Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Moving forward in bioethical theory: Theories, cases, and specified principlism.David Degrazia - 1992 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 17 (5):511-539.
    The field of bioethics has deployed different models of justification for particular moral judgments. The best known models are those of deductivism, casuistry, and principlism (under one, rather limited interpretation). Each of these models, however, has significant difficulties that are explored in this essay. An alternative model, suggested by the work of Henry Richardson, is presented. It is argued that specified principlism is the most promising model of justification in bioethics. Keywords: casuistry, deductivism, ethical theories, intuition principlism, specified principlism, specification (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Wide reflective equilibrium and theory acceptance in ethics.Norman Daniels - 1979 - Journal of Philosophy 76 (5):256-282.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   425 citations  
  • Norman Daniels: Justice and Justification. Reflective Equilibrium in Theory and Practice & Folke Tersman, Reflective Equilibrium. An Essay in Moral Epistemology. [REVIEW]Theo van Willigenburg - 1998 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 1 (1):129-132.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • Common Morality as an Alternative to Principlism.K. Danner Clouser - 1995 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 5 (3):219-236.
    Unlike the principles of Kant, Mill, and Rawls, those of principlism are not action guides that stem from an underlying, integrated moral theory. Hence problems arise in reconciling the principles with each other and, indeed, in interpreting them as action guides at all, since they have no content in and of themselves. Another approach to "theory and method in bioethics" is presented as an alternative to principlism, though actually the "alternative" predates principlism by about 10 years. The alternative's account of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • A Critique of Principlism.K. D. Clouser & B. Gert - 1990 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 15 (2):219-236.
    The authors use the term “principlism” to refer to the practice of using “principles” to replace both moral theory and particular moral rules and ideals in dealing with the moral problems that arise in medical practice. The authors argue that these “principles” do not function as claimed, and that their use is misleading both practically and theoretically. The “principles” are in fact not guides to action, but rather they are merely names for a collection of sometimes superficially related matters for (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   132 citations  
  • The Authority of the Clinical Ethicist.David J. Casarett, Frona Daskal & John Lantos - 1998 - Hastings Center Report 28 (6):6.
  • Mechanics on Duty: The Limitations of a Technical Definition of Moral Expertise for Work in Applied Ethics.Arthur L. Caplan - 1982 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 8:1-18.
    A former Prime Minister of Israel is alleged to have said that her country would never ascend to the status of authentic statehood until it possessed certain well-known social attributes — organized crime, prostitution, and corruption. These features, while obviously undesirable, were she felt, reliable indices of societal maturation. This anecdote is suggestive in understanding current events pertaining to the field of applied ethics.Philosophers have produced a massive body of opinion and argument on a diverse range of subjects under the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Mechanics on Duty: The Limitations of a Technical Definition of Moral Expertise for Work in Applied Ethics.Arthur L. Caplan - 1982 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 12 (sup1):1-18.
    A former Prime Minister of Israel is alleged to have said that her country would never ascend to the status of authentic statehood until it possessed certain well-known social attributes — organized crime, prostitution, and corruption. These features, while obviously undesirable, were she felt, reliable indices of societal maturation. This anecdote is suggestive in understanding current events pertaining to the field of applied ethics.Philosophers have produced a massive body of opinion and argument on a diverse range of subjects under the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Ethical Engineers Need Not Apply: The State of Applied Ethics Today.Arthur L. Caplan - 1980 - Science, Technology and Human Values 5 (4):24-32.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Can applied ethics be effective in health care and should it strive to be?Arthur L. Caplan - 1982 - Ethics 93 (2):311-319.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Bioethics on Trial.Arthur L. Caplan - 1991 - Hastings Center Report 21 (2):19-20.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Reply to strong on principlism and casuistry.Tom L. Beauchamp - 2000 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 25 (3):342 – 347.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • On Eliminating the Distinction Between Applied Ethics and Ethical Theory.Tom L. Beauchamp - 1984 - The Monist 67 (4):514-531.
