Results for 'Chris Brink'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  27
    A verisimilar ordering of theories phrased in a propositional language.Chris Brink & Johannes Heidema - 1987 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 38 (4):533-549.
  2.  7
    Verisimilitude: views and reviews.Chris Brink - 1989 - History and Philosophy of Logic 10 (2):181-201.
    This paper is both a survey and a review of the current state of the debate concerning verisimilitude. As a survey it is intended for the interested outsider who wants both easy access to and some comparison between the respective approaches. As a review it covers the first three books on the topic: those of Oddie. Niiniluoto and Kuipers.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  3.  10
    A Paradigm for Program Semantics: Power Structures and Duality.Chris Brink & Ingrid M. Rewitzky - 2001 - Center for the Study of Language and Inf.
    This book provides a synthesis of four versions of program semantic—srelational semantics, predicate transformer semantics, information systems, and domain theory—showing, through an exhaustive case study analysis, that it is possible to do back-and-forth translation from any of these versions of program semantics into any of the others, and demonstrating that while there are many variations of each, in principle they may be thought of as intertranslatable.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  4.  9
    R⌝-algebras and r⌝-model structures as power constructs.Chris Brink - 1989 - Studia Logica 48 (1):85 - 109.
    In relevance logic it has become commonplace to associate with each logic both an algebraic counterpart and a relational counterpart. The former comes from the Lindenbaum construction; the latter, called a model structure, is designed for semantical purposes. Knowing that they are related through the logic, we may enquire after the algebraic relationship between the algebra and the model structure. This paper offers a complete solution for the relevance logic R. Namely, R-algebras and R-model structures can be obtained from each (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  5.  14
    Three dual ontologies.Chris Brink & Ingrid Rewitzky - 2002 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 31 (6):543-568.
    In this paper we give an example of intertranslatability between an ontology of individuals (nominalism), an ontology of properties (realism), and an ontology of facts (factualism). We demonstrate that these three ontologies are dual to each other, meaning that each ontology can be translated into, and recaptured from, each of the others. The aiin of the enterprise is to raise the possibility that, at least in some settings, there may be no need for considerations of ontological primacy. Whether the world (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6.  20
    Verisimilitude by power relations: A response to Oddie.Chris Brink & Johannes Heidema - 1991 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 42 (1):101-104.
  7.  2
    A Note on Peirce and Multiple Conclusion Logic.Chris Brink - 1982 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 18 (4):349 - 351.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  3
    On Peirce's Notation for the Logic of Relatives.Chris Brink - 1978 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 14 (4):285 - 304.
  9.  8
    On Minorities.Chris Brink - 2005 - South African Journal of Philosophy 24 (3):153-175.
    In this paper I present a logical analysis of minorities and minority rights. I consider the question whether the classic social contract of a liberal democracy can be extended to include minorities without significant alteration to the accepted agreement between the individual and the state. S. Afr. J. Philos. Vol.24(3) 2005: 153-175.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  7
    The Responsive University and the Crisis in South Africa.Chris Brink (ed.) - 2021 - Brill | Sense.
    _The Responsive University_ puts forward the proposition that the societal legitimacy of universities depends on whether and how they respond to societal challenges. This issue is exemplified in South Africa, one of the most unequal countries in the world.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  5
    Quine's set theory and the definition of satisfaction.Chris Brink - 1976 - Philosophical Papers 5 (1):11-18.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  11
    The algebra of relatives.Chris Brink - 1979 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 20 (4):900-908.
  13.  8
    Two axiom systems for relation algebras.Chris Brink - 1979 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 20 (4):909-914.
  14.  1
    A comment on relevant truth table logic.Chris Brink - 1992 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 2 (2):243-246.
  15.  11
    Against the notion of Ontological Primacy.Chris Brink - 2004 - South African Journal of Philosophy 23 (3):226-243.
    Historically, it has often been maintained that some particular ontology is the right one. The hard core nominalist, for example, would claim that the world is made up of individual objects and nothing else. Likewise, the realist would stake a claim for properties, and the factualists for facts, as the real building-blocks of the world. In a softer version, each of the three protagonists acknowledge that there may be other things in the world, but still maintain that their own favourite (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  5
    Equality and economy.Chris Brink - 2012 - Perspectives: Policy and Practice in Higher Education 16 (1):29-33.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  5
    Verisimilitude.Chris Brink - 2000 - In W. Newton-Smith (ed.), A companion to the philosophy of science. Malden, Mass.: Blackwell. pp. 561--563.
