Results for 'arithmetical representation'

989 found
Order:
  1.  45
    Arithmetical representations of brownian motion I.Willem Fouché - 2000 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 65 (1):421-442.
    We discuss ways in which a typical one-dimensional Brownian motion can be approximated by oscillations which are encoded by finite binary strings of high descriptive complexity. We study the recursive properties of Brownian motions that can be thus obtained.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  2.  18
    Arithmetical representation of recursively enumerable sets.Raphael M. Robinson - 1956 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 21 (2):162-186.
  3. Arithmetical Representations of Brownian Motion I.Willem Fouche - 2000 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 65 (1):421-442.
    We discuss ways in which a typical one-dimensional Brownian motion can be approximated by oscillations which are encoded by finite binary strings of high descriptive complexity. We study the recursive properties of Brownian motions that can be thus obtained.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  12
    Robinson Raphael M.. Arithmetical representation of recursively enumerable sets. [REVIEW]Hilary Putnam - 1959 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 24 (2):170-171.
  5.  30
    Representational Structures of Arithmetical Thinking: Part I.Wojciech Krysztofiak - 2016 - Axiomathes 26 (1):1-40.
    In this paper, representational structures of arithmetical thinking, encoded in human minds, are described. On the basis of empirical research, it is possible to distinguish four types of mental number lines: the shortest mental number line, summation mental number lines, point-place mental number lines and mental lines of exact numbers. These structures may be treated as generative mechanisms of forming arithmetical representations underlying our numerical acts of reference towards cardinalities, ordinals and magnitudes. In the paper, the theoretical framework (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6.  3
    Review: Yu. V. Matiyasevich, A. O. Slisenko, Arithmetic Representations of Powers. [REVIEW]Ann S. Ferebee - 1972 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 37 (3):605-605.
  7.  21
    Ú. V. Matiásévič Arifmétičéskié prédstavléniá stépénéj. Isslédovaniá po konstruktivnoj matématiké i matématičéskoj logiké, II, edited by A. O. Slisénko, Zapiski Naučnyh Séminarov Léningradskogo Otdéléniá Ordéna Lénina Matématičéskogo Instituta im. V. A. Stéklova AN SSSR, vol. 8, Izdatél'stvo “Nauka,” Leningrad 1968, pp. 159–165. - Yu. V. Mattyasevich. Arithmetic representations of powers. English translation of the preceding. Studies in constructive mathematics and mathematical logic, Part II, edited by A. O. Slisenko, Seminars in Mathematics, V. A. Steklov Mathematical Institute, Leningrad, vol. 8, Consultants Bureau, New York-London 1970, pp. 75–78. [REVIEW]Ann S. Ferebee - 1972 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 37 (3):605.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  30
    Riesz representation theorem, Borel measures and subsystems of second-order arithmetic.Xiaokang Yu - 1993 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 59 (1):65-78.
    Yu, X., Riesz representation theorem, Borel measures and subsystems of second-order arithmetic, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 59 65-78. Formalized concept of finite Borel measures is developed in the language of second-order arithmetic. Formalization of the Riesz representation theorem is proved to be equivalent to arithmetical comprehension. Codes of Borel sets of complete separable metric spaces are defined and proved to be meaningful in the subsystem ATR0. Arithmetical transfinite recursion is enough to prove the measurability (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  9.  76
    Arithmetic from Kant to Frege: Numbers, Pure Units, and the Limits of Conceptual Representation.Daniel Sutherland - 2008 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 63:135-164.
    There is evidence in Kant of the idea that concepts of particular numbers, such as the number 5, are derived from the representation of units, and in particular pure units, that is, units that are qualitatively indistinguishable. Frege, in contrast, rejects any attempt to derive concepts of number from the representation of units. In the Foundations of Arithmetic, he softens up his reader for his groundbreaking and unintuitive analysis of number by attacking alternative views, and he devotes the (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  10. Finger-based representation of mental arithmetic.Mauro Pesenti & Michael Andres - 2015 - In Roi Cohen Kadosh & Ann Dowker (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Numerical Cognition. Oxford University Press UK.