    “Applied ethics” has been the major growth area in North American philosophy in the last decade, yet a robust confidence and enthusiasm over its promise is far from universal in academic philosophy. It is considered nonphilosophical in West Germany, and has largely failed to penetrate British departments of philosophy. Whether it has any intellectually or pedagogically redeeming value is still widely debated in North America, where many who have tried to teach some area of applied ethics for the first time (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Moving the Conversation Forward.Mark P. Aulisio, Robert M. Arnold & Stuart J. Youngner - 1999 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 10 (1):49-56.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The question of method in ethics consultation.George J. Agich - 2001 - American Journal of Bioethics 1 (4):31 – 41.
    This paper offers an exposition of what the question of method in ethics consultation involves under two conditions: when ethics consultation is regarded as a practice and when the question of method is treated systematically. It discusses the concept of the practice and the importance of rules in constituting the actions, cognition, and perceptions of practitioners. The main body of the paper focuses on three elements of the question of method: canon, discipline, and history, which are treated heuristically to outline (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Ethics Expert Testimony: Against the Skeptics.G. J. Agich & B. J. Spielman - 1997 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 22 (4):381-403.
    There is great skepticism about the admittance of expert normative ethics testimony into evidence. However, a practical analysis of the way ethics testimony has been used in courts of law reveals that the skeptical position is itself based on assumptions that are controversial. We argue for an alternative way to understand such expert testimony. This alternative understanding is based on the practice of clinical ethics.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Authority in Ethics Consultation.George J. Agich - 1995 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 23 (3):273-283.
    Authority is an uneasy, political notion. Heard with modern ears, it calls forth images of oppression and power. In institutional settings, authority is everywhere present, and its use poses problems for the exercise both of individual autonomy and of responsibility. In medical ethics, the exercise of authority has been located on the side of the physician or the health care institution, and it has usually been opposed by appeal to patient autonomy and rights. So, it is not surprising, though still (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Authority in Ethics Consultation.George J. Agich - 1995 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 23 (3):273-283.
    Authority is an uneasy, political notion. Heard with modern ears, it calls forth images of oppression and power. In institutional settings, authority is everywhere present, and its use poses problems for the exercise both of individual autonomy and of responsibility. In medical ethics, the exercise of authority has been located on the side of the physician or the health care institution, and it has usually been opposed by appeal to patient autonomy and rights. So, it is not surprising, though still (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The structures of the life-world.Alfred Schutz - 1973 - Evanston [Ill.]: Northwestern University Press. Edited by Thomas Luckmann.
    The Structures of the Life-World is the final focus of twenty-seven years of Alfred Schutz's labor, encompassing the fruits of his work between 1932 and his death in 1959. This book represents Schutz's seminal attempt to achieve a comprehensive grasp of the nature of social reality. Here he integrates his theory of relevance with his analysis of social structures. Thomas Luckmann, a former student of Schutz's, completed the manuscript for publication after Schutz's untimely death.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   173 citations  
  • Voices and time: The venture of clinical ethics.Richard M. Zaner - 1993 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 18 (1):9-31.
    Four prominent views of the nature and methods of clinical ethics (especially in consultation forums) are reviewed; each is then submitted to a criticism intended to show both weaknesses and strengths. It is argued that clinical ethics needs to be responsive to the specific complexities of clinical situations. For this, the need for an expanded notion of practical reason within unique situations is emphasized, one whose aim is to facilitate decision-making on the part of those directly responsible for them and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Medicine and dialogue.Richard M. Zaner - 1990 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 15 (3):303-325.
    Physicians have for some time been questioning the prevailing view of medicine as applied biology. It is urged that medicine needs to be reconceived so as to provide appropriate emphasis on the patient's experience and understanding of illness. After reviewing these arguments and the scientific paradigm underlying the received view in light of certain themes in medicine's history and of current thinking, Pellegrino's thesis is analyzed: medicine should be understood as an inherently moral enterprise, a form of praxis focused on (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Is “ethicist” anything to call a philosopher?Richard M. Zaner - 1984 - Human Studies 7 (3-4):71 - 90.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Immorality of Applied Ethics.James O. Young - 1986 - International Journal of Applied Philosophy 3 (2):37-43.
  • The Reluctant Retained Witness: Alleged Sexual Misconduct in the Doctor/Patient Relationship.M. Yarborough - 1997 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 22 (4):345-364.