    At the 1960 International Congress of Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science, and again in his books Conjectures and Refutations (1963) and Objective Knowledge (1972), Karl Popper proposed a formal definition of what it means for one scientific theory to be “closer to the truth” than another (see popper). Such a concept was a necessary ingredient in Popper's philosophy of science, in which all our scientific theories are not only false, but bound to be false. We can never, according to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  1
    Book review. [REVIEW]Chris Brink - 1997 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 6 (3):337-338.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  10
    Computing Verisimilitude.Katarina Britz & Chris Brink - 1995 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 36 (1):30-43.
    This paper continues the power ordering approach to verisimilitude. We define a parameterized verisimilar ordering of theories in the finite propositional case, both semantically and syntactically. The syntactic definition leads to an algorithm for computing verisimilitude. Since the power ordering approach to verisimilitude can be translated into a standard notion of belief revision, the algorithm thereby also allows the computation of membership of a belief-revised theory.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20.  8
    Games with a local permission structure: separation of authority and value generation. [REVIEW]René van den Brink & Chris Dietz - 2014 - Theory and Decision 76 (3):343-361.
    It is known that peer group games are a special class of games with a permission structure. However, peer group games are also a special class of digraph games. To be specific, they are digraph games in which the digraph is the transitive closure of a rooted tree. In this paper we first argue that some known results on solutions for peer group games hold more general for digraph games. Second, we generalize both digraph games as well as games with (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  12
    David Brink , Mill's Progressive Principles . Reviewed by.Chris Barker - 2014 - Philosophy in Review 34 (6):290-292.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  14
    Virtue, Happiness, Knowledge: Themes from the Work of Gail Fine and Terence Irwin by David O. Brink, Susan Sauvé Meyer, and Christopher Shields, eds.Chris Bobonich - 2020 - Philosophical Review 129 (4):646-651.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. A Reply To Wietske Kistner And To Chris Brink On The Relationship Between Propcal (Propositional Calculus) And English.James Moulder - 1984 - South African Journal of Philosophy 3 (February):31-32.
  24. Which Desires Are Relevant to Well‐Being?Chris Heathwood - 2019 - Noûs 53 (3):664-688.
    The desire-satisfaction theory of well-being says, in its simplest form, that a person’s level of welfare is determined by the extent to which their desires are satisfied. A question faced by anyone attracted to such a view is, *Which desires*? This paper proposes a new answer to this question by characterizing a distinction among desires that isn’t much discussed in the well-being literature. This is the distinction between what a person wants in a merely behavioral sense, in that the person (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  25.  22
    The propositional nature of human associative learning.Chris J. Mitchell, Jan De Houwer & Peter F. Lovibond - 2009 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32 (2):183-198.
    The past 50 years have seen an accumulation of evidence suggesting that associative learning depends on high-level cognitive processes that give rise to propositional knowledge. Yet, many learning theorists maintain a belief in a learning mechanism in which links between mental representations are formed automatically. We characterize and highlight the differences between the propositional and link approaches, and review the relevant empirical evidence. We conclude that learning is the consequence of propositional reasoning processes that cooperate with the unconscious processes involved (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   82 citations  
  26.  40
    Justice and Natural Resources: An Egalitarian Theory.Chris Armstrong - 2017 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    Struggles over precious resources such as oil, water, and land are increasingly evident in the contemporary world. States, indigenous groups, and corporations vie to control access to those resources, and the benefits they provide. These conflicts are rapidly spilling over into new arenas, such as the deep oceans and the Polar regions. How should these precious resources be governed, and how should the benefits and burdens they generate be shared? Justice and Natural Resources provides a systematic theory of natural resource (...)
  27.  82
    Metaphysics.Jonas Raab & Chris Daly - forthcoming - In Marcus Rossberg (ed.), The Cambridge Handbook of Analytic Philosophy. Cambridge University Press.
    This entry considers the philosophical subject called 'metaphysics'. There have been many conceptions of metaphysics, and metaphysics has faced severe criticism throughout the history of philosophy and continues to do so. Besides discussing some major trends in analytic metaphysics - understood as 'metaphysics done by analytic philosophers' - we consider some of the criticisms and possible responses.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Desire-Fulfillment Theory.Chris Heathwood - 2016 - In Guy Fletcher (ed.), The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Well-Being. Routledge. pp. 135-147.
