Results for 'Non-literal speech'

999 found
Order:
  1. Non literal speech acts and conversational maxims.Daniel Vanderveken - 1991 - In Ernest Lepore (ed.), John Searle and His Critics. Cambridge: Blackwell. pp. 371--384.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  2.  49
    Metonymy and Metaphor as Verbal Postulation: The Epistemic Status of Non-Literal Speech in Indian Philosophy.Malcolm Keating - 2017 - Journal of World Philosophies 2 (1):67-80.
    In this paper, I examine Kumārila Bha ṭṭ a's account of figurative language in Tantravārttika 1.4.11-17, arguing that, for him, both metonymy and metaphor crucially involve verbal postulation, a knowledge-conducive cognitive process which draws connections between concepts without appeal to speaker intention, but through compositional and contextual elements. It is with the help of this cognitive process that we can come to have knowledge of what is meant by a sentence in context. In addition, the paper explores the relationship between (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3. On the Possibility of Non-Literal Legislative Speech.Asgeirsson Hrafn - 2017 - In Capone Alessandro & Poggi Francesca (eds.), Pragmatics and Law: Theoretical and Practical Perspectives. Dordrecht: Springer. pp. 67–101.
    The existing literature on indeterminacy in the law focuses mostly on the use of vague terms in legislation – terms the use of which makes the content of the relevant utterance to some extent indeterminate. As I aim to show, however, not only is the content of a legislative utterance often indeterminate, it is often indeterminate what the content of such an utterance is. In the first two sections of the paper, I discuss in some detail the conditions for successful (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4. Non-literal Lies.Emanuel Viebahn - 2017 - Erkenntnis 82 (6):1367-1380.
    Many recent definitions of lying are based on the notion of what is said. This paper argues that says-based definitions of lying cannot account for lies involving non-literal speech, such as metaphor, hyperbole, loose use or irony. It proposes that lies should instead be defined in terms of assertion, where what is asserted need not coincide with what is said. And it points to possible implications this outcome might have for the ethics of lying.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  5. Bald-faced lies: how to make a move in a language game without making a move in a conversation.Jessica Keiser - 2016 - Philosophical Studies 173 (2):461-477.
    According to the naïve, pre-theoretic conception, lying seems to be characterized by the intent to deceive. However, certain kinds of bald-faced lies appear to be counterexamples to this view, and many philosophers have abandoned it as a result. I argue that this criticism of the naïve view is misplaced; bald-faced lies are not genuine instances of lying because they are not genuine instances of assertion. I present an additional consideration in favor of the naïve view, which is that abandoning it (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  6.  9
    Normativity and Variety of Speech Actions.Maciej Witek & Iwona Witczak-Plisiecka (eds.) - 2019 - Brill | Rodopi.
    Normativity and Variety of Speech Actions embraces papers focused on the performative dimension of language. While all texts in the volume recognize speech primarily as a type of action, the collection is indicative of the multifaceted nature of J.L. Austin’s original reflection, which invited many varied research programmes. The problems addressed in the volume are discussed with reference to data culled from natural conversation, mediated political discourse, law, and literary language, and include normativity, e.g. types of norms operative (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7. Rationality as the Normative Dimension of Speech Acts.Federica Berdini - 2012 - Phenomenology and Mind 2:200-207.
    The paper deals with Searle’s account of the normative dimension involved in the performance of speech acts. I will first critically assess the rule-based speech act theory behind Searle’s characterization of the normativity of language – arguing that this approach cannot explain what makes a certain illocutionary act the specific type of illocutionary act it is, both in literal and non-literal or indirect cases. As an alternative, I will endorse the inferentialist model of linguistic communication proposed (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  70
    Demystifying metaphor: a strategy for literal paraphrase.Megan Henricks Stotts - 2021 - Philosophical Studies 178 (1):113-132.
    There is a long philosophical tradition of skepticism about the possibility of adequate paraphrases for metaphorical utterances. And even among those who favor paraphrasability, there is a tendency to think that paraphrases of metaphorical utterances may themselves have to be non-literal. I argue that even the most evocative and open-ended metaphorical utterances can be literally and adequately paraphrased, once we recognize that they are actually indirect speech acts—specifically, indirect directives that command the hearer to engage in an open-ended (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9. Differential pragmatic abilities and autism spectrum disorders: The case of pragmatic determinants of literal content.Jessica de Villiers & Robert J. Stainton - unknown
    It has become something of a truism that people with Autism Spectrum Disorders (ASD) have difficulties with pragmatics. Granting this, however, it is important to keep in mind that there are numerous kinds of pragmatic ability. One very important divide lies between those pragmatic competences which pertain to non-literal contents – as in, for instance, metaphor, irony and Gricean conversational implicatures – and those which pertain to the literal contents of speech acts. It is against this backdrop (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  10.  21
    The Possibility of Transmission of Speech in the Qurʾān.Muhammed İsa Yüksek - 2019 - Cumhuriyet İlahiyat Dergisi 23 (1):273-290.
