Results for 'Posthumous interests'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  36
    Posthumous Interests: Legal and Ethical Perspectives.Daniel Sperling - 2008 - Cambridge University Press.
    Daniel Sperling discusses the legal status of posthumous interests and their possible defeat by actions performed following the death of a person. The author first explores the following questions: Do the dead have interests and/or rights, the defeat of which may constitute harm? What does posthumous harm consist of and when does it occur, if at all? This is followed by a more detailed analysis of three categories of posthumous interests arising in the medico-legal (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  2. Posthumous interests and posthumous respect.Ernest Partridge - 1981 - Ethics 91 (2):243-264.
  3.  48
    Posthumous Interests: Legal and Ethical Perspectives. By Daniel Sperling.James Stacey Taylor - 2010 - Metaphilosophy 41 (5):727-731.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  52
    Daniel sperling, posthumous interests: Legal and ethical perspectives. [REVIEW]T. M. Wilkinson - 2009 - Journal of Value Inquiry 43 (4):531-535.
  5.  37
    Posthumous Organ Retention and Use in Ghana: Regulating Individual, Familial and Societal Interests.Divine Ndonbi Banyubala - 2016 - Health Care Analysis 24 (4):301-320.
    The question of whether individuals retain interests or can be harmed after death is highly contentious, particularly within the context of deceased organ retrieval, retention and use. This paper argues that posthumous interests and/or harms can and do exist in the Konkomba traditional setting through the concept of ancestorship, a reputational concept of immense cultural and existential significance in this setting. I adopt Joel Feinberg’s account of harms as a setback to interests. The paper argues that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6.  19
    Parent-initiated posthumous-assisted reproduction revisited in light of the interest in genetic origins.Ya'arit Bokek-Cohen & Vardit Ravitsky - 2023 - Journal of Medical Ethics 49 (5):357-360.
    A rich literature in bioethics argues against the use of anonymous gamete donation in the name of the ‘interest in knowing one’s genetic origins’. This interest stems from medical as well as psychosocial and identity reasons. The term ‘genealogical bewilderment’ has been coined to express the predicament of those deprived of access to information about their origins. Another rich body of literature in bioethics discusses arguments for and against posthumous-assisted reproduction (PAR), with a recent focus on PAR that is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  30
    Parents’ posthumous use of daughter’s ovarian tissue: Ethical dimensions.Aliya O. Affdal & Vardit Ravitsky - 2018 - Bioethics 33 (1):82-90.
    In recent years, progress in cancer treatment has greatly increased the chances of recovery. Yet, treatment may have irreversible effects on patients’ fertility. In order to protect future fertility, preservation of ovarian tissue may be offered today even to very young girls, involving a surgical procedure that may be performed by minimally invasive laparoscopy, under general anesthesia. However, in the tragic event of a girl’s death, questions may arise regarding the possible use of the preserved ovarian tissue by her parents. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  8.  8
    Posthumous Satisfactions and the Individual Welfare.Alan E. Fuchs - 1991 - Journal of Philosophical Research 16:345-351.
    Can events that take place after an individual’s death affect that person’s weIl-being? Aristotle apparently thought that they could, but Mark Overvold disagrees. Like other contemporary moral theorists, Overvold analyzes the notion of a person’s utility or welfare in terms of the fulfillment of the individual’s desires, but he adds the important qualification that the desites must be for states-of-affairs in which the agent is an essential constituent. The clear implication of such a view is that our welfare cannot be (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  9.  55
    Posthumous Satisfactions and the Individual Welfare.Alan E. Fuchs - 1991 - Journal of Philosophical Research 16:345-351.
    Can events that take place after an individual’s death affect that person’s weIl-being? Aristotle apparently thought that they could, but Mark Overvold disagrees. Like other contemporary moral theorists, Overvold analyzes the notion of a person’s utility or welfare in terms of the fulfillment of the individual’s desires, but he adds the important qualification that the desites must be for states-of-affairs in which the agent is an essential constituent. The clear implication of such a view is that our welfare cannot be (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10.  9
    Posthumous autonomy: Agency and consent in body donation.Tom Farsides & Claire F. Smith - forthcoming - Philosophical Psychology.