    Human beings are permanently required to process the world numerically and, consequently, to perform computations to adapt their behaviour and they have developed various calculation strategies, some of them based on specific manipulations of the fingers. In this chapter, we argue that the way we express physically numerical concepts by raising fingers while counting leads to embodied representations of numbers and calculation procedures in the adult brain. To illustrate this, we focus on number and finger interactions in the context of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Symbolic arithmetic knowledge without instruction.Camilla K. Gilmore, Shannon E. McCarthy & Elizabeth S. Spelke - unknown
    Symbolic arithmetic is fundamental to science, technology and economics, but its acquisition by children typically requires years of effort, instruction and drill1,2. When adults perform mental arithmetic, they activate nonsymbolic, approximate number representations3,4, and their performance suffers if this nonsymbolic system is impaired5. Nonsymbolic number representations also allow adults, children, and even infants to add or subtract pairs of dot arrays and to compare the resulting sum or difference to a third array, provided that only approximate accuracy is required6–10. Here (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  12.  25
    Arithmetic of divisibility in finite models.A. E. Wasilewska & M. Mostowski - 2004 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 50 (2):169.
    We prove that the finite-model version of arithmetic with the divisibility relation is undecidable . Additionally we prove FM-representability theorem for this class of finite models. This means that a relation R on natural numbers can be described correctly on each input on almost all finite divisibility models if and only if R is of degree ≤0′. We obtain these results by interpreting addition and multiplication on initial segments of finite models with divisibility only.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  13.  19
    Representations and the Foundations of Mathematics.Sam Sanders - 2022 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 63 (1):1-28.
    The representation of mathematical objects in terms of (more) basic ones is part and parcel of (the foundations of) mathematics. In the usual foundations of mathematics, namely, ZFC set theory, all mathematical objects are represented by sets, while ordinary, namely, non–set theoretic, mathematics is represented in the more parsimonious language of second-order arithmetic. This paper deals with the latter representation for the rather basic case of continuous functions on the reals and Baire space. We show that the logical (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  34
    The Role of Gesture in Supporting Mental Representations: The Case of Mental Abacus Arithmetic.Neon B. Brooks, David Barner, Michael Frank & Susan Goldin-Meadow - 2018 - Cognitive Science 42 (2):554-575.
    People frequently gesture when problem-solving, particularly on tasks that require spatial transformation. Gesture often facilitates task performance by interacting with internal mental representations, but how this process works is not well understood. We investigated this question by exploring the case of mental abacus, a technique in which users not only imagine moving beads on an abacus to compute sums, but also produce movements in gestures that accompany the calculations. Because the content of MA is transparent and readily manipulated, the task (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15.  34
    Evaluation of a Computer-Based Training Program for Enhancing Arithmetic Skills and Spatial Number Representation in Primary School Children.Larissa Rauscher, Juliane Kohn, Tanja Käser, Verena Mayer, Karin Kucian, Ursina McCaskey, Günter Esser & Michael von Aster - 2016 - Frontiers in Psychology 7.
  16. Cognitive Foundations of Human Number Representations and Mental Arithmetic.Oliver Lindemann & Martin H. Fischer - 2015 - In Roi Cohen Kadosh & Ann Dowker (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Numerical Cognition. Oxford University Press UK.
    The chapters in this section of the volume reveal the striking variety of human numerical cognition. The section comprises four chapters that focus on different aspects of the representation of numerical knowledge, as well as three chapters that examine the several cognitive processes involved in the manipulation of numbers during simple mental arithmetic. They show how chronometric analyses, in combination with clever experimental designs, can reveal the cognitive processes and representations underlying this impressive collection of cognitive skills. Our goal (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  13
    Geometry and arithmetic in the medieval traditions of Euclid’s Elements: a view from Book II.Leo Corry - 2013 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 67 (6):637-705.