    Explains the desire-fulfillment theory of well-being, its history, its development, its varieties, its advantages, and its challenges.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  29. Normative Perfectionism and the Kantian Tradition.David O. Brink - 2019 - Philosophers' Imprint 19.
    Perfectionism is an underexplored tradition, perhaps because of doubts about the grounds, content, and implications of perfectionist ideals. Aristotle, J.S. Mill, and T.H. Green are normative perfectionists, grounding perfectionist ideals in a normative conception of human nature involving personality or agency. This essay explores the prospects of normative perfectionism by examining Kant’s criticisms of the perfectionist tradition. First, Kant claims that the perfectionist can generate only hypothetical, not categorical, imperatives. But insofar as the normative perfectionist appeals to the normative category (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  30. Subjective Theories of Well-Being.Chris Heathwood - 2014 - In Ben Eggleston & Dale E. Miller (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Utilitarianism. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 199-219.
    Subjective theories of well-being claim that how well our lives go for us is a matter of our attitudes towards what we get in life rather than the nature of the things themselves. This article explains in more detail the distinction between subjective and objective theories of well-being; describes, for each approach, some reasons for thinking it is true; outlines the main kinds of subjective theory; and explains their advantages and disadvantages.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  31. The Heteronomy of Choice Architecture.Chris Mills - 2015 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 6 (3):495-509.
    Choice architecture is heralded as a policy approach that does not coercively reduce freedom of choice. Still we might worry that this approach fails to respect individual choice because it subversively manipulates individuals, thus contravening their personal autonomy. In this article I address two arguments to this effect. First, I deny that choice architecture is necessarily heteronomous. I explain the reasons we have for avoiding heteronomous policy-making and offer a set of four conditions for non-heteronomy. I then provide examples of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  32. The Good Life of Teaching: An Ethics of Professional Practice.Chris Higgins - 2011 - Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
    _The Good Life of Teaching_ extends the recent revival of virtue ethics to professional ethics and the philosophy of teaching. It connects long-standing philosophical questions about work and human growth to questions about teacher motivation, identity, and development. Makes a significant contribution to the philosophy of teaching and also offers new insights into virtue theory and professional ethics Offers fresh and detailed readings of major figures in ethics, including Alasdair MacIntyre, Charles Taylor, and Bernard Williams and the practical philosophies of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  33. Unconscious Pleasures and Attitudinal Theories of Pleasure.Chris Heathwood - 2018 - Utilitas 30 (2):219-227.
    This paper responds to a new objection, due to Ben Bramble, against attitudinal theories of sensory pleasure and pain: the objection from unconscious pleasures and pains. According to the objection, attitudinal theories are unable to accommodate the fact that sometimes we experience pleasures and pains of which we are, at the time, unaware. In response, I distinguish two kinds of unawareness and argue that the subjects in the examples that support the objection are unaware of their sensations in only a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  34.  20
    Mill's deliberative utilitarianism.David O. Brink - 1992 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 21 (1):67-103.
  35.  36
    Situationism, responsibility, and fair opportunity.David O. Brink - 2013 - Social Philosophy and Policy 30 (1-2):121-149.
    The situationist literature in psychology claims that conduct is not determined by character and reflects the operation of the agent's situation or environment. For instance, due to situational factors, compassionate behavior is much less common than we might have expected from people we believe to be compassionate. This article focuses on whether situationism should revise our beliefs about moral responsibility. It assesses the implications of situationism against the backdrop of a conception of responsibility that is grounded in norms about the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  36. Rational egoism and the separateness of persons.David O. Brink - 1997 - In J. Dancy (ed.), Reading Parfit. Blackwell. pp. 96--134.
  37.  40
    Hilbert-style axiomatic completion: On von Neumann and hidden variables in quantum mechanics.Chris Mitsch - 2022 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 95 (C):84-95.
  38. The significance of desire.David O. Brink - 2008 - Oxford Studies in Metaethics 3:5-45.
  39. Not the optimistic type.Ben Caplan, Chris Tillman, Brian McLean & Adam Murray - 2013 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 43 (5):575-589.
    In recent work, Peter Hanks and Scott Soames argue that propositions are types whose tokens are acts, states, or events. Let’s call this view the type view. Hanks and Soames think that one of the virtues of the type view is that it allows them to explain why propositions have semantic properties. But, in this paper, we argue that their explanations aren’t satisfactory. In Section 2, we present the type view. In Section 3, we present one explanation—due to Hanks (2007, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  40.  55
    The Nature and Significance of Culpability.David O. Brink - 2019 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 13 (2):347-373.
