Results for 'geometric means'

984 found
Order:
  1.  15
    On geometric mean fitness: a reply to Takacs and Bourrat.Bengt Autzen & Samir Okasha - 2022 - Biology and Philosophy 37 (5):1-7.
    In a recent paper, Takacs and Bourrat (Biol Philos 37:12, 2022) examine the use of geometric mean reproductive output as a measure of biological fitness. We welcome Takacs and Bourrat’s scrutiny of a fitness definition that some philosophers have adopted uncritically. We also welcome Takacs and Bourrat’s attempt to marry the philosophical literature on fitness with the biological literature on mathematical measures of fitness. However, some of the main claims made by Takacs and Bourrat are not correct, while others (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  2.  48
    The Geometrical Meaning of Time.Asher Yahalom - 2008 - Foundations of Physics 38 (6):489-497.
    It is stated in many text books that the any metric appearing in general relativity should be locally Lorentzian i.e. of the type η μ ν =diag (1,−1,−1,−1) this is usually presented as an independent axiom of the theory, which can not be deduced from other assumptions. The meaning of this assertion is that a specific coordinate (the temporal coordinate) is given a unique significance with respect to the other spatial coordinates. In this work it is shown that the above (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Human bisection at the geometric mean.Lg Allan & J. Gibbon - 1989 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 27 (6):529-529.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  4. √ −1 as geometric mean Wallis' proof of.Adrian Heathcote - unknown
    The geometric mean is also called the mean proportional. This is how the mathematicians of the √ −1. 19th Century, such as Gauss, understood..
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  66
    The arithmetic mean of what? A Cautionary Tale about the Use of the Geometric Mean as a Measure of Fitness.Peter Takacs & Pierrick Bourrat - 2022 - Biology and Philosophy 37 (2):1-22.
    Showing that the arithmetic mean number of offspring for a trait type often fails to be a predictive measure of fitness was a welcome correction to the philosophical literature on fitness. While the higher mathematical moments of a probability-weighted offspring distribution can influence fitness measurement in distinct ways, the geometric mean number of offspring is commonly singled out as the most appropriate measure. For it is well-suited to a compounding process and is sensitive to variance in offspring number. The (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  6.  18
    Singer's definition and the generalized law of the geometric mean in numerical estimation.C. C. Lienau - 1934 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 17 (2):189.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  2
    On the effective permeability of a heterogeneous porous medium: the role of the geometric mean.P. A. Selvadurai & A. P. S. Selvadurai - 2014 - Philosophical Magazine 94 (20):2318-2338.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  13
    Geometric and arithmetic means as indexes of UCS intensity with variable reinforcement.George E. Passey & Francis Sekyra - 1964 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 67 (1):7.
  9. Geometric conventionalism and carnap's principle of tolerance: We discuss in this paper the question of the scope of the principle of tolerance about languages promoted in Carnap's The Logical Syntax of Language and the nature of the analogy between it and the rudimentary conventionalism purportedly exhibited in the work of Poincaré and Hilbert. We take it more or less for granted that Poincaré and Hilbert do argue for conventionalism. We begin by sketching Coffa's historical account, which suggests that tolerance be interpreted as a conventionalism that allows us complete freedom to select whatever language we wish—an interpretation that generalizes the conventionalism promoted by Poincaré and Hilbert which allows us complete freedom to select whatever axiom system we wish for geometry. We argue that such an interpretation saddles Carnap with a theory of meaning that has unhappy consequences, a theory we believe he did not hold. We suggest that the principle of linguistic tolerance in.David De Vidi & Graham Solomon - 1993 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 25 (5):773-783.
    We discuss in this paper the question of the scope of the principle of tolerance about languages promoted in Carnap's The Logical Syntax of Language and the nature of the analogy between it and the rudimentary conventionalism purportedly exhibited in the work of Poincaré and Hilbert. We take it more or less for granted that Poincaré and Hilbert do argue for conventionalism. We begin by sketching Coffa's historical account, which suggests that tolerance be interpreted as a conventionalism that allows us (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. The geometric methodology of Hobbes, Thomas-origin and meaning.J. Prins - 1988 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 50 (2):248-251.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Geometrizing the meaning. An interview with Peter Gardenfors.Andrej Demuth & Peter Gaerdenfors - 2013 - Filozofia 68 (7):621-624.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. The origin and meaning of geometrical axioms.H. Helmholtz - 1876 - Mind 1 (3):301-321.