    Six people were interviewed about the possibility of becoming posthumous body donors. Interview transcripts were analyzed using interpretative phenomenological analysis. Individual-level analysis suggested a common interest in Personhood Concerns and a common commitment to Enlightenment Values. Investigations of these possible themes across participants resulted in identification of two sample-level themes, each with two subthemes: Autonomy, with subthemes of agency and consent, and Rationality, with subthemes of knowledge/epistemology and materialism/ontology. This paper concentrates on the former. Consent for posthumous body (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  3
    Posthumous art, law and the art market: the afterlife of art.Sharon Hecker & Peter J. Karol (eds.) - 2022 - New York: Routledge.
    This book takes an interdisciplinary, transnational and cross-cultural approach to reflect on, critically examine, and challenge the surprisingly robust practice of making art after death in an artist's name, through the lenses of scholars from the fields of art history, economics and law, as well as practicing artists. Works of art conceived as multiples, such as sculptures, etchings, prints, photographs and conceptual art, can be - and often are - remade from original models and plans long after the artist has (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  68
    Against posthumous rights.Stephen Winter - 2010 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 27 (2):186-199.
    A number of prominent nonconsequentialists support the thesis that we can wrong the dead by violating their moral claims. In contrast, this study suggests that the arguments offered by Thomson, Scanlon, Dworkin, Feinberg and others do not warrant posthumous rights because having claim-grounding interests requires an entity to have the capacity to experience significance. If dead people don't have this capacity, there is no reason to attribute claims to them. Raising doubts about prominent hypothetical examples of ‘no-effect injury’, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  13.  9
    Posthumous Satisfactions and the Individual Welfare.Alan E. Fuchs - 1991 - Journal of Philosophical Research 16:345-351.
    Can events that take place after an individual’s death affect that person’s weIl-being? Aristotle apparently thought that they could, but Mark Overvold disagrees. Like other contemporary moral theorists, Overvold analyzes the notion of a person’s utility or welfare in terms of the fulfillment of the individual’s desires, but he adds the important qualification that the desites must be for states-of-affairs in which the agent is an essential constituent. The clear implication of such a view is that our welfare cannot be (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  17
    Against Posthumous Rights.Stephen Winter - 2010 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 27 (2):186-199.
    abstract A number of prominent nonconsequentialists support the thesis that we can wrong the dead by violating their moral claims. In contrast, this study suggests that the arguments offered by Thomson, Scanlon, Dworkin, Feinberg and others do not warrant posthumous rights because having claim‐grounding interests requires an entity to have the capacity to experience significance. If dead people don't have this capacity, there is no reason to attribute claims to them. Raising doubts about prominent hypothetical examples of ‘no‐effect (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  15.  82
    Prenatal and Posthumous Non-Existence: A Reply to Johansson.John Martin Fischer & Anthony L. Brueckner - 2014 - The Journal of Ethics 18 (1):1-9.
    We have argued that it is rational to have asymmetric attitudes toward prenatal and posthumous non-existence insofar as this asymmetry is a special case of a more general (and arguably rational) asymmetry in our attitudes toward past and future pleasures. Here we respond to an interesting critique of our view by Jens Johansson. We contend that his critique involves a crucial and illicit switch in temporal perspectives in the process of considering modal claims (sending us to other possible worlds).
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  16. Welfare and Posthumous Harm.Douglas W. Portmore - manuscript
    WHEN ONE ASSUMES, as I will, that death marks the irrevocable end to one’s existence, it is difficult to make sense of the idea that a person could be harmed or benefited by events that take place after her death. How could a posthumous event either enhance or diminish the welfare of the deceased, who no longer exists? Yet we find that many people have a prudential (i.e., self-interested) concern for what’s going to happen after their deaths.1 People are, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  21
    The Posthumous Life of Plato. [REVIEW]S. L. - 1979 - Review of Metaphysics 33 (1):193-195.
