Results for 'Space-time geometry'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Vigier III.Spin Foam Spinors & Fundamental Space-Time Geometry - 2000 - Foundations of Physics 30 (1).
  2. On the reality of space-time geometry and the wavefunction.Jeeva Anandan & Harvey R. Brown - 1995 - Foundations of Physics 25 (2):349--60.
    The action-reaction principle (AR) is examined in three contexts: (1) the inertial-gravitational interaction between a particle and space-time geometry, (2) protective observation of an extended wave function of a single particle, and (3) the causal-stochastic or Bohm interpretation of quantum mechanics. A new criterion of reality is formulated using the AR principle. This criterion implies that the wave function of a single particle is real and justifies in the Bohm interpretation the dual ontology of the particle and (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  3.  71
    Optical axiomatization of Minkowski space-time geometry.Brent Mundy - 1986 - Philosophy of Science 53 (1):1-30.
    Minkowski geometry is axiomatized in terms of the asymmetric binary relation of optical connectibility, using ten first-order axioms and the second-order continuity axiom. An axiom system in terms of the symmetric binary optical connection relation is also presented. The present development is much simpler than the corresponding work of Robb, upon which it is modeled.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  4.  32
    From disorder to space-time geometry.F. Englert - 1987 - Foundations of Physics 17 (6):621-635.
    Field propagation on fractal structures can generate a large scale symmetric space-time geometry. The significance of this fact and the nature of the resulting space-time are discussed.“Each contained all the others, but in this totality each was confused and comingled with all the others without order and system.”—Haïm Vital, 1543–1620 (Kabbalist of Safed); English translation taken from “Sabbatai Sevi” by G. Scholem (Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, 1973), p. 36.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Causal models and space-time geometries.Zoltan Domotor - 1972 - Synthese 24 (1-2):5 - 57.
  6. Consciousness, the brain, and space-time geometry.Stuart R. Hameroff - 2001 - Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 929:74-104.
    What is consciousness? Conventional approaches see it as an emergent property of complex interactions among individual neurons; however these approaches fail to address enigmatic features of consciousness. Accordingly, some philosophers have contended that "qualia," or an experiential medium from which consciousness is derived, exists as a fundamental component of reality. Whitehead, for example, described the universe as being composed of "occasions of experience." To examine this possibility scientifically, the very nature of physical reality must be re-examined. We must come to (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  7. Spacetime philosophy reconstructed via massive Nordström scalar gravities? Laws vs. geometry, conventionality, and underdetermination.J. Brian Pitts - 2016 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 53:73-92.
    What if gravity satisfied the Klein-Gordon equation? Both particle physics from the 1920s-30s and the 1890s Neumann-Seeliger modification of Newtonian gravity with exponential decay suggest considering a "graviton mass term" for gravity, which is _algebraic_ in the potential. Unlike Nordström's "massless" theory, massive scalar gravity is strictly special relativistic in the sense of being invariant under the Poincaré group but not the 15-parameter Bateman-Cunningham conformal group. It therefore exhibits the whole of Minkowski space-time structure, albeit only indirectly concerning (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  8.  31
    Email: Tmuel 1 er@ F dm. uni-f reiburg. De.Branching Space-Time & Modal Logic - 2002 - In T. Placek & J. Butterfield (eds.), Non-Locality and Modality. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 273.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  11
    Leszek Wronski.Branching Space-Times - 2013 - In Hanne Andersen, Dennis Dieks, Wenceslao González, Thomas Uebel & Gregory Wheeler (eds.), New Challenges to Philosophy of Science. Springer Verlag. pp. 135.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  11
    Nuel Belnap.of Branching Space-Times - 2002 - In T. Placek & J. Butterfield (eds.), Non-Locality and Modality. Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Part XI: Flesh, Body, Embodiment.Space & Time - 2018 - In Daniela Verducci, Jadwiga Smith & William Smith (eds.), Eco-Phenomenology: Life, Human Life, Post-Human Life in the Harmony of the Cosmos. Cham: Springer Verlag.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Perverted Space-Time Geodesy in Einstein’s Views on Geometry.Mario Bacelar Valente - 2018 - Philosophia Scientiae 22:137-162.