    The object in this article is to discuss the philosophical bearing of recent inquiries concerning geometrical axioms and the possibility of working out analytically other systems of geometry with other axioms than Euclid's. Digital edition compiled by Gabriele Dörflinger, Heidelberg University Library.
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  13. The origin and meaning of geometrical axioms.H. Helmholtz - 1878 - Mind 3 (10):212-225.
    The object in this article is to discuss the philosophical bearing of recent inquiries concerning geometrical axioms and the possibility of working out analytically other systems of geometry with other axioms than Euclid's. Digital edition compiled by Gabriele Dörflinger, Heidelberg University Library.
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  14. Interaction of color and geometric cues in depth perception: When does red mean "near"?Christophe Guibal & Birgitta Dresp - 2004 - Psychological Research 69:30-40.
    Luminance and color are strong and self-sufficient cues to pictorial depth in visual scenes and images. The present study investigates the conditions Under which luminance or color either strengthens or overrides geometric depth cues. We investigated how luminance contrasts associated with color contrast interact with relative height in the visual field, partial occlusion, and interposition in determining the probability that a given figure is perceived as ‘‘nearer’’ than another. Latencies of ‘‘near’’ responses were analyzed to test for effects of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  15.  23
    I.—the origin and meaning of geometrical axioms.H. Helmholtz - 1876 - Mind 1 (3):301-321.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  16.  43
    Visualizing as a Means of Geometrical Discovery.Marcus Giaquinto - 1992 - Mind and Language 7 (4):382-401.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  17. Geometrical premisses in Aristotle’s Incessu animalium and kind-crossing.Lucas Angioni - 2018 - Anais de Filosofia Clássica 24 (12):53-71.
    At some point in the Incessu Animalium, Aristotle appeals to some geometrical claims in order to explain why animal progression necessarily involves the bending (of the limbs), and this appeal to geometrical claims might be taking as violating the recommendation to avoid “kind-crossing” (as found in the Posterior Analytic). But a very unclear notion of kind-crossing has been assumed in most debates. I will argue that kind-crossing in the Posterior Analytics does not mean any employment of premises from a discipline (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  18. On geometric objects, the non-existence of a gravitational stress-energy tensor, and the uniqueness of the Einstein field equation.Erik Curiel - 2009 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 66:90-102.
    The question of the existence of gravitational stress-energy in general relativity has exercised investigators in the field since the inception of the theory. Folklore has it that no adequate definition of a localized gravitational stress-energetic quantity can be given. Most arguments to that effect invoke one version or another of the Principle of Equivalence. I argue that not only are such arguments of necessity vague and hand-waving but, worse, are beside the point and do not address the heart of the (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  19. Geometric foundations of classical yang–mills theory.Gabriel Catren - 2008 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 39 (3):511-531.
    We analyze the geometric foundations of classical Yang-Mills theory by studying the relationships between internal relativity, locality, global/local invariance, and background independence. We argue that internal relativity and background independence are the two independent defining principles of Yang-Mills theory. We show that local gauge invariance -heuristically implemented by means of the gauge argument- is a direct consequence of internal relativity. Finally, we analyze the conceptual meaning of BRST symmetry in terms of the invariance of the gauge fixed theory (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  20.  47
    Geometric Representations for Minimalist Grammars.Peter Beim Graben & Sabrina Gerth - 2012 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 21 (4):393-432.
    We reformulate minimalist grammars as partial functions on term algebras for strings and trees. Using filler/role bindings and tensor product representations, we construct homomorphisms for these data structures into geometric vector spaces. We prove that the structure-building functions as well as simple processors for minimalist languages can be realized by piecewise linear operators in representation space. We also propose harmony, i.e. the distance of an intermediate processing step from the final well-formed state in representation space, as a measure of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  94
    A geometric approach to quantum mechanics.J. Anandan - 1991 - Foundations of Physics 21 (11):1265-1284.