    This article explores the changing relationships between geometric and arithmetic ideas in medieval Europe mathematics, as reflected via the propositions of Book II of Euclid’s Elements. Of particular interest is the way in which some medieval treatises organically incorporated into the body of arithmetic results that were formulated in Book II and originally conceived in a purely geometric context. Eventually, in the Campanus version of the Elements these results were reincorporated into the arithmetic books of the Euclidean treatise. Thus, while (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  18. Of arithmetic word problems.Denise Dellarosa Cummins - unknown
    Two experiments were conducted to investigate children’s interpretations of standard arithmetic word problems and the factors that influence their interpretations. In Experiment 1, children were required to solve a series of problems and then to draw and select pictures that represented the problems’ structures. Solution performance was found to vary systematically with the nature of the representations drawn and chosen. The crucial determinant of solution success was the interpretation a child assigned to certain phrases used in the problems. In Experiment (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  22
    Is Nonsymbolic Arithmetic Truly “Arithmetic”? Examining the Computational Capacity of the Approximate Number System in Young Children.Chen Cheng & Melissa M. Kibbe - 2023 - Cognitive Science 47 (6):e13299.
    Young children with limited knowledge of formal mathematics can intuitively perform basic arithmetic‐like operations over nonsymbolic, approximate representations of quantity. However, the algorithmic rules that guide such nonsymbolic operations are not entirely clear. We asked whether nonsymbolic arithmetic operations have a function‐like structure, like symbolic arithmetic. Children (n = 74 4‐ to ‐8‐year‐olds in Experiment 1; n = 52 7‐ to 8‐year‐olds in Experiment 2) first solved two nonsymbolic arithmetic problems. We then showed children two unequal sets of objects, and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Psychophysiological evidence for binding and unbinding arithmetic knowledge representations.Frank Rosler, Kerstin Jost & Niedeggen & Michael - 2006 - In Hubert D. Zimmer, Axel Mecklinger & Ulman Lindenberger (eds.), Handbook of Binding and Memory: Perspectives From Cognitive Neuroscience. Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  56
    Sentences undecidable in formalized arithmetic: an exposition of the theory of Kurt Gödel.Andrzej Mostowski - 1952 - Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press.
    The famous theory of undecidable sentences created by Kurt Godel in 1931 is presented as clearly and as rigorously as possible. Introductory explanations beginning with the necessary facts of arithmetic of integers and progressing to the theory of representability of arithmetical functions and relations in the system (S) prepare the reader for the systematic exposition of the theory of Godel which is taken up in the final chapter and the appendix.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  22.  12
    Numerical abstractness and elementary arithmetic.Jamie Id Campbell & Arron Ws Metcalfe - 2009 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32 (3-4):330 - 331.
    Like number representation, basic arithmetic seems to be a natural candidate for abstract instantiation in the brain. To investigate this, researchers have examined effects of numeral format on elementary arithmetic (e.g., 4+5 vs. four+five). Different numeral formats often recruit distinct processes for arithmetic, reinforcing the conclusion that number processing is not necessarily abstracted away from numeral format.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  27
    The Arithmetic of Emotion: Integration of Incidental and Integral Affect in Judgments and Decisions.Daniel Västfjäll, Paul Slovic, William J. Burns, Arvid Erlandsson, Lina Koppel, Erkin Asutay & Gustav Tinghög - 2016 - Frontiers in Psychology 7:184696.
    Research has demonstrated that two types of affect have an influence on judgment and decision making: incidental affect (affect unrelated to a judgment or decision such as a mood) and integral affect (affect that is part of the perceiver’s internal representation of the option or target under consideration). So far, these two lines of research have seldom crossed so that knowledge concerning their combined effects is largely missing. To fill this gap, the present review highlights differences and similarities between (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  24.  34
    Essai de représentation par des nombres réels d'une analyse infinite des notions individuelles dans une infinité de mondes possibles.Miguel Sánchez-Mazas - 1989 - Argumentation 3 (1):75-96.
