Results for 'cancer screening'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  20
    Cervical cancer screening: a prospective cohort study of the effects of historical patient compliance and a population‐based informatics prompted reminder on screening rates.Kathy L. MacLaughlin, Kristi M. Swanson, James M. Naessens, Kurt B. Angstman & Rajeev Chaudhry - 2014 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 20 (2):136-143.
  2.  80
    Safe, or Sorry? Cancer Screening and Inductive Risk.Anya Plutynski - 2017 - In Kevin Christopher Elliott & Ted Richards (eds.), Exploring Inductive Risk: Case Studies of Values in Science. New York: Oup Usa. pp. 149-169.
    The focus of this chapter will be on the epistemic and normative questions at issue in debates about cancer screening, with a special focus on mammography as a case study. Such questions include: How do we know who needs to be screened? What are the benefits and harms of cancer screening, and what is the quality of evidence for each? How ought we to measure and compare these benefits and harms? What are the sources of uncertainty (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  3.  23
    Breast cancer screening in younger women: evidence and decision making.J. Mark Elwood - 1997 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 3 (3):179-186.
  4. Cervical cancer screening in Nepal: ethical considerations.Bishal Gyawali, June Keeling, Edwin van Teijlingen, Liladhar Dhakal & Arja Aro - forthcoming - Medicolegal and Bioethics:1.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  37
    Epistemic risks in cancer screening: Implications for ethics and policy.Justin B. Biddle - 2020 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 79:101200.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  6. Older Adults and Forgoing Cancer Screening.Alexia M. Torke, Peter H. Schwartz, Laura R. Holtz, Kianna Montz & Greg A. Sachs - 2013 - Journal of the American Medical Association Internal Medicine 173 (7):526-531.
    Although there is a growing recognition that older adults and those with extensive comorbid conditions undergo cancer screening too frequently, there is little information about patients’ perceptions regarding cessation of cancer screening. Information on older adults’ views of screening cessation would be helpful both for clinicians and for those designing interventions to reduce overscreening.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  12
    Knowledge about cervical cancer screening among family physicians: cross‐sectional survey.Maria del Refugio Gonzalez-Losa, Glendy K. Gongora-Marfil & Marylin Puerto-Solis - 2009 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 15 (2):289-291.
  8.  30
    Potential biases in colorectal cancer screening using faecal occult blood test.Dea Grip Riboe, Tilde Steen Dogan & John Brodersen - 2013 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 19 (2):311-316.
  9.  37
    Truth or Spin? Disease Definition in Cancer Screening.Lynette Reid - 2017 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 42 (4):385-404.
    Are the small and indolent cancers found in abundance in cancer screening normal variations, risk factors, or disease? Naturalists in philosophy of medicine turn to pathophysiological findings to decide such questions objectively. To understand the role of pathophysiological findings in disease definition, we must understand how they mislead in diagnostic reasoning. Participants on all sides of the definition of disease debate attempt to secure objectivity via reductionism. These reductivist routes to objectivity are inconsistent with the Bayesian nature of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  10.  34
    Optimal two‐stage breast cancer screening for countries with intermediate or low incidence of breast cancer.Shou-Jen Kuo, Tony Hsiu-Hsi Chen, Amy Ming-Fang Yen, Dar-Ren Chen & Li-Sheng Chen - 2010 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 16 (6):1345-1352.
  11.  32
    Non-maleficence and the ethics of consent to cancer screening.Lotte Elton - 2021 - Journal of Medical Ethics 47 (7):510-513.
    Cancer screening programmes cause harm to individuals via overdiagnosis and overtreatment, even where they confer population-level benefit. Screening thus appears to violate the principle of non-maleficence, since it entails medically unnecessary harm to individuals. Can consent to screening programmes negate the moral significance of this harm? In therapeutic medical contexts, consent is used as a means of rendering medical harm morally permissible. However, in this paper, I argue that it is unclear that the model of consent (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  12.  21
    How should we measure informed choice? The case of cancer screening.R. G. Jepson - 2005 - Journal of Medical Ethics 31 (4):192-196.
    Informed choice is increasingly recognised as important in supporting patient autonomy and ensuring that people are neither deceived nor coerced. In cancer screening the emphasis has shifted away from just promoting the benefits of screening to providing comprehensive information to enable people to make an informed choice. Cancer screening programmes in the UK now have policies in place which state that it is their responsibility to ensure that individuals are making an individual informed choice. There (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  13. Ethical and Scientific Issues in Cancer Screening and Prevention.Anya Plutynski - 2012 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 37 (3):310-323.