    Culpability is not a unitary concept within the criminal law, and it is important to distinguish different culpability concepts and the work they do. Narrow culpability is an ingredient in wrongdoing itself, describing the agent’s elemental mens rea. Broad culpability is the responsibility condition that makes wrongdoing blameworthy and without which wrongdoing is excused. Inclusive culpability is the combination of wrongdoing and responsibility or broad culpability that functions as the retributivist desert basis for punishment. Each of these kinds of culpability (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  41.  12
    Thinking in, with, across, and beyond cases with John Forrester.Chris Millard & Felicity Callard - 2020 - History of the Human Sciences 33 (3-4):3-14.
    We consider the influence that John Forrester’s work has had on thinking in, with, and from cases in multiple disciplines. Forrester’s essay ‘If p, Then What? Thinking in Cases’ was published in History of the Human Sciences in 1996 and transformed understandings of what a case was, and how case-based thinking worked in numerous human sciences. Forrester’s collection of essays Thinking in Cases was published posthumously, after his untimely death in 2015, and is the inspiration for the special issue we (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  42. Organic Unities.Chris Heathwood - 2013 - In Hugh LaFollette (ed.), The International Encyclopedia of Ethics. Hoboken, NJ: Blackwell.
    A short encyclopedia entry on the issue of whether the value of a whole is equal to the sum of the values of its parts.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  43. Monism and Pluralism about Value.Chris Heathwood - 2015 - In Iwao Hirose & Jonas Olson (eds.), Oxford Handbook of Value Theory. Oxford University Press. pp. 136-157.
    This essay discusses monism and pluralism about two related evaluative notions: welfare, or what makes people better off, and value simpliciter, or what makes the world better. These are stipulatively referred to as 'axiological value'. Axiological value property monists hold that one of these notions is reducible to the other (or else eliminable), while axiological value property pluralists deny this. Substantive monists about axiological value hold that there is just one basic kind of thing that makes our lives or the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  44.  29
    Moral and epistemic open-question arguments.Chris Heathwood - 2009 - Philosophical Books 50 (2):83-98.
    An important and widely-endorsed argument for moral realism is based on alleged parallels between that doctrine and epistemic realism -- roughly the view that there are genuine epistemic facts, facts such as that it is reasonable to believe that astrology is false. I argue for an important disanalogy between moral and epistemic facts. Epistemic facts, but not moral facts, are plausibly identifiable with mere descriptive facts about the world. This is because, whereas the much-discussed moral open-question argument is compelling, the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  45.  12
    Welfare.Chris Heathwood - 2010 - In John Skorupski (ed.), The Routledge Companion to Ethics. Routledge. pp. 645-655.
    An introduction to the philosophical debate over what makes a person's life go well. It attempts to clarify the question of welfare and to explore several of the most important answers, while displaying the main contours of the dialectic.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  46.  1
    Mill's moral and political philosophy.David Brink - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  47.  20
    Philosophy of science and the Kyoto school: an introduction to Nishida Kitarō, Tanabe Hajime and Tosaka Jun.Dean Anthony Brink - 2021 - New York: Bloomsbury Academic.
    This book offers the first introduction to a major Japanese philosophical movement through the interests and arguments of its founder, Nishida Kitaro (1870-1945), his successor, Tanabe Hajime (1885-1962), and student-turned-critic, Tosaka Jun (1900-1945). Focusing on their contributions to thinking about place, space, and dialectics, this concise introduction brings these influential thinkers to life by connecting their work to issues still debated in the philosophy of science and physics today. Beginning with an overview of the reception of quantum physics and relativity (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48. The Separateness of Persons, Distributive Norms, and Moral Theory.David Brink - 1993 - In R. G. Frey & Christopher Morris (eds.), Value, Welfare, and Morality. Cambridge University Press. pp. 252-289.
  49. Happiness and Desire Satisfaction.Chris Heathwood - 2022 - Noûs 56 (1):57-83.
    This paper develops and defends a novel version of a relatively neglected category of theory of the nature of happiness: the desire-satisfaction theory. My account is similar in its fundamentals to Wayne Davis’s theory of happiness-as-subjective-desire-satisfaction. After arguing that this is the best general way to proceed for the desire-based approach, I develop an improved version of subjective desire satisfactionism in light of recent arguments in the happiness literature.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50. The Significance of Desire.David O. Brink - 2008 - In Russ Shafer-Landau (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics: Volume Iii. Oxford University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000