    The aim of this study is to try to make use of real numbers for representing an infinite analysis of individual notions in an infinity of possible worlds.As an introduction to the subject, the author shows, firstly, the possibility of representing Boole's lattice of universal notions by an associate Boole's lattice of rational numbers.But, in opposition to the universal notions, definable by a finite number of predicates, an individual notion, cannot admits this sort of definition, because each state of an (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Arithmetic on a parallel computer: Perception versus logic. [REVIEW]James A. Anderson - 2003 - Brain and Mind 4 (2):169-188.
    This article discusses the properties of a controllable, flexible, hybrid parallel computing architecture that potentially merges pattern recognition and arithmetic. Humans perform integer arithmetic in a fundamentally different way than logic-based computers. Even though the human approach to arithmetic is both slow and inaccurate it can have substantial advantages when useful approximations ( intuition ) are more valuable than high precision. Such a computational strategy may be particularly useful when computers based on nanocomponents become feasible because it offers a way (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. Modeling ancient and modern arithmetic practices: Addition and multiplication with Arabic and Roman numerals.Dirk Schlimm & Hansjörg Neth - 2008 - In B. C. Love, K. McRae & V. M. Sloutsky (eds.), Proceedings of the 30th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society. Cognitive Science Society. pp. 2097--2102.
    To analyze the task of mental arithmetic with external representations in different number systems we model algorithms for addition and multiplication with Arabic and Roman numerals. This demonstrates that Roman numerals are not only informationally equivalent to Arabic ones but also computationally similar—a claim that is widely disputed. An analysis of our models' elementary processing steps reveals intricate tradeoffs between problem representation, algorithm, and interactive resources. Our simulations allow for a more nuanced view of the received wisdom on Roman (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  27.  38
    Disentangling the Mechanisms of Symbolic Number Processing in Adults’ Mathematics and Arithmetic Achievement.Josetxu Orrantia, David Muñez, Laura Matilla, Rosario Sanchez, Sara San Romualdo & Lieven Verschaffel - 2019 - Cognitive Science 43 (1).
    A growing body of research has shown that symbolic number processing relates to individual differences in mathematics. However, it remains unclear which mechanisms of symbolic number processing are crucial—accessing underlying magnitude representation of symbols (i.e., symbol‐magnitude associations), processing relative order of symbols (i.e., symbol‐symbol associations), or processing of symbols per se. To address this question, in this study adult participants performed a dots‐number word matching task—thought to be a measure of symbol‐magnitude associations (numerical magnitude processing)—a numeral‐ordering task that focuses (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  16
    Cognitive Foundations of Arithmetic: Evolution and Ontogenisis.Susan Carey - 2002 - Mind and Language 16 (1):37-55.
    Dehaene (this volume) articulates a naturalistic approach to the cognitive foundations of mathematics. Further, he argues that the ‘number line’ (analog magnitude) system of representation is the evolutionary and ontogenetic foundation of numerical concepts. Here I endorse Dehaene’s naturalistic stance and also his characterization of analog magnitude number representations. Although analog magnitude representations are part of the evolutionary foundations of numerical concepts, I argue that they are unlikely to be part of the ontogenetic foundations of the capacity to represent (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  29. Grounding Concepts: An Empirical Basis for Arithmetical Knowledge.Carrie Jenkins - 2008 - Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
    Carrie Jenkins presents a new account of arithmetical knowledge, which manages to respect three key intuitions: a priorism, mind-independence realism, and empiricism. Jenkins argues that arithmetic can be known through the examination of empirically grounded concepts, non-accidentally accurate representations of the mind-independent world.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  30. On Radical Enactivist Accounts of Arithmetical Cognition.Markus Pantsar - 2022 - Ergo: An Open Access Journal of Philosophy 9.