    November 2009’s announcement of the USPSTF’s recommendations for screening for breast cancer raised a firestorm of objections. Chief among them were that the panel had insufficiently valued patients’ lives or allowed cost considerations to influence recommendations. The publicity about the recommendations, however, often either simplified the actual content of the recommendations or bypassed significant methodological issues, which a philosophical examination of both the science behind screening recommendations and their import reveals. In this article, I discuss two of (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  14.  18
    Challenges in providing breast and cervical cancer screening services to Vietnamese Canadian women: the healthcare providers’ perspective.Tam Truong Donnelly - 2008 - Nursing Inquiry 15 (2):158-168.
    Breast cancer and cervical cancer are major contributors to morbidity and mortality among Vietnamese Canadian women. Vietnamese women are at risk because of their low participation rate in cancer‐preventative screening programmes. Drawing from the results of a larger qualitative study, this paper reports factors that influence Vietnamese women's participation in breast and cervical cancer screening from the healthcare providers’ perspectives. The women participants’ perspective was reported elsewhere.Semistructured interviews were conducted with six healthcare providers. Analysis (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  17
    Women’s participation in breast cancer screening in France – an ethical approach.Grégoire Moutel, Nathalie Duchange, Sylviane Darquy, Sandrine de Montgolfier, Frédérique Papin-Lefebvre, Odile Jullian, Jérôme Viguier, Hélène Sancho-Garnier & $authorfirstName $authorlastName - 2014 - BMC Medical Ethics 15 (1):64.
    Breast cancer is a major public health challenge. Organized mammography screening (OS) is considered one way to reduce breast cancer mortality. EU recommendations prone mass deployment of OS, and back in 2004, France introduced a national OS programme for women aged 50–74 years. However, in 2012, participation rate was still just 52.7%, well short of the targeted 70% objective. In an effort to re-address the (in) efficiency of the programme, the French National Cancer Institute has drafted (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  17
    Autonomous and informed decision-making : The case of colorectal cancer screening.Linda N. Douma, Ellen Uiters, Marcel F. Verweij & Danielle R. M. Timmermans - 2020 - PLoS ONE 15.
    Introduction It is increasingly considered important that people make an autonomous and informed decision concerning colorectal cancer screening. However, the realisation of autonomy within the concept of informed decision-making might be interpreted too narrowly. Additionally, relatively little is known about what the eligible population believes to be a 'good' screening decision. Therefore, we aimed to explore how the concepts of autonomous and informed decision-making relate to how the eligible CRC screening population makes their decision and when (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  15
    Informed Decision-Making and Capabilities in Population-based Cancer Screening.Ineke L. L. E. Bolt, Maartje H. N. Schermer, Hanna Bomhof-Roordink & Danielle R. M. Timmermans - 2022 - Public Health Ethics 15 (3):289-300.
    Informed decision-making (IDM) is considered an important ethical and legal requirement for population-based screening. Governments offering such screening have a duty to enable invitees to make informed decisions regarding participation. Various views exist on how to define and measure IDM in different screening programmes. In this paper we first address the question which components should be part of IDM in the context of cancer screening. Departing from two diverging interpretations of the value of autonomy—as a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  41
    Debating the Desirability of New Biomedical Technologies: Lessons from the Introduction of Breast Cancer Screening in the Netherlands. [REVIEW]Marianne Boenink - 2012 - Health Care Analysis 20 (1):84-102.
    Health technology assessment (HTA) was developed in the 1970s and 1980s to facilitate decision making on the desirability of new biomedical technologies. Since then, many of the standard tools and methods of HTA have been criticized for their implicit normativity. At the same time research into the character of technology in practice has motivated philosophers, sociologists and anthropologists to criticize the traditional view of technology as a neutral instrument designed to perform a specific function. Such research suggests that the tools (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  19.  36
    The Role of Socially Embedded Concepts in Breast Cancer Screening: An Empirical Study with Australian Experts.Lisa M. Parker & Stacy M. Carter - 2016 - Public Health Ethics 9 (3):276-289.
    It is not clear whether breast cancer screening is a public health intervention or an individual clinical service. The question is important because the concepts best suited for ethical reasoning in public health might be different to the concepts commonly employed in biomedical ethics. We consider it likely that breast screening has elements of a public health intervention and used an empirical ethics approach to explore this further. If breast screening has public health characteristics, it is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  35
    A Role for Science in Public Policy? The Obstacles, Illustrated by the Case of Breast Cancer Screening Policy.Manuela Fernández Pinto & Janet A. Kourany - 2018 - Science, Technology, and Human Values 43 (5):917-943.