    In terms of classical tafsir literature, it is possible that the speeches made to a person or group in the Qurʾān carry messages for other individuals or groups. According to some approaches that emerged in the modern period, when the speech was made and to whom it was directed not only determine the meaning, but also limits it. This dilemma has to be based on the theoretical dimension. The most obvious example of the transition of the speech from (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  43
    Non-literalness and non-bona-fîde in language: An approach to formal and computational treatments of humor.Jonathan D. Raskin & Salvatore Attardo - 1994 - Pragmatics and Cognition 2 (1):31-69.
    The paper is devoted to the study of humor as an important pragmatic phenomenon bearing on cognition, and, more specifically, as a cooperative mode of non-bona-fide communication. Several computational models of humor are presented in increasing order of complexity and shown to reveal important cognitive structures in jokes. On the basis of these limited implementations, the concept of a full-fledged computational model for the understanding and generation of humor is introduced and discussed in various aspects. The model draws upon the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  12.  90
    Non-literalness and non-bona-fîde in language: An approach to formal and computational treatments of humor.Victor Raskin & Salvatore Attardo - 1994 - Pragmatics and Cognition 2 (1):31-69.
    The paper is devoted to the study of humor as an important pragmatic phenomenon bearing on cognition, and, more specifically, as a cooperative mode of non-bona-fide communication. Several computational models of humor are presented in increasing order of complexity and shown to reveal important cognitive structures in jokes. On the basis of these limited implementations, the concept of a full-fledged computational model for the understanding and generation of humor is introduced and discussed in various aspects. The model draws upon the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  13.  29
    Comprehending Non-literal Language: Effects of Aging and Bilingualism.Shamala Sundaray, Theodoros Marinis & Arpita Bose - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 9.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  34
    Perceptual adaptation to non-native speech.Ann R. Bradlow & Tessa Bent - 2008 - Cognition 106 (2):707-729.
  15.  4
    On the Understanding of Non-Literal Expressions.Marian Przełecki - 2010 - Studia Semiotyczne—English Supplement 27:5-14.
    The following remarks should be treated as a discussion of a semiotic claim posed in the quotation above. Kołakowski opted for this rather radical perspective to challenge semiotic views prevailing in the analytical philosophy of that day. No wonder that his intellectual opponents felt obliged to take a stand. I once tended to side with his opponents, which is one of the reasons why I would like to take the emerging opportunity and revisit Kołakowski’s argument. I won’t be discussing the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. Processing models for non-literal discourse.Francois Recanati - 1994 - In Roberto Casati, Barry Smith & Graham Whiteca (eds.), Philosophy and the Cognitive Sciences, Proceedings of the 16th International Wittgenstein Symposium. pp. 277-290.
  17.  51
    The Literal/Non-Literal Distinction in Indian Philosophy.Malcolm Keating - 2016 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Article lays out the conceptual space for Indian theorizing about literal and non-literal meaning by way of each of these three textual traditions. Since the article’s structure is topical rather than historical, a chronology of major figures is appended to help orient readers. The focus of the article is the period demarcated roughly from 200 CE to 1300 CE, often characterized as the Classical Period of Indian philosophy.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  34
    Technological Knowledge among Non-Literate Ethiopian Adults in Israel.Yarden Fanta-Vagenshtein & David Chen - 2009 - Knowledge, Technology & Policy 22 (4):287-302.
    Ethiopian Jewish immigrants in Israel are one of the most ancient communities in the world, one that has been detached from the known Jewish world for about 2,500 years. Throughout this very long period of isolation, the Ethiopian Jewish community maintained Jewish tradition and dreamed over the centuries to unite with the rest of the Jewish world and immigrate to the Jewish state—Israel. But this transition occurred within a short time from an agrarian society in Ethiopia (traditional culture) with an (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. "John Wesley's Non-Literal Literalism and Hermeneutics of Love".Rem B. Edwards - 2016 - Wesleyan Theological Journal 51 (2):26-40.