    Hutto and Myin have proposed an account of radically enactive (or embodied) cognition (REC) as an explanation of cognitive phenomena, one that does not include mental representations or mental content in basic minds. Recently, Zahidi and Myin have presented an account of arithmetical cognition that is consistent with the REC view. In this paper, I first evaluate the feasibility of that account by focusing on the evolutionarily developed proto-arithmetical abilities and whether empirical data on them support the radical (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31.  28
    Automorphisms of models of arithmetic: a unified view.Ali Enayat - 2007 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 145 (1):16-36.
    We develop the method of iterated ultrapower representation to provide a unified and perspicuous approach for building automorphisms of countable recursively saturated models of Peano arithmetic . In particular, we use this method to prove Theorem A below, which confirms a long-standing conjecture of James Schmerl.Theorem AIf is a countable recursively saturated model of in which is a strong cut, then for any there is an automorphism j of such that the fixed point set of j is isomorphic to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  32. Representation and Reality by Language: How to make a home quantum computer?Vasil Penchev - 2020 - Philosophy of Science eJournal (Elsevier: SSRN) 13 (34):1-14.
    A set theory model of reality, representation and language based on the relation of completeness and incompleteness is explored. The problem of completeness of mathematics is linked to its counterpart in quantum mechanics. That model includes two Peano arithmetics or Turing machines independent of each other. The complex Hilbert space underlying quantum mechanics as the base of its mathematical formalism is interpreted as a generalization of Peano arithmetic: It is a doubled infinite set of doubled Peano arithmetics having a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  29
    Cognitive Foundations of Arithmetic: Evolution and Ontogenisis.Susan Carey - 2002 - Mind and Language 16 (1):37-55.
    Dehaene (this volume) articulates a naturalistic approach to the cognitive foundations of mathematics. Further, he argues that the ‘number line’ (analog magnitude) system of representation is the evolutionary and ontogenetic foundation of numerical concepts. Here I endorse Dehaene’s naturalistic stance and also his characterization of analog magnitude number representations. Although analog magnitude representations are part of the evolutionary foundations of numerical concepts, I argue that they are unlikely to be part of the ontogenetic foundations of the capacity to represent (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  34.  17
    The Power of 2: How an Apparently Irregular Numeration System Facilitates Mental Arithmetic.Andrea Bender & Sieghard Beller - 2016 - Cognitive Science 40 (6):n/a-n/a.
    Mangarevan traditionally contained two numeration systems: a general one, which was highly regular, decimal, and extraordinarily extensive; and a specific one, which was restricted to specific objects, based on diverging counting units, and interspersed with binary steps. While most of these characteristics are shared by numeration systems in related languages in Oceania, the binary steps are unique. To account for these characteristics, this article draws on—and tries to integrate—insights from anthropology, archeology, linguistics, psychology, and cognitive science more generally. The analysis (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  35. Knowledge of arithmetic.C. S. Jenkins - 2005 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 56 (4):727-747.
    The goal of the research programme I describe in this article is a realist epistemology for arithmetic which respects arithmetic's special epistemic status (the status usually described as a prioricity) yet accommodates naturalistic concerns by remaining fundamentally empiricist. I argue that the central claims which would allow us to develop such an epistemology are (i) that arithmetical truths are known through an examination of our arithmetical concepts; (ii) that (at least our basic) arithmetical concepts are accurate mental (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  36.  19
    Understanding and Using Principles of Arithmetic: Operations Involving Negative Numbers.Richard W. Prather & Martha W. Alibali - 2008 - Cognitive Science 32 (2):445-457.