    A perverted space-time geodesy results from the idea of variable rods and clocks, whose length and rates are taken to be affected by the gravitational field. By contrast, what we might call a concrete geodesy relies on the idea of invariable unit-measuring rods and clocks. Indeed, this is a basic assumption of general relativity. Variable rods and clocks lead to a perverted geodesy, in the sense that a curved space-time may be seen as a result of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  52
    Space, time and geometry.Patrick Suppes - 1973 - Boston,: Reidel.
    Griinbaum's own article sets forth his views on the ontology of the curvature of empty space, especially in the geometrodynamics of Clifford and Wheeler. ...
  14. Time, consciousness, and quantum events in fundamental space-time geometry.Stuart R. Hameroff - 2003 - In R. Buccheri (ed.), The Nature of Time: Geometry, Physics and Perception. pp. 77-89.
    1. Introduction: The problems of time and consciousness What is time? St. Augustine remarked that when no one asked him, he knew what time was; however when someone asked him, he did not. Is time a process which flows? Is time a dimension in which processes occur? Does time actually exist? The notion that time is a process which "flows" directionally may be illusory (the "myth of passage") for if time did flow (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  15. Einstein, Newton and the empirical foundations of space time geometry.Robert DiSalle - 1992 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 6 (3):181 – 189.
    Abstract Einstein intended the general theory of relativity to be a generalization of the relativity of motion and, therefore, a radical departure from previous spacetime theories. It has since become clear, however, that this intention was not fulfilled. I try to explain Einstein's misunderstanding on this point as a misunderstanding of the role that spacetime plays in physics. According to Einstein, earlier spacetime theories introduced spacetime as the unobservable cause of observable relative motions and, in particular, as the cause of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  16.  13
    Perverted Space-Time Geodesy in Einstein’s Views on Geometry.Mario Bacelar Valente - 2018 - Philosophia Scientiae 22:137-162.
    Une géodésie spatio-temporelle pervertie résulte des notions de règles et d’horloges variables, qui sont prises pour avoir leur longueur et leur rythme affectés par le champ gravitationnel. D’autre part ce que nous pourrions appeler une géodésie concrète repose sur les notions de règles et d’horloges invariables de mesure d’unité. En fait, il s’agit d’une hypothèse de base de la relativité générale. Les règles et les horloges variables conduisent à une géodésie pervertie dans le sens où un espace-temps courbe pourrait être (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  13
    Derivation of the relativistic momentum and relativistic equation of motion from Newton's second law and Minkowskian space-time geometry.Krzysztof Rebilas - 2008 - Apeiron: Studies in Infinite Nature 15 (3).
  18.  94
    Hermann Weyl on Minkowskian SpaceTime and Riemannian Geometry.Yvon Gauthier - 2005 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 19 (3):261 – 269.
    Hermann Weyl as a founding father of field theory in relativistic physics and quantum theory always stressed the internal logic of mathematical and physical theories. In line with his stance in the foundations of mathematics, Weyl advocated a constructivist approach in physics and geometry. An attempt is made here to present a unified picture of Weyl's conception of space-time theories from Riemann to Minkowski. The emphasis is on the mathematical foundations of physics and the foundational significance of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19.  34
    Torsion Fields, Cartan–Weyl SpaceTime and State-Space Quantum Geometries, their Brownian Motions, and the Time Variables.Diego L. Rapoport - 2007 - Foundations of Physics 37 (4-5):813-854.
    We review the relation between spacetime geometries with trace-torsion fields, the so-called Riemann–Cartan–Weyl (RCW) geometries, and their associated Brownian motions. In this setting, the drift vector field is the metric conjugate of the trace-torsion one-form, and the laplacian defined by the RCW connection is the differential generator of the Brownian motions. We extend this to the state-space of non-relativistic quantum mechanics and discuss the relation between a non-canonical quantum RCW geometry in state-space associated with the gradient of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20.  35
    Space, time, & stuff.Frank Arntzenius - 2012 - New York: Oxford Univ. Press. Edited by Cian Seán Dorr.