    A thorough examination of John Wesley’s writings will show that he was not a biblical literalist or infallibilist, despite his own occasional suggestions to the contrary. His most important principles for interpreting the Bible were: We should take its words literally only if doing so is not absurd, in which case we should “look for a looser meaning;” and “No Scripture can mean that God is not love, or that his mercy is not over all his works.” Eleven instances of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Ellipsis and non-sentential speech.Reinaldo Elugardo & Robert J. Stainton (eds.) - 2005 - Springer.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  16
    That's not what you said! Semantic constraints on literal speech.Sarah A. Fisher - forthcoming - Mind and Language.
    According to some philosophers, a sentence's semantics can fail to constitute a complete propositional content, imposing mere constraints on such a content. Recently, Daniel Harris has begun developing a formal constraint semantics. He claims that the semantic values of sentences constrain what speakers can literally say with them—and what hearers can know about what was said. However, that claim is undermined by his conception of semantics as the study of a psychological module. I argue instead that semantic constraints should be (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Understanding Minds and Understanding Communicated Meanings in Schizophrenia.Robyn Langdon, Martin Davies & Max Coltheart - 2002 - Mind and Language 17 (1‐2):68-104.
    The work reported in this paper investigated the putative functional dependence of pragmatic language skills on general mind‐reading capacity by testing theory‐of‐mind abilities and understanding of non‐literal speech in patients with schizophrenia and in healthy controls. Patients showed difficulties with inferring mental states on a false‐belief picture‐sequencing task and with understanding metaphors and irony on a story‐comprehension task. These difficulties were independent of low verbal IQ and a more generalised problem inhibiting prepotent information. Understanding of metaphors and understanding (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  23.  66
    Metaphors and Martinis: a response to Jessica Keiser.Andreas Stokke - 2017 - Philosophical Studies 174 (4):853-859.
    This note responds to criticism put forth by Jessica Keiser against a theory of lying as Stalnakerian assertion. According to this account, to lie is to say something one believes to be false and thereby propose that it become common ground. Keiser objects that this view wrongly counts particular kinds of non-literal speech as instances of lying. In particular, Keiser argues that the view invariably counts metaphors and certain uses of definite descriptions as lies. It is argued here (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  24.  13
    The Nature of the Literal/Non-literal Distinction.Martina Blečić - 2014 - Croatian Journal of Philosophy 14 (3):357-375.
    In this paper I would like to suggest that a cognitive approach to pragmatics does not lead necessarily to the impossibility of a distinction between literal and non-literal contents and interpretations. If my reading is correct, this approach is focused on the cognitive activities that take place in the minds of regular language users and not on models applied to ideal speaker-hearers. If we accept that, then we should also accept that the distinction between the literal and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  7
    Non-human speech in literature - (h.) schmalzgruber (ed.) Speaking animals in ancient literature. (Kalliope 20.) pp. 619, ills. Heidelberg: Universitätsverlag winter, 2020. Cased, €78. Isbn: 978-3-8253-4690-4. [REVIEW]Tua Korhonen - 2021 - The Classical Review 71 (1):9-12.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  3
    Non-human speech in literature schmalzgruber (h.) (ed.) Speaking Animals in Ancient Literature. (Kalliope 20.) pp. 619, ills. Heidelberg: Universitätsverlag winter, 2020. Cased, €78. Isbn: 978-3-8253-4690-4 – corrigendum. [REVIEW]Tua Korhonen - 2021 - The Classical Review 71 (2):597-597.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  51
    Learning Foreign Sounds in an Alien World: Videogame Training Improves Non-Native Speech Categorization.Sung-joo Lim & Lori L. Holt - 2011 - Cognitive Science 35 (7):1390-1405.
    Although speech categories are defined by multiple acoustic dimensions, some are perceptually weighted more than others and there are residual effects of native-language weightings in non-native speech perception. Recent research on nonlinguistic sound category learning suggests that the distribution characteristics of experienced sounds influence perceptual cue weights: Increasing variability across a dimension leads listeners to rely upon it less in subsequent category learning (Holt & Lotto, 2006). The present experiment investigated the implications of this among native Japanese learning (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  28. Meaning and force: The pragmatics of performative utterances.François Récanati - 1987 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Professor Recanati's book is a major new contribution to the philosophy of language. Its point of departure is a refutation of two views central to the work of speech-act theorists such as Austin & Searle: that speech acts are essentially conventional, & that the force of an utterance can be made fully explicit at the level of sentence-meaning & is in principle a matter of linguistic decoding. The author argues that no utterance can be fully understood simply in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  29. The Lying-Misleading Distinction: A Commitment-Based Approach.Emanuel Viebahn - 2021 - Journal of Philosophy 118 (6):289-319.