    A coherent and helpful public policy based on science is difficult to achieve for at least three reasons. First, there are purely practical problems—for example, that scientific experts often disagree on policy-relevant questions and their debates often continue well beyond policy appropriate timelines. Second, there are epistemic problems—for example, that science is hardly the neutral supplier of factual information that traditionally has been supposed. And third, there are social problems: given the commercialization of today’s science and its enduring limitations, much (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  19
    Accessing rural populations: role of the community pharmacist in a breast and cervical cancer screening programme.Timothy R. McGuire, Melissa Leypoldt, Warren A. Narducci & Kathy Ward - 2007 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 13 (1):146-149.
  22.  14
    Overuse of mammography during the first round of an organized breast cancer screening programme.Eric Chamot, Agathe Charvet & Thomas V. Perneger - 2009 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 15 (4):620-625.
  23.  19
    A discussion on controversies and ethical dilemmas in prostate cancer screening.Satish Chandra Mishra - 2021 - Journal of Medical Ethics 47 (3):152-158.
    Prostate cancer (PCa) is one of the the most common cancers in men. A blood test called prostate-specific antigen (PSA) has a potential to pick up this cancer very early and is used for screening of this disease. However, screening for prostate cancer is a matter of debate. Level 1 evidence from randomised controlled trials suggests a reduction in cancer-specific mortality from PCa screening. However, there could be an associated impact on quality of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  19
    Analytical decision model for sample size and effectiveness projections for use in planning a population‐based randomized controlled trial of colorectal cancer screening.Sherry Y.-H. Chiu, Nea Malila, Amy M.-F. Yen, Ahti Anttila, Matti Hakama & H.-H. Chen - 2011 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 17 (1):123-129.
  25.  14
    Using iron deficiency tests for colorectal cancer screening: a feasibility study in one UK general practice.Adrian Edwards, Michael Penney & Miles Allison - 2004 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 10 (3):475-479.
  26.  31
    Evaluation of a community‐based intervention to enhance breast cancer screening practices in Brazil.Luiz Claudio Santos Thuler & Hilda Guimaraes Freitas - 2008 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 14 (6):1012-1017.
  27.  16
    Impact of the Scottish Bowel Cancer Screening Programme on patient and tumour characteristics at a single centre.Craig Mackay, George Ramsay, Anthony Rafferty & Malcolm Loudon - 2014 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 20 (1):7-11.
  28.  19
    Good Ethics Begins With Sound Medicine: Prostate Cancer Screening and Chemoprevention.Ronald Ennis & Alan Jotkowitz - 2011 - American Journal of Bioethics 11 (12):26-27.
    The American Journal of Bioethics, Volume 11, Issue 12, Page 26-27, December 2011.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  34
    Breast cancer genetic screening and critical bioethics' gaze.Lisa S. Parker - 1995 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 20 (3):313-337.
    This paper illustrates a role that bioethics should play in developing and criticizing protocols for breast cancer genetic screening. It demonstrates how a critical bioethics, using approaches and reflecting concerns of contemporary philosophy of science and science studies, may critically interrogate the normative and conceptual schemes within which ethical considerations about such screening protocols are framed. By exploring various factors that influence the development of such protocols, including politics, cultural norms, and conceptions of disease, this paper and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  30. Part I: Ethics in Public Health Studies and Clinical Research. Introduction / Mayfong Mayxay, Bansa Oupathana, Bernard Taverne. Examples of Medical Ethical Issues in Laos: Dilemmas in Health Care Decisions / Mayfong Mayxay, Bansa Oupathana. Informed Consent in Medical Studies: An Essential Ethical Step / Laurence Borand, Bunnet Dim. Ethical Issues Surrounding a Study on Cervical Cancer Screening of Women Living with HIV in Laos / Phimpha Paboribourne, Bernard Tavenre. Ethical Issues to Consider Before Starting Research: Example of a Study on Preventing Mother-to-Child Transmission of the Hepatitis B Virus / Gonzague Jourdain, Woottichai Khamduang, Vatthanaphone Latthaphasavang. Ethical Aspects When Using Biological Samples for Research, Audrey Dubot-Pérès, Claire Lajaunie with Manivanh Vongsouvath. Ethical Perspectives on a Survey of Adolescents Born with HIV in Thailand. [REVIEW]Sophie Le Coeur, Eva Lelièvre & Cheeraya Kanabkaew - 2018 - In Anne Marie Moulin, Bansa Oupathana, Manivanh Souphanthong & Bernard Taverne (eds.), The paths of ethics in research in Laos and the Mekong countries: health, environment, societies. Marseille: Institut de recherche pour le développement.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Cáncer y screening genético.M. Carmen Sanchez Monserrate - 1996 - Ludus Vitalis 4 (7):103-130.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  45
    Uninformed consent: Mass screening for prostate cancer.Stewart Justman - 2010 - Bioethics 26 (3):143-148.