    Novotný is the Czech philologist who between 1915 and 1961 translated the entire corpus platonicum into Czech and who in 1948-49 wrote a "systematic study" in three volumes on Plato’s life, writings and philosophy. Its fourth volume on the influence of Plato upon subsequent eras appeared in 1964 and is now translated into English. The Posthumous Life of Plato can be best, although somewhat irreverently, described as a successful "Everything You Always Wanted to Know About Plato But Were Afraid (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  69
    A puzzle about posthumous predication.David-Hillel Ruben - 1988 - Philosophical Review 97 (2):211-236.
  19.  26
    Taylor on posthumous organ procurement.Walter Glannon - 2014 - Journal of Medical Ethics 40 (9):637-638.
    In defending what he calls ‘full-blooded Epicureanism’, James Stacey Taylor argues that the dead cannot be harmed or wronged.1 This has implications for a range of bioethical issues pertaining to death, including posthumous organ procurement. Taylor claims that respecting the autonomy of persons requires that their desires regarding the treatment of their postmortem bodies be given due consideration while these persons are alive. It is not obvious what this means in practical terms, though Taylor says that respect for autonomy (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  29
    Posthumous Writings. [REVIEW]Eike-Henner W. Kluge - 1982 - Philosophical Review 91 (1):115-118.
  21.  3
    Philosophy & Science: Wittgenstein Solves (Posthumously) the Species Problem.Massimo Pigliucci - 2005 - Philosophy Now 50:51-51.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  25
    Philosophy & Science: Wittgenstein Solves (Posthumously) the Species Problem.Massimo Pigliucci - 2005 - Philosophy Now 50:51-51.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  71
    Agnosticism. A Posthumous Essay.William Maccall - 1893 - The Monist 4 (1):31-43.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  20
    Certains naissent de façon posthume : la survie d'Henri Lefebvre.Stuart Elden - 2004 - Actuel Marx 36 (2):181-198.
    This article discusses the French reception of Lefebvre since his death in 1991. It initially discusses two books that he had worked on shortly before, but which appeared post-humously. The main focus of the piece is the programme of reeditions of Lefebvre’s writings that have appeared over the last five or so years. Treating these thematically the article provides an overview of Lefebvre’s career, showing what his contemporary relevance is, while pointing out important concerns that have been neglected in the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  3
    Certains naissent de façon posthume : la survie d'Henri Lefebvre.Stuart Elden - 2004 - Actuel Marx 36 (2):181-198.
    This article discusses the French reception of Lefebvre since his death in 1991. It initially discusses two books that he had worked on shortly before, but which appeared post-humously. The main focus of the piece is the programme of reeditions of Lefebvre’s writings that have appeared over the last five or so years. Treating these thematically the article provides an overview of Lefebvre’s career, showing what his contemporary relevance is, while pointing out important concerns that have been neglected in the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  44
    In search of the missing subject: narrative identity and posthumous wronging.Malin Masterton, Mats G. Hansson & Anna T. Höglund - 2010 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 41 (4):340-346.
    With the advanced methods of analysing old biological material, it is pressing to discuss what should be allowed to be done with human remains, particularly for well documented historical individuals. We argue that Queen Christina of Sweden, who challenged the traditional gender roles, has an interest in maintaining her privacy when there are continued attempts to reveal her ‘true’ gender. In the long-running philosophical debate on posthumous wronging, the fundamental question is: Who is wronged? Our aim is to find (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27.  49
    Response to Orr and Siegler--collective intentionality and procreative desires: the permissible view on consent to posthumous conception.M. Parker - 2004 - Journal of Medical Ethics 30 (4):389-392.
    Orr and Siegler have recently defended a restrictive view concerning posthumous sperm retrieval and conception, which would limit insemination to those cases where the deceased man has provided explicit consent for such a procedure. The restrictive view dominates current law and practice. A permissible view, in contrast, would allow insemination and conception in all but those cases where the posthumous procedure has been explicitly refused, or where there is no reasonable evidence that the deceased person desired children. I (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  28.  33
    Interest and Pregivenness in Husserl’s Genealogy of Logic.Tarjei Larsen - 2018 - Studia Phaenomenologica 18:49-70.