    Space, Time, and Stuff is an attempt to show that physics is geometry: that the fundamental structure of the physical world is purely geometrical structure. Along the way, he examines some non-standard views about the structure of spacetime and its inhabitants, including the idea that space and time are pointless, the idea that quantum mechanics is a completely local theory, the idea that antiparticles are just particles travelling back in time, and the idea that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  21.  5
    The axiomatic geometry of Space-Time: An assessment of the work of A. A. Robb.A. J. Briginshaw - 1979 - Centaurus 22 (4):315-323.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  31
    The Geometry of Love: Space, Time, Mystery and Meaning in an Ordinary Church, by Margaret Visser.Thomas Storck - 2001 - The Chesterton Review 27 (4):524-525.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Space-Time and Isomorphism.Brent Mundy - 1992 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1992 (Volume One: Contributed Papers):515-527.
    Earman and Norton argue that manifold realism leads to inequivalence of Leibniz-shifted space-time models, with undesirable consequences such as indeterminism. I respond that intrinsic axiomatization of space-time geometry shows the variant models to be isomorphic with respect to the physically meaningful geometric predicates, and therefore certainly physically equivalent because no theory can characterize its models more closely than this. The contrary philosophical arguments involve confusions about identity and representation of space-time points, fostered by (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  24. Space, Time and Falsifiability Critical Exposition and Reply to "A Panel Discussion of Grünbaum's Philosophy of Science".Adolf Grünbaum - 1970 - Philosophy of Science 37 (4):469 - 588.
    Prompted by the "Panel Discussion of Grünbaum's Philosophy of Science" (Philosophy of Science 36, December, 1969) and other recent literature, this essay ranges over major issues in the philosophy of space, time and space-time as well as over problems in the logic of ascertaining the falsity of a scientific hypothesis. The author's philosophy of geometry has recently been challenged along three main distinct lines as follows: (i) The Panel article by G. J. Massey calls for (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  25.  30
    Space, time, and gravitation.Arthur Stanley Eddington - 1929 - New York,: Harper.
    PREFACE: - BY his theory of relativity Albert Einstein has provoked a revolution of thought in physical science. The achievement consists essentially in this Einstein has succeeded in separating far more completely than hitherto the share of the observer and the share of external nature in the things we see happen. The perception of an object by an observer depends on his own situation and circumstances for example, distance will make it appear smaller and dimmer. We make allowance for this (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  26.  77
    Constructing or completing physical geometry? On the relation between theory and evidence in accounts of space-time structure.Martin Carrier - 1990 - Philosophy of Science 57 (3):369-394.
    The aim of this paper is to discuss the relation between the observation basis and the theoretical principles of General Relativity. More specifically, this relation is analyzed with respect to constructive axiomatizations of the observation basis of space-time theories, on the one hand, and in attempts to complete them, on the other. The two approaches exclude one another so that a choice between them is necessary. I argue that the completeness approach is preferable for methodological reasons.
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  27.  44
    Space-time constructivism vs. modal provincialism: Or, how special relativistic theories needn't show Minkowski chronogeometry.J. Brian Pitts - 2017 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 67:191-198.
    Already in 1835 Lobachevski entertained the possibility of multiple geometries of the same type playing a role. This idea of rival geometries has reappeared from time to time but had yet to become a key idea in space-time philosophy prior to Brown's _Physical Relativity_. Such ideas are emphasized towards the end of Brown's book, which I suggest as the interpretive key. A crucial difference between Brown's constructivist approach to space-time theory and orthodox "space- (...) realism" pertains to modal scope. Constructivism takes a broad modal scope in applying to all local classical field theories---modal cosmopolitanism, one might say, including theories with multiple geometries. By contrast the orthodox view is modally provincial in assuming that there exists a _unique_ geometry, as the familiar theories have. These theories serve as the "canon" for the orthodox view. Their historical roles also suggest a Whiggish story of inevitable progress. Physics literature after c. 1920 is relevant to orthodoxy primarily as commentary on the canon, which closed in the 1910s. The orthodox view explains the spatio-temporal behavior of matter in terms of the manifestation of the real geometry of space-time, an explanation works fairly well within the canon. The orthodox view, Whiggish history, and the canon have a symbiotic relationship. If one happens to philosophize about a theory outside the canon, space-time realism sheds little light on the spatio-temporal behavior of matter. Worse, it gives the _wrong_ answer when applied to an example arguably _within_ the canon, a sector of Special Relativity, namely, _massive_ scalar gravity with universal coupling. Which is the true geometry---the flat metric from the Poincare' symmetry group, the conformally flat metric exhibited by material rods and clocks, or both---or is the question faulty? How does space-time realism explain the fact that all matter fields see the same curved geometry, when so many ways to mix and match exist? Constructivist attention to dynamical details is vindicated; geometrical shortcuts can disappoint. The more exhaustive exploration of relativistic field theories in particle physics, especially massive theories, is a largely untapped resource for space-time philosophy. (shrink)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  28.  53
    Some Mathematical, Epistemological, and Historical Reflections on the Relationship Between Geometry and Reality, SpaceTime Theory and the Geometrization of Theoretical Physics, from Riemann to Weyl and Beyond.Luciano Boi - 2019 - Foundations of Science 24 (1):1-38.