    It is argued that quantum mechanics is fundamentally a geometric theory. This is illustrated by means of the connection and symplectic structures associated with the projective Hilbert space, using which the geometric phase can be understood. A prescription is given for obtaining the geometric phase from the motion of a time dependent invariant along a closed curve in a parameter space, which may be finite dimensional even for nonadiabatic cyclic evolutions in an infinite dimensional Hilbert space. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  22.  33
    Geometric significance of the spinor Lie derivative. II.V. Jhangiani - 1978 - Foundations of Physics 8 (7-8):593-601.
    The formulas for the Lie covariant differentiation of spinors are deduced from an algebraic viewpoint. The Lie covariant derivative of the spinor connection is calculated, and is given a geometric meaning. A theorem about the Lie covariant derivative of an operator in spin space that was stated in Part I of this work is discussed.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  24
    Mathematical Thinking and Geometric Exploration in Africa and Elsewhere.Paulus Gerdes - 2004 - Diogenes 51 (2):107-122.
    The author was invited by the organizers of the Benin symposium on the encounter between rationalities to contribute from the particular perspective of his research experience in ethno-mathematics – the study of mathematical ideas and practices as embedded in their cultural contexts. In this article he tries to contribute to the understanding of mathematical reasoning, as embedded in cultural practices, by means of illuminating some complementary aspects of geometrical exploration in diverse cultural contexts. He ends by offering a few (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  8
    On how some fundamental chemical concepts are correlated by arithmetic, geometric and harmonic means.Francesco Di Giacomo - 2023 - Foundations of Chemistry 25 (2):265-268.
    Examples are given of applications by Pauling, Mulliken, Marcus and G.E.Kimball of the three Pythagorian means to formulate the scales of electronegativity of the elements, to the calculations of rate constants of electron transfer cross-reactions, to the calculation of the observed rate constant as function of activation and diffusion rate constants in the case of mixed reaction-diffusion rates and to the calculation of the effective diffusion coefficient in solution of a salt AB as a whole from the diffusion coefficients (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  55
    Geometrical First Principles in Proclus’ Commentary on the First Book of Euclid’s Elements.D. Gregory MacIsaac - 2014 - Phronesis 59 (1):44-98.
    In his commentary on Euclid, Proclus says both that the first principle of geometry are self-evident and that they are hypotheses received from the single, highest, unhypothetical science, which is probably dialectic. The implication of this seems to be that a geometer both does and does not know geometrical truths. This dilemma only exists if we assume that Proclus follows Aristotle in his understanding of these terms. This paper shows that this is not the case, and explains what Proclus himself (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26.  11
    Geometrical Studies.Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel - 2008 - Hegel Bulletin 29 (1-2):132-153.
    The fragmentary nature ofGSmakes it difficult to read as it stands, and for this reason, I have rearranged the material slightly so that it falls into four primary, reasonably coherent, parts. Their titles are: ‘The nature of mathematical objects’, ‘Thirteen propositions of Euclid 1’, ‘The philosophy of parallel lines’ and ‘On the algebra of geometrical figures’.GSactually starts with ‘Thirteen propositions of Euclid 1’. The justification for the reversal of order in the translation is to have Hegel's philosophical basis for geometry (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. A Geometric Look at Manipulation.Jan van Eijck - unknown
    We take a fresh look at voting theory, in particular at the notion of manipulation, by employing the geometry of the Saari triangle. This yields a geometric proof of the Gibbard/Satterthwaite theorem, and new insight into what it means to manipulate the vote. Next, we propose two possible strengthenings of the notion of manipulability (or weakenings of the notion of non-manipulability), and analyze how these affect the impossibility proof for non-manipulable voting rules.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  18
    The theorem of the means for cardinal and ordinal numbers.George Rousseau - 1993 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 39 (1):279-286.
    The theorem that the arithmetic mean is greater than or equal to the geometric mean is investigated for cardinal and ordinal numbers. It is shown that whereas the theorem of the means can be proved for n pairwise comparable cardinal numbers without the axiom of choice, the inequality a2 + b2 ≥ 2ab is equivalent to the axiom of choice. For ordinal numbers, the inequality α2 + β2 ≥ 2αβ is established and the conditions for equality are derived; (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Aristotle on Geometrical Potentialities.Naoya Iwata - 2021 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 59 (3):371-397.