    The problem of accounting for the cognitively relevant relation between experience and thought is among the defining problems of modern philosophy. I suggest that addressing this problem provides an important motive for the “genealogy of logic” that Husserl outlines in his posthumously published Experience and Judgment. Arguing that the notions of “interest” and “pregivenness” are crucial to this approach, I seek to assess it through a detailed analysis of the use to which these notions are put in its most decisive (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  92
    Elective ventilation and interests.Julian Savulescu - 2013 - Journal of Medical Ethics 39 (3):129-129.
    This paper examines questions concerning elective ventilation, contextualised within English law and policy. It presents the general debate with reference both to the Exeter Protocol on elective ventilation, and the considerable developments in legal principle since the time that that protocol was declared to be unlawful. I distinguish different aspects of what might be labelled elective ventilation policies under the following four headings: ‘basic elective ventilation’; ‘epistemically complex elective ventilation’; ‘practically complex elective ventilation’; and ‘epistemically and practically complex elective ventilation’. (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  30.  39
    Queen Christina’s moral claim on the living: Justification of a tenacious moral intuition. [REVIEW]Malin Masterton, Gert Helgesson, Anna T. Höglund & Mats G. Hansson - 2007 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 10 (3):321-327.
    In the long-running debate on the interest of the dead, Joan C. Callahan argues against such interests and although Søren Holm for practical reasons is prepared to consider posthumous interests, he does not see any moral basis to support such interests. He argues that the whole question is irresolvable, yet finds privacy interests where Tutankhamen is concerned. Callahan argues that there can be reasons to hold on to the fiction that there are posthumous (...), namely if it is comforting for the living and instrumental for society. Thus, despite arguing against the position that the dead have any interests or for any moral basis for such interests, these “interests” are still taken into consideration in the end. This shows the unsatisfactory basis of their positions and indicates the tenacity of the moral intuition that the dead can have moral claims on the living. One example of a posthumous interest is the interest in one’s good name. Here we argue that it is an interest of moral significance. This implies that if individuals restrict use of their sample when they are still alive, those restrictions apply after their death. Further, it implies that one should be concerned with the reputation of historic persons. Research that defeats these interests calls for justification. We have suggested two lines of thinking along which such a discussion could go: investigating the truth-value of the good name and the relevance of bringing it into possible disrepute. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  31. David Enoch, Hebrew University of Jerusalem.is General Jurisprudence Interesting? - 2019 - In Toh Kevin, Plunkett David & Shapiro Scott (eds.), Dimensions of Normativity: New Essays on Metaethics and Jurisprudence. New York: Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Katharina Nieswandt, Concordia University. Authority & Interest in the Theory Of Right - 2019 - In Toh Kevin, Plunkett David & Shapiro Scott (eds.), Dimensions of Normativity: New Essays on Metaethics and Jurisprudence. New York: Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Pets are property.National Animal Interest Alliance - 2006 - In William Dudley (ed.), Animal rights. Detroit, [Mich.]: Thomson Gale.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  15
    From scientific exploitation to individual memorialization: Evolving attitudes towards research on Nazi victims’ bodies.Herwig Czech, Paul Weindling & Christiane Druml - 2021 - Bioethics 35 (6):508-517.
    During the Third Reich, state‐sponsored violence was linked to scientific research on many levels. Prisoners were used as involuntary subjects for medical experiments, and body parts from victims were used in anatomy and neuropathology on a massive scale. In many cases, such specimens remained in scientific collections and were used until long after the war. International bioethics, for a long time, had little to say on the issue. Since the late 1980s, with a renewed interest in the Holocaust and other (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  52
    Harming the dead, once again.Barbara Baum Levenbook - 1985 - Ethics 96 (1):162-164.
    This article responds to criticism by Don Marquis of my previous article, "Harming Someone after His Death." I argue that because the idea of surviving interests in not plausible, the harm-as-loss-theory is not on all fours with the harm-as-invasion-of-interests theory (especially when it comes to the harm of murder), and that the former is preferable.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36. Why Consent May Not Be Needed For Organ Procurement.James Delaney & David B. Hershenov - 2009 - American Journal of Bioethics 9 (8):3-10.
