic. Dignāga states in the third chapter of the Pramāṇasamuccayavṛtti that the co-existence of a logical reason with what is to be proved is understood by means (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46. Is consciousness reflexively self‐aware? A Buddhist analysis.Bronwyn Finnigan - 2018 - Ratio 31 (4):389-401.
    This article examines contemporary Buddhist defences of the idea that consciousness is reflexively aware or self-aware. Call this the Self-Awareness Thesis. A version of this thesis was historically defended by Dignāga but rejected by Prāsaṅgika Mādhyamika Buddhists. Prāsaṅgikas historically advanced four main arguments against this thesis. In this paper I consider whether some contemporary defence of the Self-Awareness Thesis can withstand these Prāsaṅgika objections. A problem is that contemporary defenders of the Self-Awareness Thesis have subtly different accounts with different assessment (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  47.  86
    Dharmakīrti on the role of causation in inference as presented in pramāṇavārttika svopajñavṛtti 11–38.Brendan S. Gillon & Richard P. Hayes - 2008 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 36 (3):335-404.
    In the svārthānumāna chapter of his Pramāṇavārttika, the Buddhist philosopher Dharmakīrti presented a defense of his claim that legitimate inference must rest on a metaphysical basis if it is to be immune from the risks ordinarily involved in inducing general principles from a finite number of observations. Even if one repeatedly observes that x occurs with y and never observes y in the absence of x, there is no guarantee, on the basis of observation alone, that one will never observe (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48.  29
    Once Again on the *Hetucakraḍamaru: Rotating the Wheels.Huanhuan He & Leonard W. J. van der Kuijp - 2016 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 44 (2):267-302.
    The little versified treatise on the elements of Buddhist logic, often referred to as the Hetucakraḍamaru, is usually attributed to Dignāga. It is only available in a Tibetan translation and quotations from a few of its verses are extant in Sanskrit sources. On the basis of a novel interpretation that is based on a critical edition of the text, we argue that there is a good reason why its title was Hetucakraḍamaru - a ḍamaru is a two-headed drum. The “heads” (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  29
    Who is that Masked Man? Candrakīrti’s Opponent in Prasannapadā I 55.11–58.13.Anne MacDonald - 2011 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 39 (6):677-694.
    The paper aims to determine the identity of an unnamed opponent in a passage of the first chapter of the Prasannapadā whose school affiliation eluded traditional Tibetan scholars and is disputed by modern scholars. The individual(s) in question, whose fundamental ontological views are made evident in the passage’s opening objection as presented by Candrakīrti, has/have alternatively been identified as the Mādhyamika Bhāviveka, as representatives of the Naiyāyika school and, following Stcherbatsky, as Dignāga and/or later members of his epistemological-logical tradition. Although (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  31
    The Notion of Apoha in Chinese Buddhism.Chien-Hsing Ho - 2022 - Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 21 (2):283-298.
    In this essay, I investigate how Chinese Yogācāra scholars of the Tang dynasty explicated and supplemented the theory of apoha (exclusion) propounded by the Indian Buddhist epistemologist Dignāga, according to which a nominal word functions by excluding everything other than its own referent. I first present a brief exposition of the theory. Then, I show that although they had very limited access to Dignāga’s theory, Kuiji and Shentai provide constructive and significant explanations that supplement the theory. I also show that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 119