    The distinction between lying and mere misleading is commonly tied to the distinction between saying and conversationally implicating. Many definitions of lying are based on the idea that liars say something they believe to be false, while misleaders put forward a believed-false conversational implicature. The aim of this paper is to motivate, spell out, and defend an alternative approach, on which lying and misleading differ in terms of commitment: liars, but not misleaders, commit themselves to something they believe to be (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  30.  10
    Motor activation in literal and non-literal sentences: does time matter?Cristina Cacciari & Francesca Pesciarelli - 2013 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 7.
  31.  11
    Emblem Gestures Improve Perception and Evaluation of Non-native Speech.Kiana Billot-Vasquez, Zhongwen Lian, Yukari Hirata & Spencer D. Kelly - 2020 - Frontiers in Psychology 11.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32.  26
    Metaphoric Measure of Meaning - the Problem of Non–Literal Use of Language in Science Reconsidered.Zdravko Radman - 1991 - Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 33:153-170.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  20
    Metaphoric Measure of Meaning - the Problem of Non–Literal Use of Language in Science Reconsidered.Zdravko Radman - 1991 - Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 33:153-170.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  14
    Metaphoric Measure of Meaning - the Problem of Non–Literal Use of Language in Science Reconsidered.Zdravko Radman - 1991 - Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 33:153-170.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Unfamiliar Voices: Harmonizing the Non-Socratic Speeches and Plato's Psychology.Jeremy Reid - 2017 - In Pierre Destrée & Zina Giannopoulou (eds.), Plato's Symposium: A Critical Guide. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. pp. 28–47.
    Commentators have often been puzzled by the structure of the Symposium; in particular, it is unclear what the relationship is between Socrates’ speech and that of the other symposiasts. This chapter seeks to make a contribution to that debate by highlighting parallels between the first four speeches of the Symposium and the goals of the early education in the Republic. In both dialogues, I contend, we see Plato concerned with educating people through (a) activating and cultivating spirited motivations, (b) (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  20
    Rethinking the Neural Basis of Prosody and Non-literal Language: Spared Pragmatics and Cognitive Compensation in a Bilingual With Extensive Right-Hemisphere Damage.Noelia Calvo, Sofía Abrevaya, Macarena Martínez Cuitiño, Brenda Steeb, Dolores Zamora, Lucas Sedeño, Agustín Ibáñez & Adolfo M. García - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 10.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  64
    Could knowledge-talk be largely non-literal?Julianne Chung - 2018 - Episteme 15 (4):383-411.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  11
    Bilinguals' Plausibility Judgments for Phrases with a Literal vs. Non-literal Meaning: The Influence of Language Brokering Experience.Belem G. López, Jyotsna Vaid, Sümeyra Tosun & Chaitra Rao - 2017 - Frontiers in Psychology 8.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39. Showing, telling and seeing.Elisabeth Camp - 2007 - The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 3 (1):1-24.
    Theorists often associate certain “poetic” qualities with metaphor – most especially, producing an open-ended, holistic perspective which is evocative, imagistic and affectively-laden. I argue that, on the one hand, non-cognitivists are wrong to claim that metaphors only produce such perspectives: like ordinary literal speech, they also serve to undertake claims and other speech acts with propositional content. On the other hand, contextualists are wrong to assimilate metaphor to literal loose talk: metaphors depend on using one thing (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  40.  19
    Alexithymic traits predict the speed of classifying non-literal statements using nonverbal cues.Lorna S. Jakobson & Pauline M. Pearson - forthcoming - Tandf: Cognition and Emotion:1-7.
  41.  4
    Alexithymic traits predict the speed of classifying non-literal statements using nonverbal cues.Lorna S. Jakobson & Pauline M. Pearson - 2021 - Cognition and Emotion 35 (3):569-575.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  34
    Speech in non-ideal conditions: On silence and being silenced.Alessandra Tanesini - 2023 - In Laura Caponetto & Paolo Labinaz (eds.), Sbisà on Speech as Action. Palgrave-Macmillan. pp. 2147483647-2147483647.
    In this chapter I show that idealizing assumptions can obscure conversational dynamics because they neglect power differentials that are crucial enablers of the successful performance of some speech acts (see, Sbisà, 2020). I examine how silencing is promoted by conversational norms that would defeasibly entitle linguistic agents to presume that silence indicates acceptance. I focus on Goldberg’s (2020) discussion of these phenomena. Goldberg argues in support of a norm of no silent rejections claiming that silencing is partly the result (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  8
    Subjective ratings of masker disturbance during the perception of native and non-native speech.Lisa Kilman - 2016 - Frontiers in Psychology 7.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Framing the Ethical Boundaries of Humor.David Poplar - 2022 - The Philosophy of Humor Yearbook 3 (1):153-178.