    Testifying as an expert ethics witness raises a number of important issues. These include: the prospect of generating adverse publicity for oneself and one's institution, avoiding bias, giving testimony that is at odds with testimony given by colleagues, potential conflicts of interest introduced by reimbursement, the need of those who hear the testimony of bioethicists to appreciate the nature of moral expertise, the difficulty of assessing the quality of legal evidence which emerges from adversarial legal proceedings, and the need to (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Applied Philosophy.Leslie Stephenson - 2007 - Metaphilosophy 1 (3):258-267.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Applied philosophy.Leslie Stevenson - 1970 - Metaphilosophy 1 (3):258–267.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Bioethics as Methodological Case Resolution: Specification, Specified Principlism and Casuistry.Ana Smith Iltis - 2000 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 25 (3):271-284.
    Bioethical decision-making depends on presuppositions about the function and goal of bioethics. The authors in this issue of The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy share the assumption that bioethics is about resolving cases, not about moral theory, and that the best method of bioethical decision-making is that which produces useful answers. Because we have no universally agreed upon background moral theory which can serve as the basis for bioethical decision-making, they try to move bioethics away from theory. For them, a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Cautionary Advice for Humanists.Mark Siegler - 1981 - Hastings Center Report 11 (2):19-20.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Reflections on the problem of relevance.Alfred Schutz - 1970 - Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press. Edited by Richard M. Zaner.
  • The Task Force Report: Comprehensible Forest or Unknown Beetles?Judith Wilson Ross - 1999 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 10 (1):26-33.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Outline of a decision procedure for ethics.John Rawls - 1951 - Philosophical Review 60 (2):177-197.
  • Defending principlism well understood.Michael Quante & Andreas Vieth - 2002 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 27 (6):621 – 649.
    After presenting the current version of principlism, in the process repudiating a widespread deductivist misinterpretation, a fundamental metaethical disagreement is developed by outlining the deductivistic critique of principlism. Once the grounds for this critique have been understood, the dispute between casuistry, deductivism and principlism can be restructured, and the model of "application" proven to be the central difference. In the concluding section it is argued that principlism is the most attractive position, if the perceptual model of weak intuitionism is made (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Medical ethics in the courtroom: the need for scrutiny.Edmund D. Pellegrino & Virginia Ashby Sharpe - 1988 - Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 32 (4):547-564.
  • Clinical Ethics Consultations: Some Reflections on the Report of the SHHV-SBC.Edmund D. Pellegrino - 1999 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 10 (1):5-12.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Ethics and Experts.Cheryl N. Noble - 1982 - Hastings Center Report 12 (3):7-15.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Facilitating Medical Ethics Case Review: What Ethics Committees Can Learn from Mediation and Facilitation Techniques.Mary Beth West & Joan McIver Gibson - 1992 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 1 (1):63.
    Medical ethics committees are increasingly called on to assist doctors, patients, and families in resolving difficult ethics issues. Although committees are becoming more sophisticated in the substance of medical ethics, little attention has been given to the processes these committees use to facilitate decision-making. In 1990, the National Institute for Dispute Resolution in Washington, D.C., provided a planning grant from its Innovation Fund to the Institute of Public Law of the University of New Mexico School of Law to look at (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The method of 'principlism': A critique of the critique.B. Andrew Lustig - 1992 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 17 (5):487-510.
    Several scholars have recently criticized the dominant emphasis upon mid-level principles in bioethics best exemplified by Beauchamp and Childress's Principles of Biomedical Ethics . In Part I of this essay, I assess the fairness and cogency of three broad criticisms raised against ‘principlism’ as an approach: (1) that principlism, as an exercise in applied ethics, is insufficiently attentive to the dialectical relations between ethical theory and moral practice; (2) that principlism fails to offer a systematic account of the principles of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Must the Ethics Consultant See the Patient?John La Puma & David L. Schiedermayer - 1990 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 1 (1):56-59.
  • Casuistry and principlism: The convergence of method in biomedical ethics. [REVIEW]Mark Kuczewski - 1998 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 19 (6):509-524.
    Casuistry and principlism are two of the leading contenders to be considered the methodology of bioethics. These methods may be incommensurable since the former emphasizes the examination of cases while the latter focuses on moral principles. Conversely, since both analyze cases in terms of mid-level principles, there is hope that these methods may be reconcilable or complementary. I analyze the role of principles in each and thereby show that these theories are virtually identical when interpreted in a certain light. That (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • What is applied about "applied" philosophy?Loretta M. Kopelman - 1990 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 15 (2):199-218.