    The history and philosophy of science are destined to play a fundamental role in an epoch marked by a major scientific revolution. This ongoing revolution, principally affecting mathematics and physics, entails a profound upheaval of our conception of space, spacetime, and, consequently, of natural laws themselves. Briefly, this revolution can be summarized by the following two trends: by the search for a unified theory of the four fundamental forces of nature, which are known, as of now, as (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29.  6
    Space, Time, and Mechanics: Basic Structures of a Physical Theory.D. Mayr & G. Süssmann - 1982 - Springer.
    In connection with the "Philosophy of Science" research program conducted by the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft a colloquium was held in Munich from 18th to 20th May 1919. This covered basic structures of physical theories, the main emphasis being on the interrelation of space, time and mechanics. The present volume contains contributions and the results of the discussions. The papers are given here in the same order of presentation as at the meeting. The development of these "basic structures of physical (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Does the causal structure of space-time determine its geometry?David Malament - 1975
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  31.  54
    Space-time and synonymy.Peter Spirtes & Clark Glymour - 1982 - Philosophy of Science 49 (3):463-477.
    In "The Epistemology of Geometry" Glymour proposed a necessary structural condition for the synonymy of two space-time theories. David Zaret has recently challenged this proposal, by arguing that Newtonian gravitational theory with a flat, non-dynamic connection (FNGT) is intuitively synonymous with versions of the theory using a curved dynamical connection (CNGT), even though these two theories fail to satisfy Glymour's proposed necessary condition for synonymy. Zaret allowed that if FNGT and CNGT were not equally well (bootstrap) tested (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32.  6
    Life in Elastic SpaceTime.Tim Maudlin - 2002-01-01 - In Quantum Non‐Locality and Relativity. Tim Maudlin. pp. 205–220.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Non‐Euclidean Geometry The General Theory Superluminal Constraints and the GTR Lorentz Invariance and the GTR Quantum Theories in Non‐Minkowski Space‐times The GTR to the Rescue?
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  13
    SUPPES, P., Space, time and geometry[REVIEW]Janusz Plazowski - 1977 - Studia Logica 36:229.
  34. Space-time and probability.Simon Saunders - unknown
    Special relativity is most naturally formulated as a theory of spacetime geometry, but within the spacetime framework probability appears to be a purely epistemic notion. It is possible that progress can be made with rather different approaches - covariant stochastic equations, in particular - but the results to date are not encouraging. However, it seems a non-epistemic notion of probability can be made out in Minkowski space on Everett's terms. I shall work throughout with the consistent histories formalism. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  35. Theories of space-time in modern physics.Luciano Boi - 2004 - Synthese 139 (3):429 - 489.
    The physicist's conception of space-time underwent two major upheavals thanks to the general theory of relativity and quantum mechanics. Both theories play a fundamental role in describing the same natural world, although at different scales. However, the inconsistency between them emerged clearly as the limitation of twentieth-century physics, so a more complete description of nature must encompass general relativity and quantum mechanics as well. The problem is a theorists' problem par excellence. Experiment provide little guide, and the inconsistency (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  36.  31
    Geometry of time and space.Alfred Arthur Robb - 1936 - Cambridge [Eng.]: University Press.