    This paper examines Aristotle's discussion of the priority of actuality to potentiality in geometry at Metaphysics Θ9, 1051a21–33. Many scholars have assumed what I call the "geometrical construction" interpretation, according to which his point here concerns the relation between an inquirer's thinking and a geometrical figure. In contrast, I defend what I call the "geometrical analysis" interpretation, according to which it concerns the asymmetrical relation between geometrical propositions in which one is proved by means of the other. His argument (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  68
    Meaning in Spinoza’s Method.Aaron V. Garrett - 2003 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Readers of Spinoza's philosophy have often been daunted, and sometimes been enchanted, by the geometrical method which he employs in his philosophical masterpiece the Ethics. In Meaning in Spinoza's Method Aaron Garrett examines this method and suggests that its purpose, in Spinoza's view, was not just to present claims and propositions but also in some sense to change the readers and allow them to look at themselves and the world in a different way. His discussion draws not only on Spinoza's (...)
  31.  15
    Using of optimization geometric design methods for the problems of the spent nuclear fuel safe storage.Chugay A. M. & Alyokhina S. V. - 2020 - Artificial Intelligence Scientific Journal 25 (3):51-63.
    Packing optimization problems have a wide spectrum of real-word applications. One of the applications of the problems is problem of placement of containers with spent nuclear fuel on the storage platform. The solution of the problem can be reduced to the solution of the problem of finding the optimal placement of a given set of congruent circles into a multiconnected domain taking into account technological restrictions. A mathematical model of the prob-lem is constructed and its peculiarities are considered. Our approach (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Spinoza’s Ontology Geometrically Illustrated: A Reading of Ethics IIP8S.Valtteri Viljanen - 2018 - In Beth Lord (ed.), Spinoza’s Philosophy of Ratio. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. pp. 5-18.
    This essay offers an in-depth reading of the geometrical illustration of Ethics IIP8S and shows how it can be used to explicate the whole architecture of Spinoza’s system by specifying the way in which all the key structural features of his basic ontology find their analogies in the example. The illustration can also throw light on Spinoza’s ontology of finite things and inform us about what is at stake when we form universal ideas. In general, my reading of IIP8S thus (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  54
    Understanding geometrical phases in quantum mechanics: An elementary example. [REVIEW]J. C. Solem & L. C. Biedenharn - 1993 - Foundations of Physics 23 (2):185-195.
    We discuss an exact solution to the simplest nontrivial example of a geometrical phase in quantum mechanics. By means of this example: (1) we elucidate the fundamental distinction between rays and vectors in describing quantum mechanical states; (2) we show that superposition of quantal states is invalid; only decomposition is allowed—which is adequate for the measurement process. Our example also shows that the origin of singularities in the analog vector potential is to be found in the unavoidable breaking of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  13
    Gravitational Quantum Dynamics: A Geometrical Perspective.Ivano Tavernelli - 2021 - Foundations of Physics 51 (2):1-24.
    We present a gravitational quantum dynamics theory that combines quantum field theory for particle dynamics in space-time with classical Einstein’s general relativity in a non-Riemannian Finsler space. This approach is based on the geometrization of quantum mechanics proposed in Tavernelli and combines quantum and gravitational effects into a global curvature of the Finsler space induced by the quantum potential associated to the matter quantum fields. In order to make this theory compatible with general relativity, the quantum effects are described in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  10
    The Role of Geometrical Representations – Wittgenstein’s Colour Octahedron and Kuki’s Rectangular Prism of Taste.Shogo Hashimoto - 2022 - Athens Journal of Philosophy 1 (1):9-24.
    In his writings Philosophical Remarks, the Austrian-British Philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein draws an octahedron with the words of pure colours such as “white”, “red” and “blue” at the corners and argues: “The colour octahedron is grammar, since it says that you can speak of a reddish blue but not of a reddish green, etc”. He uses the word “grammar” in such a specific way that the grammar or grammatical rules describe the meanings of words/expressions, in other words, how we use them (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  20
    Hume's Geometric.E. W. Van Steenburgh - 1980 - Hume Studies 6 (1):61-68.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:61. HUME'S GEOMETRIC "OBJECTS" Arithmetic and algebra allow of precision and certainty. The science of geometry is not likewise a perfect and infallible science. At any rate, this is Hume's teaching in the Treatise. When two numbers are so combin ' d, as that the one has always an unite answering to every unite of the other, we pronounce them equal; and 'tis for want of such a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  30
    Hume's Geometric "Objects".E. W. Van Steenburgh - 1980 - Hume Studies 6 (1):61-68.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:61. HUME'S GEOMETRIC "OBJECTS" Arithmetic and algebra allow of precision and certainty. The science of geometry is not likewise a perfect and infallible science. At any rate, this is Hume's teaching in the Treatise. When two numbers are so combin ' d, as that the one has always an unite answering to every unite of the other, we pronounce them equal; and 'tis for want of such a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Le contre Les géomètres de sextus empiricus: Sources, cible, structure.Guillaume Dye & Bernard Vitrac - 2009 - Phronesis 54 (2):155-203.