    While medicine may agree in principle that cancer screening requires informed consent, such consent is not, in fact, common practice. In the case of prostate-cancer screening this means that men in large numbers undergo PSA testing with little understanding of its liabilities – in particular, that it may or may not decrease mortality, often detects cancer of questionable significance, and may lead to unnecessary surgery. Given that prostate cancer is known to be overtreated and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  23
    Evaluation of screening for a cancer: annotated catechism of the Gold Standard creed.Olli S. Miettinen, David F. Yankelevitz & Claudia I. Henschke - 2003 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 9 (2):145-150.
  34.  13
    Prevention in the age of personal responsibility: epigenetic risk-predictive screening for female cancers as a case study.Ineke Bolt, Eline M. Bunnik, Krista Tromp, Nora Pashayan, Martin Widschwendter & Inez de Beaufort - 2021 - Journal of Medical Ethics 47 (12):e46-e46.
    Epigenetic markers could potentially be used for risk assessment in risk-stratified population-based cancer screening programmes. Whereas current screening programmes generally aim to detect existing cancer, epigenetic markers could be used to provide risk estimates for not-yet-existing cancers. Epigenetic risk-predictive tests may thus allow for new opportunities for risk assessment for developing cancer in the future. Since epigenetic changes are presumed to be modifiable, preventive measures, such as lifestyle modification, could be used to reduce the risk (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  37
    Ethical issues evolving from patients' perspectives on compulsory screening for syphilis and voluntary screening for cervical cancer in Kenya.Dickens S. Omondi Aduda & Nhlanhla Mkhize - 2014 - BMC Medical Ethics 15 (1):27.
    Public health aims to provide universal safety and progressive opportunities to populations to realise their highest level of health through prevention of disease, its progression or transmission. Screening asymptomatic individuals to detect early unapparent conditions is an important public health intervention strategy. It may be designed to be compulsory or voluntary depending on the epidemiological characteristics of the disease. Integrated screening, including for both syphilis and cancer of the cervix, is a core component of the national reproductive (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  41
    How would a latent period for early breast cancer affect the benefit of screening?Leslie E. Blumenson - 1987 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 2 (2):169-182.
    The ideal goal of a screening program for breast cancer is to detect the disease at a stage when it is still curable by a simple lumpectomy. This goal would be possible if the tumor had an early latent period before it was vascularized. However, even if there existed a harmless screening examination that was sensitive enough to discover the cancer at this stage the benefit to be gained from a screening program would be highly (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. NCG 4.0: the network of cancer genes in the era of massive mutational screenings of cancer genomes.Omer An, Pendino Vera, D'Antonio Matteo, Ratti Emanuele, Gentilini Marco & Ciccarelli Francesca - 2014 - Database: The Journal of Biological Databases and Curation 2014.
    NCG 4.0 is the latest update of the Network of Cancer Genes, a web-based repository of systems-level properties of cancer genes. In its current version, the database collects information on 537 known (i.e. experimentally supported) and 1463 candidate (i.e. inferred using statistical methods) cancer genes. Candidate cancer genes derive from the manual revision of 67 original publications describing the mutational screening of 3460 human exomes and genomes in 23 different cancer types. For all 2000 (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  22
    Knowledge of oral cancer and screening practice of B.Sc. nursing students in Davangere City, India.Simpy Mittal, Usha Mohandas, ChanduGowrapura Natraj, Subramaniam Ramanarayanan, Mahesh Hiregoudar, Amit Mahuli & PrashantGoudar Manjunath - 2013 - Journal of Education and Ethics in Dentistry 3 (1):40.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  9
    Is Population Mass Screening for Certain Cancers Always Beneficial ?Anne Moates - 2003 - Chisholm Health Ethics Bulletin 9 (1):4.
  40.  34
    What ethical and legal principles should guide the genotyping of children as part of a personalised screening programme for common cancer?N. Hallowell, S. Chowdhury, A. E. Hall, P. Pharoah, H. Burton & N. Pashayan - 2014 - Journal of Medical Ethics 40 (3):163-167.
    Increased knowledge of the gene–disease associations contributing to common cancer development raises the prospect of population stratification by genotype and other risk factors. Individual risk assessments could be used to target interventions such as screening, treatment and health education. Genotyping neonates, infants or young children as part of a systematic programme would improve coverage and uptake, and facilitate a screening package that maximises potential benefits and minimises harms including overdiagnosis. This paper explores the potential justifications and risks (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  30
    "If you think you've got a lump, they'll screen you." Informed consent, health promotion, and breast cancer.N. Pfeffer - 2004 - Journal of Medical Ethics 30 (2):227-230.