    Alfred A. Robb. THEOREM 54 If P1 and P2 be a pair of parallel inertia planes while an inertia plane Q1 has parallel general lines a and b in common with P1 and P2 respectively and if Q2 be an inertia plane parallel to Q1 through some ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  37.  86
    The Isomorphism of Space, Time and Matter in Seventeenth-century Natural Philosophy.Carla Rita Palmerino - 2011 - Early Science and Medicine 16 (4):296-330.
    This article documents the general tendency of seventeenth-century natural philosophers, irrespective of whether they were atomists or anti-atomists, to regard space, time and matter as magnitudes having the same internal composition. It examines the way in which authors such as Fromondus, Basson, Sennert, Arriaga, Galileo, Magnen, Descartes, Gassendi, Charleton as well as the young Newton motivated their belief in the isomorphism of space, time and matter, and how this belief reflected on their views concerning the relation (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  29
    J. J. C. Smart. Introduction. Problems of space and time, Readings selected, edited and furnished with an introduction by J. J. C. Smart, The Macmillan Company, New York, and Collier-Macmillan Limited, London, 1964, pp. 1–23. - G. E. M. Anscombe. Aristotle and the sea battle; De interpretatione, Chapter IX. A revised version of XXI 388, with some omissions and additions. Problems of space and time, Readings selected, edited and furnished with an introduction by J. J. C. Smart, The Macmillan Company, New York, and Collier-Macmillan Limited, London, 1964, pp. 43–57. - Ernest Nagel. Space and geometry. A reprint of Chapter 8 of The structure of science by Ernest Nagel. Problems of space and time, Readings selected, edited and furnished with an introduction by J. J. C. Smart, The Macmillan Company, New York, and Collier-Macmillan Limited, London, 1964, pp. 178–213. - Nelson Goodman. Time and language, and the passage of time. A partial reprint of sections 2–3 of Chapter XI of XVII 130. Pro. [REVIEW]Alonzo Church - 1973 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 38 (1):146.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  52
    Implications of Space-Time Foam for Entanglement Correlations of Neutral Kaons.Sarben Sarkar - 2010 - Foundations of Physics 40 (7):978-1003.
    The role of CPT invariance and consequences for bipartite entanglement of neutral (K) mesons are discussed. A relaxation of CPT leads to a modification of the entanglement which is known as the ω effect. The relaxation of assumptions required to prove the CPT theorem are examined within the context of models of space-time foam. It is shown that the evasion of the EPR type entanglement implied by CPT (which is connected with spin statistics) is rather elusive. Relaxation of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  12
    Review of P. J. Zwart: About time: a philosophical inquiry into the origin and nature of time_; Ian Hinckfuss: _The Existence of Space and Time_; Patrick Suppes: _Space, Time and Geometry[REVIEW]Simon Prokhovnik - 1977 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 28 (4):389-390.
  41. The 4D Space-Time Dimensions of Facial Perception.Adelaide L. Burt & David P. Crewther - 2020 - Frontiers in Psychology 11.
    Facial information is a powerful channel for human-to-human communication. Characteristically, faces can be defined as biological objects that are four-dimensional (4D) patterns, whereby they have concurrently a spatial structure as well as temporal dynamics. The spatial characteristics of facial objects possess three dimensions (3D), namely breadth, height and importantly, depth. The temporal properties of facial objects are defined by how a 3D facial structure evolves dynamically over time; where time is referred to as the fourth dimension (4D). Our (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  18
    Inquiring into Space-Time, the Human Mind, and Religion: The Life and Work of Adolf Grünbaum.Martin Carrier & Gereon Wolters - 2019 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 50 (4):409-427.
    Grünbaum's three chief fields of research were space-time philosophy, the methodological credentials of psychoanalysis, and reasons given in favor of the existence of God. Grünbaum defended the so-called conventionality thesis of physical geometry. He partially followed Hans Reichenbach in this respect but developed a new ontological argument for the conventionality claim in addition. In addressing the physical basis of the direction of time, Grünbaum advocated that there is a physical basis for the distinction between the past (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  73
    Kant, Schlick and Friedman on Space, Time and Gravity in Light of Three Lessons from Particle Physics.J. Brian Pitts - 2018 - Erkenntnis 83 (2):135-161.