    In this paper, we examine Sextus Empiricus' treatise Against the geometers . We first set this treatise in the overall context of the sceptic's polemics against the liberal arts. After a discussion of Sextus' attitude to the quadrivium , we discuss the structure, the sources and the target of the Against the geometers . It appears that Euclid is not Sextus' source, and neither he, nor the professional geometers, seem to be Sextus' main targets. Of course, Sextus never really makes (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  39.  68
    The Extended Relativity Theory in Born-Clifford Phase Spaces with a Lower and Upper Length Scales and Clifford Group Geometric Unification.Carlos Castro - 2005 - Foundations of Physics 35 (6):971-1041.
    We construct the Extended Relativity Theory in Born-Clifford-Phase spaces with an upper R and lower length λ scales (infrared/ultraviolet cutoff). The invariance symmetry leads naturally to the real Clifford algebra Cl (2, 6, R) and complexified Clifford Cl C (4) algebra related to Twistors. A unified theory of all Noncommutative branes in Clifford-spaces is developed based on the Moyal-Yang star product deformation quantization whose deformation parameter involves the lower/upper scale $$(\hbar \lambda / R)$$. Previous work led us to show from (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  40.  46
    The Perceptual Roots of Geometric Idealizations.John J. Drummond - 1984 - Review of Metaphysics 37 (4):785 - 810.
    EDMUND HUSSERL in his early writings on space distinguishes three kinds of problems surrounding the presentation of space: psychological, logical, and metaphysical. By the term "psychology" Husserl means a descriptive and genetic psychology which seeks to characterize the contents and structure of particular experiences and to investigate the genetic relations between different experiences. Included among the genetic questions concerning space is the problem of the origin of the science of space.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  41.  43
    Isaac Barrow on the Mathematization of Nature: Theological Voluntarism and the Rise of Geometrical Optics.Antoni Malet - 1997 - Journal of the History of Ideas 58 (2):265-287.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Isaac Barrow on the Mathematization of Nature: Theological Voluntarism and the Rise of Geometrical OpticsAntoni MaletIntroductionIsaac Newton’s Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy embodies a strong program of mathematization that departs both from the mechanical philosophy of Cartesian inspiration and from Boyle’s experimental philosophy. The roots of Newton’s mathematization of nature, this paper aims to demonstrate, are to be found in Isaac Barrow’s (1630–77) philosophy of the mathematical sciences.Barrow’s attitude (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  42.  72
    Musing on Means: Fitness, Expectation, and the Principles of Natural Selection.Bengt Autzen - 2020 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 71 (1):373-389.
    How to measure fitness in the theory of natural selection? A fitness measure that has been proposed in both the biological and the philosophical literature is the expected relative reproductive success. The aim of this article is to examine the relationship between expected relative reproductive success and future actual evolutionary success. Doing so will not only clarify the use of expected relative reproductive success as a fitness measure but also shed light on the role of fitness in the theory of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  36
    Meaning in Spinoza's Method (review).Alan Jean Nelson & Noa Shein - 2005 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 43 (1):118-119.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Meaning in Spinoza’s MethodAlan Nelson and Noa SheinAaron V. Garrett. Meaning in Spinoza’s Method. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2003. Pp. xii + 240. Cloth, $60.00.This is a book about some fundamental aspects of Spinoza's mature metaphysics. The principal focus is on Part I of the Ethics concerning infinite substance, and on Part V concerning the intuitive knowledge that is the goal of philosophy. Within this focus, Garrett (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  6
    Meaning Negotiation.Peter Gärdenfors & Massimo Warglien - 2015 - In Peter Gärdenfors & Frank Zenker (eds.), Applications of Conceptual Spaces : the Case for Geometric Knowledge Representation. Cham: Springer Verlag.