    Most people think it is wrong to take organs from the dead if the potential donors had previously expressed a wish not to donate. Yet people respond differently to a thought experiment that seems analogous in terms of moral relevance to taking organs without consent. We argue that our reaction to the thought experiment is most representative of our deepest moral convictions. We realize not everyone will be convinced by the conclusions we draw from our thought experiment. Therefore, we point (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  37. Bodyworlds and the ethics of using human remains: A preliminary discussion.Y. Michael Barilan - 2006 - Bioethics 20 (5):233–247.
    ABSTRACT Accepting the claim that the living have some moral duties with regard to dead bodies, this paper explores those duties and how they bear on the popular travelling exhibition Bodyworlds. I argue that the concept of informed consent presupposes substantial duties to the dead, namely duties that reckon with the meaning of the act in question. An attitude of respect and not regarding human remains as mere raw material are non‐alienable substantial duties. I found the ethos of Bodyworlds premature (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  38.  52
    The Power to Bequeath.Robert Lamb - 2014 - Law and Philosophy 33 (5):629-654.
    What should happen to a property holding after the death of its owner? One conventional answer to this question is that the owner can legitimately designate the beneficiary of a posthumous transfer through a written will. Yet this aspect of property ownership has received little in the way of philosophical attention or moral justification. Philosophers tend either to accept bequest as a conventional feature of property ownership or reject its legitimacy on egalitarian grounds. Dissatisfied by both approaches, this paper: (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  39.  42
    Last rights: The ethics of research on the dead.T. M. Wilkinson - 2002 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 19 (1):31–41.
    People often have strong views about being the subjects of research after their deaths. Should these views be given any weight and, if so, how much? How could we find out what the views are and what should we do if we cannot? This paper defends the idea of posthumous interests and discusses the significance of those interests for research ethics. It argues that we can be guided by a symmetry between the interests of living and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  40. Historic Injustices and the Moral Case for Cultural Repatriation.Karin Edvardsson Björnberg - 2015 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 18 (3):461-474.
    It is commonly argued that cultural objects ought to be returned to their place of origin in order to remedy injustices committed in the past. In this paper, it is shown that significant challenges attach to this way of arguing. Although there is considerable intuitive appeal in the idea that if somebody wrongs another person then she ought to compensate for that injustice, the principle is difficult to apply to wrongdoings committed many decades or centuries ago. It is not clear (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  41. Dignity- A Regenerative Idea.Deepa Kansra - 2016 - Indian Law Institute Law Review (ILI Law Review) 2 (Winter):202-203.
    AN ATTEMPT to understand the role of dignity in human rights is worthwhile and challenging. Popularly referred to as a “constitutional principle”, “moral precept”, or a “supreme virtue”, dignity has allowed legal systems to adopt evolutionary and impactful practices concerning the welfare of human beings. Defined also as the precursor and basis to the various human rights defined and adopted, dignity continues to facilitate the integration of diverse interests and stakeholders within the framework of human rights thought and practice. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  34
    Addressing organ shortage: An automatic organ procurement model as a proposal.Marina Morla-González, Clara Moya-Guillem, David Rodríguez-Arias, Íñigo de Miguel Beriain, Alberto Molina-Pérez & Iván Ortega-Deballon - 2021 - Clinical Ethics 16 (4):278-290.
    Organ shortage constitutes an unsolved problem for every country that offers transplantation as a therapeutic option. Besides the largely implemented donation model and the eventually implemented market model, a theorized automatic organ procurement model has raised a rich debate in the legal, medical and bioethical community, since it could show a higher potential to solve organ shortage. In this paper, we study the main arguments for and against this model. We show how, in the light of empirical data extracted from (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  97
    Harming someone after his death.Barbara Baum Levenbook - 1984 - Ethics 94 (3):407-419.
    I argue for the possibility of posthumous harm based on an account of the harm of murder. I start with the deep-seated intuition that when someone is murdered he (or she) is harmed (over and above the pain of injury or dying), and argue that Feinberg's account that assumes that harm is an invasion of an interest cannot plausibly accommodate this intuition. I propose a new account of the harm of murder: it is an irreversible loss of functions necessary (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  44.  44
    The Mirror-Image Argument: An Additional Reply to Johansson.John Martin Fischer & Anthony Brueckner - 2014 - The Journal of Ethics 18 (4):325-330.