    Kantian philosophy of space, time and gravity is significantly affected in three ways by particle physics. First, particle physics deflects Schlick’s General Relativity-based critique of synthetic a priori knowledge. Schlick argued that since geometry was not synthetic a priori, nothing was—a key step toward logical empiricism. Particle physics suggests a Kant-friendlier theory of space-time and gravity presumably approximating General Relativity arbitrarily well, massive spin-2 gravity, while retaining a flat space-time geometry that is (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  44.  36
    Reconstructing an Open Order from Its Closure, with Applications to Space-Time Physics and to Logic.Francisco Zapata & Vladik Kreinovich - 2012 - Studia Logica 100 (1-2):419-435.
    In his logical papers, Leo Esakia studied corresponding ordered topological spaces and order-preserving mappings. Similar spaces and mappings appear in many other application areas such the analysis of causality in space-time. It is known that under reasonable conditions, both the topology and the original order relation $${\preccurlyeq}$$ can be uniquely reconstructed if we know the “interior” $${\prec}$$ of the order relation. It is also known that in some cases, we can uniquely reconstruct $${\prec}$$ (and hence, topology) from $${\preccurlyeq}$$. (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  54
    On the Significance of Space-Time.Robert Palter - 1955 - Review of Metaphysics 9 (1):149 - 155.
    Mathematically, the fusion of space and time may be explained as follows. In pre-relativity physics, space was envisaged as a three-dimensional Euclidean continuum. Such a continuum is homogeneous and isotropic, and its metrical character can be specified by the definition of the distance between any two points in the continuum: s2 = 2 + 2 + 2. Now, while it is possible to speak of a four-dimensional continuum in pre-relativity physics by adding the time-coordinate to the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. On the Problem of Emergence of Classical SpaceTime: The Quantum-Mechanical Approach.Alexey A. Kryukov - 2003 - Foundations of Physics 34 (8):1225-1248.
    The Riemannian manifold structure of the classical (i.e., Einsteinian) space-time is derived from the structure of an abstract infinite-dimensional separable Hilbert space S. For this S is first realized as a Hilbert space H of functions of abstract parameters. The space H is associated with the space of states of a macroscopic test-particle in the universe. The spatial localization of state of the particle through its interaction with the environment is associated with the selection (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  47.  45
    Contractions of space-time groups and relativistic quantum mechanics.P. L. Huddleston, M. Lorente & P. Roman - 1975 - Foundations of Physics 5 (1):75-87.
    The relation of the conformal group to various earlier proposed relativistic quantum mechanical dynamical groups (and other related groups) is studied in the framework of projective geometry, by explicitly constructing the contractions of the six-dimensional coordinate transformations. Five-dimensional realizations are then derived. An attempt is made to improve our physical insight through geometry.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  20
    Diagrams, Conceptual Space and Time, and Latent Geometry.Lorenzo Magnani - 2022 - Axiomathes 32 (6):1483-1503.
    The “origins” of (geometric) space is examined from the perspective of the so-called “conceptual space” or “semantic space”. Semantic space is characterized by its fundamental “locality” that generates an “implicit” mode of geometrizing. This view is examined from within three perspectives. First, the role that various diagrammatic entities play in the everyday life and pragmatic activities of selected ethnic groups is illustrated. Secondly, it is shown how conceptual spaces are fundamentally linked to the meaning effects of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  49.  62
    Quantum conformal fluctuations near the classical space-time singularity.J. V. Narlikar - 1981 - Foundations of Physics 11 (5-6):473-492.
    This paper investigates the behavior of conformal fluctuations of space-time geometry that are admissible under the quantized version of Einstein's general relativity. The approach to quantum gravity is via path integrals. It is shown that considerable simplification results when only the conformal degrees of freedom are considered under this scheme, so much so that it is possible to write down a formal kernel in the most general case where the space-time contains arbitrary distributions of particles (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Geometry and Monadology: Leibniz’s Analysis Situs and Philosophy of Space.Vincenzo De Risi - 2007 - Boston: Birkhäuser.
    This book reconstructs, both from the historical and theoretical points of view, Leibniz's geometrical studies, focusing in particular on the research Leibniz ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000