    Previous work has investigated adults' knowledge of principles for arithmetic with positive numbers (Dixon, Deets, & Bangert, 2001). The current study extends this past work to address adults' knowledge of principles of arithmetic with a negative number, and also investigates links between knowledge of principles and problem representation. Participants (N = 44) completed two tasks. In the Evaluation task, participants rated how well sets of equations were solved. Some sets violated principles of arithmetic and others did not. Participants rated (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37. WEIHRAUCH, K. and KREITZ, C., Representations of the real numbers and of the open subsets of the set of real numbers WILKIE, AJ and PARIS, JB, On the scheme of induction for bounded arithmetic formulas. [REVIEW]Las Kirby & R. Diaconescu - 1987 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 35:303.
  38. Analogue Magnitude Representations: A Philosophical Introduction.Jacob Beck - 2015 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 66 (4):829-855.
    Empirical discussions of mental representation appeal to a wide variety of representational kinds. Some of these kinds, such as the sentential representations underlying language use and the pictorial representations of visual imagery, are thoroughly familiar to philosophers. Others have received almost no philosophical attention at all. Included in this latter category are analogue magnitude representations, which enable a wide range of organisms to primitively represent spatial, temporal, numerical, and related magnitudes. This article aims to introduce analogue magnitude representations to (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  39.  29
    Object individuation by iconic content: How is numerosity represented in iconic representation?Athanasios Raftopoulos - 2020 - Rivista Internazionale di Filosofia e Psicologia 11 (1):42-70.
    : Fodor argues that perceptual representations are a subset of iconic representations, which are distinguished from symbolic/discursive representations. Iconic representations are nonconceptual and they do not support the abilities afforded by concepts. Iconic representations, for example, cannot support object individuation. If someone thinks that perception or some of its parts has imagistic NCC, they face the following dilemma. Either they will have to accept that this NCC does not allow for object individuation, but it represents instead conglomerations of properties and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  47
    Geometric Representations for Minimalist Grammars.Peter Beim Graben & Sabrina Gerth - 2012 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 21 (4):393-432.
    We reformulate minimalist grammars as partial functions on term algebras for strings and trees. Using filler/role bindings and tensor product representations, we construct homomorphisms for these data structures into geometric vector spaces. We prove that the structure-building functions as well as simple processors for minimalist languages can be realized by piecewise linear operators in representation space. We also propose harmony, i.e. the distance of an intermediate processing step from the final well-formed state in representation space, as a measure (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41. A Mathematical Model of Quantum Computer by Both Arithmetic and Set Theory.Vasil Penchev - 2020 - Information Theory and Research eJournal 1 (15):1-13.
    A practical viewpoint links reality, representation, and language to calculation by the concept of Turing (1936) machine being the mathematical model of our computers. After the Gödel incompleteness theorems (1931) or the insolvability of the so-called halting problem (Turing 1936; Church 1936) as to a classical machine of Turing, one of the simplest hypotheses is completeness to be suggested for two ones. That is consistent with the provability of completeness by means of two independent Peano arithmetics discussed in Section (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  25
    Ordinal operations on graph representations of sets.Laurence Kirby - 2013 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 59 (1-2):19-26.
    Any set x is uniquely specified by the graph of the membership relation on the set obtained by adjoining x to the transitive closure of x. Thus any operation on sets can be looked at as an operation on these graphs. We look at the operations of ordinal arithmetic of sets in this light. This turns out to be simplest for a modified ordinal arithmetic based on the Zermelo ordinals, instead of the usual von Neumann ordinals. In this arithmetic, addition (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  43.  14
    Arithmetic of Dedekind cuts of ordered Abelian groups.Antongiulio Fornasiero & Marcello Mamino - 2008 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 156 (2):210-244.
    We study Dedekind cuts on ordered Abelian groups. We introduce a monoid structure on them, and we characterise, via a suitable representation theorem, the universal part of the theory of such structures.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  18
    Kolmogorov complexity and set theoretical representations of integers.Marie Ferbus-Zanda & Serge Grigorieff - 2006 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 52 (4):375-403.