    We have argued that it is rational to have asymmetric attitudes toward prenatal and posthumous non-existence insofar as this asymmetry is a special case of a more general asymmetry in our attitudes toward past and future pleasures. Here we respond to an interesting critique of our view by Jens Johansson. We contend that his critique involves an inappropriate conflation of the time from which the relevant asymmetry emerges and the time of the badness of death.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  45.  5
    Essays in the philosophy of art.R. G. Collingwood - 1964 - Bloomington,: Indiana University Press. Edited by Alan Donagan.
    Published posthumously in 1964, this volume contains a fantastic collection of essays by R. G. Collingwood on the subject of art and it's relationship with philosophy. Robin George Collingwood, FBA (1889 - 1943) was an English historian, philosopher, and archaeologist most famous for his philosophical works including "The Principles of Art" (1938) and the posthumously-published "The Idea of History" (1946). This fascinating volume will appeal to those with an interest in Collingwood's seminal work, and is not to be missed by (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  38
    Legal Causes and Council in Reproductive Health.Naira Roland Matevosyan - 2013 - International Journal for the Semiotics of Law - Revue Internationale de Sémiotique Juridique 26 (2):509-529.
    To study Judicial determinants of the ordered obstetrical and fertility interventions. Nature, corresponding laws, decisions upon the 37 expounded holdings at the Probate, Trial, District, Appellate, and Supreme Courts are studied in 92 published materials identified through the ACOG, RCOG, SOCG portals, and Legal Scholarship Repository. Hearings are held in the US (83.8 %), Canada (10.8 %) and U.K (5.4 %). Of all the hearings reviewed, 27 % concern mentally impaired, 37.8 %-maternal incompetence, and 21.6 % cases are of criminal (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Metaphysics: An Unfinished Essay. [REVIEW]M. C. - 1957 - Review of Metaphysics 11 (2):347-348.
    A posthumous edition of Jordan's unrevised and unfinished draft of a metaphysics, with a complete bibliography of works by and about Jordan, and a preface outlining the course of his life and thought. For those who are unacquainted with Jordan's earlier writings this book is difficult to follow and to evaluate. It is extremely polemical and often dogmatic in tone; we are told that... "religion and science are the two forms of scepticism that have posed as the philosophy of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  28
    Harming the Dead.James Stacey Taylor - 2008 - Journal of Philosophical Research 33:185-202.
    It is widely accepted that a person can be harmed by events that occur after her death. The most influential account of how persons can suffer such posthumous harm has been provided by George Pitcher and Joel Feinberg. Yet, despite its influence (or perhaps because of it) the Feinberg-Pitcher account of posthumous harm has been subject to several well-known criticisms. Surprisingly, there has been no attempt to defend this account of posthumous harm against these criticisms, either by (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  49.  15
    Truth and Existence. [REVIEW]John King-Farlow - 1994 - Review of Metaphysics 48 (1):162-162.
    Written in 1948 and posthumously published in 1989, this transitional essay is not, as Arlette Elkaim-Sartre suggested in her brief introduction to it, centered on an existential ethics. Rather, it is an attempt to grapple with the question of truth in relation to the ontology of Being and Nothingness. In part, Sartre wrote this work in response to the appearance of the French translation of Heidegger's "The Essence of Truth." Truth is characterized as the "event" in which there is a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  34
    Tafsīr and Translation: Traditional Arabic Qurʾān Exegesis and the Latin Qurʾāns of Robert of Ketton and Mark of Toledo.Thomas E. Burman - 1998 - Speculum 73 (3):703-732.
    It was a strange posthumous fate that awaited the Englishman Robert of Ketton : he was to be both best known and most strenuously criticized for a work that he surely viewed as a sideline to his own interests and career. By trade Robert was a Latin translator of Arabic scientific and mathematical works, one of those remarkable twelfth-century men who, as his contemporary Petrus Alfonsi put it, were willing “to traverse distant provinces and withdraw into remote regions (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000