    Humor is unlike other forms of communication because its content is not meant literally. Like acts of play, humor is not intended to be taken at face value. As a consequence, the assumptions and rules that govern normal conversation do not apply. Humor therefore depends upon both the speaker and the audience fully understanding that what was communicated should be treated in this unique way. The play frame refers to this shared understanding about the nature of the communication. Analyzing whether (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45. The Argument from Accidental Truth against Deflationism.Masaharu Mizumoto - forthcoming - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy.
    In this paper, we present what we call the argument from accidental truth, according to which some instances of deflationist schemata, even those carefully reformulated and adjusted by Field and Horwich to accommodate the truth of utterances, are falsified due to accidental truths. Since the folk concept of truth allows for accidental truths, the deflationary theory of truth will face a serious problem. In particular, it follows that the deflationist schema fails to capture the proper extension of truth by precluding (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  9
    Being ambivalent by exploiting indeterminacy in the explicit import of an utterance.Agnieszka Piskorska - 2021 - Pragmatics and Cognition 28 (2):376-393.
    In line with recent interest in weak and often not fully determinate effects of communication permeating relevance-theoretic research, I contribute a discussion on two possible sources of speaker-intended indeterminacy within explicit import of an utterance: one residing in an intentionally underspecified location of an ad hoc concept between literal or non-literal (e.g. metaphorical or hyperbolic) interpretation, and the other lying in the higher-level explicature of an utterance, and being related to propositional attitude (e.g. pretence, reporting, dissociation) or (...)-act description (e.g. complementing, reproaching). In both cases, the speaker leaves a certain amount of indeterminacy concerning the degree of her commitment to the content communicated, by not indicating where precisely the concept or the attitude is to be located on the literalness-metaphor continuum or on the continuum of various propositional attitudes/speech-act descriptions, respectively. Using a number of illustrative examples drawn from television discourse, I try to show that this kind of intended indeterminacy gives rise to communicative effects of a non-propositional kind. Additionally, the analyses presented here support the deflationary view of figurative uses of language, on which they form continua with non-figurative utterances. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  74
    Inner Speech Generation in a Video Game Non-Player Character: From Explanation to Self?Raúl Arrabales - 2012 - International Journal of Machine Consciousness 4 (2):367-381.
    The use of human language is a hallmark of human consciousness, even when it is not used publicly. Inner speech is the way humans consciously communicate with themselves and arguably a key factor contributing to the formation of more self-aware selves. From the perspective of cognitive science and artificial cognitive architectures, inner speech can be also seen as a meta-management system that modulates some cognitive processes of the subject. In this paper, we describe a preliminary version of a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48.  36
    Revisiting pragmatic abilities in autism spectrum disorders: A follow-up study with controls.Jessica de Villiers, Brooke Myers & Robert J. Stainton - 2013 - Pragmatics and Cognition 21 (2):253-269.
    In a 2007 paper, we argued that speakers with Autism Spectrum Disorders exhibit pragmatic abilities which are surprising given the usual understanding of communication in that group. That is, it is commonly reported that people diagnosed with an ASD have trouble with metaphor, irony, conversational implicature and other non-literal language. This is not a matter of trouble with knowledge and application of rules of grammar. The difficulties lie, rather, in successful communicative interaction. Though we did find pragmatic errors within (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  49.  37
    Revisiting pragmatic abilities in autism spectrum disorders.Jessica de Villiers, Brooke Myers & Robert J. Stainton - 2013 - Pragmatics and Cognition 21 (2):253-269.
    In a 2007 paper, we argued that speakers with Autism Spectrum Disorders exhibit pragmatic abilities which are surprising given the usual understanding of communication in that group. That is, it is commonly reported that people diagnosed with an ASD have trouble with metaphor, irony, conversational implicature and other non-literal language. This is not a matter of trouble with knowledge and application of rules of grammar. The difficulties lie, rather, in successful communicative interaction. Though we did find pragmatic errors within (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  50.  29
    Pragmatic disorders and their social impact.Louise Cummings - 2011 - Pragmatics and Society 2 (1):17-36.
    Pragmatic disorders in children and adults have been the focus of clinical investigations for approximately 40 years. In that time, clinicians and researchers have established a diverse range of pragmatic phenomena that are disrupted in these disorders. Pragmatic deficits include problems with the use and understanding of speech acts, the processing of non-literal language, failure to adhere to Gricean maxims in conversation and discourse deficits. These deficits are found in several clinical populations including individuals with autistic spectrum disorders, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 999