    A great deal has been written about information that is or should be provided when seeking consent to medical research and treatment. Relatively little attention has been paid to information describing health promotion interventions. This paper critically examines some information material describing three different methods of encouraging early presentation of breast cancer in the UK: the NHS breast screening programme, breast self examination, and breast awareness. Findings from a content analysis of printed material and a series of focus (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  42.  41
    Risks and Benefits, Testing and Screening, Cancer, Genes and Dollars.Eric Kodish - 1997 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 25 (4):252-255.
    The ability to determine genetic predisposition to cancer represents an opportunity to expand cancer control efforts in a manner that was previously unimaginable. This possibility also forces individual patients, families, health care professionals, and society to confront difficult questions about genetic knowledge. Although genetic testing or screening for cancer risk may hold promise of cancer control benefits, this prospect also raises significant ethical and legal concerns that must inform and shape policy decisions. In “Cancer (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  14
    Marginal public health gain of screening for colorectal cancer: modelling study, based on WHO and national databases in the Nordic countries.Johann A. Sigurdsson, Linn Getz, Göran Sjönell, Paula Vainiomäki & John Brodersen - 2013 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 19 (2):400-407.
  44.  8
    How would a latent period for early breast cancer affect the benefit of screening?Leslie E. Blumenson - 1981 - Metamedicine 2 (2):169-182.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  21
    Rational choice(s)? Rethinking decision-making on breast cancer risk and screening mammography.Mandana Vahabi & Denise Gastaldo - 2003 - Nursing Inquiry 10 (4):245-256.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  4
    Transmissible cancers in mammals and bivalves: How many examples are there?Antoine M. Dujon, Georgina Bramwell, Benjamin Roche, Frédéric Thomas & Beata Ujvari - 2021 - Bioessays 43 (3):2000222.
    Transmissible cancers are elusive and understudied parasitic life forms caused by malignant clonal cells (nine lineages are known so far). They emerge by completing sequential steps that include breaking cell cooperation, evade anti‐cancer defences and shedding cells to infect new hosts. Transmissible cancers impair host fitness, and their importance as selective force is likely largely underestimated. It is, therefore, crucial to determine how common they might be in the wild. Here, we draw a parallel between the steps required for (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  7
    Biomarkers for Early Cancer Diagnosis: Prospects for Success through the Lens of Tumor Genetics.Tommaso A. Dragani, Valerie Matarese & Francesca Colombo - 2020 - Bioessays 42 (4):1900122.
    Thousands of candidate cancer biomarkers have been proposed, but so far, few are used in cancer screening. Failure to implement these biomarkers is attributed to technical and design flaws in the discovery and validation phases, but a major obstacle stems from cancer biology itself. Oncogenomics has revealed broad genetic heterogeneity among tumors of the same histology and same tissue (or organ) from different patients, while tumors of different tissue origins also share common genetic mutations. Moreover, there (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  36
    Breast cancer incidence: what do the figures mean?Ann Johnson & Jane Shekhdar - 2005 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 11 (1):27-31.
  49.  47
    Analysing the ethics of breast cancer overdiagnosis: a pathogenic vulnerability.Wendy A. Rogers - 2019 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 22 (1):129-140.
    Breast cancer screening aims to help women by early identification and treatment of cancers that might otherwise be life-threatening. However, breast cancer screening also leads to the detection of some cancers that, if left undetected and untreated, would not have damaged the health of the women concerned. At the time of diagnosis, harmless cancers cannot be identified as non-threatening, therefore women are offered invasive breast cancer treatment. This phenomenon of identifying non-harmful cancers is called overdiagnosis. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50. Patients Living With Breast Cancer During the Coronavirus Pandemic: The Role of Family Resilience, Coping Flexibility, and Locus of Control on Affective Responses.Eleonora Brivio, Paolo Guiddi, Ludovica Scotto, Alice V. Giudice, Greta Pettini, Derna Busacchio, Florence Didier, Ketti Mazzocco & Gabriella Pravettoni - 2021 - Frontiers in Psychology 11.
    The coronavirus disease 2019 pandemic has strongly affected oncology patients. Many screening and treatment programs have been postponed or canceled, and such patients also experience fear of increased risk of exposure to the virus. In many cases, locus of control, coping flexibility, and perception of a supportive environment, specifically family resilience, can allow for positive emotional outcomes for individuals managing complex health conditions like cancer. This study aims to determine if family resilience, coping flexibility, and locus of control (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000