    We reconsider some classical natural semantics of integers in the perspective of Kolmogorov complexity. To each such semantics one can attach a simple representation of integers that we suitably effectivize in order to develop an associated Kolmogorov theory. Such effectivizations are particular instances of a general notion of “self-enumerated system” that we introduce in this paper. Our main result asserts that, with such effectivizations, Kolmogorov theory allows to quantitatively distinguish the underlying semantics. We characterize the families obtained by such (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45.  6
    Uniform proofs of ACC representations.Sam Buss - 2017 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 56 (5-6):639-669.
    We give a uniform proof of the theorems of Yao and Beigel–Tarui representing ACC predicates as constant depth circuits with MODm\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$\hbox {MOD}_{m}$$\end{document} gates and a symmetric gate. The proof is based on a relativized, generalized form of Toda’s theorem expressed in terms of closure properties of formulas under bounded universal, existential and modular counting quantifiers. This allows the main proofs to be expressed in terms of formula classes instead of Boolean circuits. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46. Leibniz on Binary: The Invention of Computer Arithmetic.Lloyd Strickland & Harry R. Lewis - 2022 - Cambridge, MA, USA: The MIT Press.
    The first collection of Leibniz's key writings on the binary system, newly translated, with many previously unpublished in any language. -/- The polymath Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646–1716) is known for his independent invention of the calculus in 1675. Another major—although less studied—mathematical contribution by Leibniz is his invention of binary arithmetic, the representational basis for today's digital computing. This book offers the first collection of Leibniz's most important writings on the binary system, all newly translated by the authors with many (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47.  49
    Critical Decisions under Uncertainty: Representation and Structure.Benjamin Kuipers, Alan J. Moskowitz & Jerome P. Kassirer - 1988 - Cognitive Science 12 (2):177-210.
    How do people make difficult decisions in situations involving substantial risk and uncertainty? In this study, we presented a difficult medical decision to three expert physicians in a combined “thinking aloud” and “cross examination” experiment. Verbatim transcripts were analyzed using script analysis to observe the process of constructing and making the decision, and using referring phrase analysis to determine the representation of knowledge of likelihoods. These analyses are compared with a formal decision analysis of the same problem to highlight (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  48.  26
    Complete, Recursively Enumerable Relations in Arithmetic.Giovanna D'Agostino & Mario Magnago - 1995 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 41 (1):65-72.
    Using only propositional connectives and the provability predicate of a Σ1-sound theory T containing Peano Arithmetic we define recursively enumerable relations that are complete for specific natural classes of relations, as the class of all r. e. relations, and the class of all strict partial orders. We apply these results to give representations of these classes in T by means of formulas.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49. Logicism, Interpretability, and Knowledge of Arithmetic.Sean Walsh - 2014 - Review of Symbolic Logic 7 (1):84-119.
    A crucial part of the contemporary interest in logicism in the philosophy of mathematics resides in its idea that arithmetical knowledge may be based on logical knowledge. Here an implementation of this idea is considered that holds that knowledge of arithmetical principles may be based on two things: (i) knowledge of logical principles and (ii) knowledge that the arithmetical principles are representable in the logical principles. The notions of representation considered here are related to theory-based and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  50.  14
    “The Etherealization of Common Sense?” Arithmetical and Algebraic Modes of Intelligibility in Late Victorian Mathematics of Measurement.Daniel Jon Mitchell - 2019 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 73 (2):125-180.
    The late nineteenth century gradually witnessed a liberalization of the kinds of mathematical object and forms of mathematical reasoning permissible in physical argumentation. The construction of theories of units illustrates the slow and difficult spread of new “algebraic” modes of mathematical intelligibility, developed by leading mathematicians from the 1830s onwards, into elementary arithmetical pedagogy, experimental physics, and fields of physical practice like telegraphic engineering. A watershed event in this process was a clash that took place during 1878 between J. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 989