    While “meaning negotiation” has become an ubiquitous term, its use is often confusing. A negotiation problem implies not only a convenience to agree, but also diverging interest on what to agree upon. It implies agreement but also the possibility of disagreement. In this chapter, we look at meaning negotiation as the process through which agents starting from different preferred conceptual representations of an object, an event or a more complex entity, converge to an agreement through some communication medium. We shortly (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  45. Meaning and Demonstration.Matthew Stone & Una Stojnic - 2015 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 6 (1):69-97.
    In demonstration, speakers use real-world activity both for its practical effects and to help make their points. The demonstrations of origami mathematics, for example, reconfigure pieces of paper by folding, while simultaneously allowing their author to signal geometric inferences. Demonstration challenges us to explain how practical actions can get such precise significance and how this meaning compares with that of other representations. In this paper, we propose an explanation inspired by David Lewis’s characterizations of coordination and scorekeeping in conversation. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  46.  70
    ‘…But I still can׳t get rid of a sense of artificiality’: The Reichenbach–Einstein debate on the geometrization of the electromagnetic field.Marco Giovanelli - 2016 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 54:35-51.
    This paper analyzes correspondence between Reichenbach and Einstein from the spring of 1926, concerning what it means to ‘geometrize’ a physical field. The content of a typewritten note that Reichenbach sent to Einstein on that occasion is reconstructed, showing that it was an early version of §49 of the untranslated Appendix to his Philosophie der Raum-Zeit-Lehre, on which Reichenbach was working at the time. This paper claims that the toy-geometrization of the electromagnetic field that Reichenbach presented in his note (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  47. The meaning of category theory for 21st century philosophy.Alberto Peruzzi - 2006 - Axiomathes 16 (4):424-459.
    Among the main concerns of 20th century philosophy was that of the foundations of mathematics. But usually not recognized is the relevance of the choice of a foundational approach to the other main problems of 20th century philosophy, i.e., the logical structure of language, the nature of scientific theories, and the architecture of the mind. The tools used to deal with the difficulties inherent in such problems have largely relied on set theory and its “received view”. There are specific issues, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  48.  81
    What Does It Mean That “Space Can Be Transcendental Without the Axioms Being So”?: Helmholtz’s Claim in Context.Francesca Biagioli - 2014 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 45 (1):1-21.
    In 1870, Hermann von Helmholtz criticized the Kantian conception of geometrical axioms as a priori synthetic judgments grounded in spatial intuition. However, during his dispute with Albrecht Krause (Kant und Helmholtz über den Ursprung und die Bedeutung der Raumanschauung und der geometrischen Axiome. Lahr, Schauenburg, 1878), Helmholtz maintained that space can be transcendental without the axioms being so. In this paper, I will analyze Helmholtz’s claim in connection with his theory of measurement. Helmholtz uses a Kantian argument that can be (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  49.  74
    Applications of Conceptual Spaces : the Case for Geometric Knowledge Representation.Peter Gärdenfors & Frank Zenker (eds.) - 2015 - Cham: Springer Verlag.
    Why is a red face not really red? How do we decide that this book is a textbook or not? Conceptual spaces provide the medium on which these computations are performed, but an additional operation is needed: Contrast. By contrasting a reddish face with a prototypical face, one gets a prototypical ‘red’. By contrasting this book with a prototypical textbook, the lack of exercises may pop out. Dynamic contrasting is an essential operation for converting perceptions into predicates. The existence of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  50.  96
    On the meaning of Hilbert's consistency problem (paris, 1900).Enrico Moriconi - 2003 - Synthese 137 (1-2):129 - 139.
    The theory that ``consistency implies existence'' was put forward by Hilbert on various occasions around the start of the last century, and it was strongly and explicitly emphasized in his correspondence with Frege. Since (Gödel's) completeness theorem, abstractly speaking, forms the basis of this theory, it has become common practice to assume that Hilbert took for granted the semantic completeness of second order logic. In this paper I maintain that this widely held view is untrue to the facts, and that (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 984