    "Applied" is a technical term describing a variety of new philosophical enterprises. The author examines and rejects the view that these fields are derivative. Whatever principles, judgments, or background theories that are employed to solve problems in these areas are either changed by how they are used, or at least the possibility exists of their being changed. Hence we ought to stop calling these endeavors "applied", or agree that the meaning of "apply" will have to include the possibility that what (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Confessions of an Expert Ethics Witness.K. Kipnis - 1997 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 22 (4):325-343.
    The aim of this essay is to describe and reflect upon the concrete particulars of one academician's work as an expert ethics witness. The commentary on my practices and the narrative descriptions of three cases are offered as evidence for the thesis that it is possible to act honorably within a role that some have considered to be inherently illicit. Practical measures are described for avoiding some of the best known pitfalls. The discussion concludes with a listing of the distinctive (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Who ate the apple? A commentary on the core competencies report.Nancy M. P. King - 1999 - HEC Forum 11 (2):170-175.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Review of Albert R. Jonsen and Stephen Toulmin: The Abuse of Casuistry: A History of Moral Reasoning[REVIEW]Kenneth W. Kemp - 1989 - Ethics 99 (4):945-946.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • The Abuse of Casuistry: A History of Moral Reasoning.Kenneth W. Kemp - 1988 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 24 (1):76-80.
    In this engaging study, the authors put casuistry into its historical context, tracing the origin of moral reasoning in antiquity, its peak during the sixteenth and early seventeenth century, and its subsequent fall into disrepute from the mid-seventeenth century.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   218 citations  
  • Case Analysis in Clinical Ethics.Albert R. Jonsen - 1990 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 1 (1):63-65.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Can Principlism Save Medical Ethics?Patrick Guinan - 2002 - The National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly 2 (2):229-234.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Method of Public Morality versus the Method of Principlism.R. M. Green, B. Gert & K. D. Clouser - 1993 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 18 (5):477-489.
    Two years ago in two articles in a thematic issue of this journal the three of us engaged in a critique of principlism. In a subsequent issue, B. Andrew Lustig defended aspects of principlism we had criticized and argued against our own account of morality. Our reply to Lustig's critique is also in two parts, corresponding with his own. Our first part shows how Lustig's criticisms are seriously misdirected. Our second and philosophically more important part picks up on Lustig's challenge (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Ethics Consultation: The Least Dangerous Profession?Giles R. Scofield, John C. Fletcher, Albert R. Jonsen, Christian Lilje, Donnie J. Self & Judith Wilson Ross - 1993 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2 (4):417.
    Whether ethics is too important to be left to the experts or so important that it must be is an age-old question. The emergence of clinical ethicists raises it again, as a question about professionalism. What role clinical ethicists should play in healthcare decision making – teacher, mediator, or consultant – is a question that has generated considerable debate but no consensus.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Common morality versus specified principlism: Reply to Richardson.Bernard Gert, Charles M. Culver & K. Danner Clouser - 2000 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 25 (3):308 – 322.
    In his article 'Specifying, balancing and interpreting bioethical principles' (Richardson, 2000), Henry Richardson claims that the two dominant theories in bioethics - principlism, put forward by Beauchamp and Childress in Principles of Bioethics , and common morality, put forward by Gert, Culver and Clouser in Bioethics: A Return to Fundamentals - are deficient because they employ balancing rather than specification to resolve disputes between principles or rules. We show that, contrary to Richardson's claim, the major problem with principlism, either the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Bioethics in a Legal Forum: Confessions of an "Expert" Witness.J. C. Fletcher - 1997 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 22 (4):297-324.
    This article reflects on the author's modest experience as an expert witness in two trials: Osheroff vs. Greenspan (1983), and In the Matter of Baby K (1994). Bioethicists' expertise as scholar-teachers and consultants on particular issues merits qualification by judges as expert witnesses. The article argues that a different kind of expertise – strong moral advocacy – is required to be an effective expert witness. The major lessons of expert witnessing for the author concern the demands and strains on the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations