Results for 'Model Penal Code'

991 found
Order:
  1. a Model Penal Code for Democratic Societies, 17 CRIM. JUST.Kent Greenawalt & Excuses Justifications - 1998 - In Stephen Everson (ed.), Ethics: Companions to Ancient Thought, Vol. 4. Cambridge University Press. pp. 14--25.
  2. Pinkerton Short-Circuits the Model Penal Code.Andrew Ingram - 2019 - Villanova Law Review 64 (1):71-99.
    I show that the Pinkerton rule in conspiracy law is doctrinally and morally flawed. Unlike past critics of the rule, I propose a statutory fix that preserves and reforms it rather than abolishing it entirely. As I will show, this accommodates authors like Neil Katyal who have defended the rule as an important crime fighting tool while also fixing most of the traditional problems with it identified by critics like Wayne LaFave. Pinkerton is a vicarious liability rule that makes conspirators (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  32
    Justifications, excuses, and a model penal code for democratic societies.Kent Greenawalt - 1998 - Criminal Justice Ethics 17 (1):14-28.
  4.  21
    Donald Davidson and section 2.01 of the model penal code.James W. Child - 1992 - Criminal Justice Ethics 11 (1):31-43.
    (1992). Donald Davidson and section 2.01 of the model penal code. Criminal Justice Ethics: Vol. 11, No. 1, pp. 31-43. doi: 10.1080/0731129X.1992.9991909.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5. Insanity Defenses.Walter Sinnott-Armstrong & Ken Levy - 2011 - In John Deigh & David Dolinko (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of the Criminal Law. Oxford University Press. pp. 299--334.
    We explicate and evaluate arguments both for and against the insanity defense itself, different versions of the insanity defense (M'Naghten, Model Penal Code, and Durham (or Product)), the Irresistible Impulse rule, and various reform proposals.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  6. It's Not Too Difficult: A Plea to Resurrect the Impossibility Defense.Ken Levy - 2014 - New Mexico Law Revview 45:225-274.
    Suppose you are at the gym trying to see some naked beauties by peeping through a hole in the wall. A policeman happens by, he asks you what you are doing, and you honestly tell him. He then arrests you for voyeurism. Are you guilty? We don’t know yet because there is one more fact to be considered: while you honestly thought that a locker room was on the other side of the wall, it was actually a squash court. Are (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  16
    ‘De Minimis’ and the Structure of the Criminal Trial.R. A. Duff - 2022 - Law and Philosophy 42 (1):57-86.
    The Model Penal Code’s ‘De Minimis’ provisions (§ 2.12) cover different kinds of case in which, for reasons of equity, a prosecution should be dismissed. An exploration of these different cases illuminates some general issues about the structure of the criminal process, and about the processes of criminalization. These include the significance of the difference between dismissing a case and acquitting the defendant, and of the distinction between offences and defences; whether criminal offences should always be so (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8.  12
    Les structures sémantiques profondes du code pénal chinois.Zhu Lin - 2017 - Semiotica 2017 (216):497-508.
    Name der Zeitschrift: Semiotica Jahrgang: 2017 Heft: 216 Seiten: 497-508.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  17
    Prohibited Risks and Culpable Disregard or Inattentiveness: Challenge and Confusion in the Formulation of Risk-Creation Offenses.Paul H. Robinson - 2003 - Theoretical Inquiries in Law 4 (1).
    Because they track the Model Penal Code, current criminal law formulations of risk offenses typically fail to distinguish the rule of conduct question—What risks does the criminal law prohibit?—from the adjudication question — When is a particular violator’s conscious disregard of, or his inattentiveness to, a risk in a particular situation sufficiently condemnable to deserve criminal liability? Instead, the formulations address only the second question — through their definition of reckless and negligent culpability — and fail to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10.  2
    Source code obfuscation with genetic algorithms using LLVM code optimizations.Juan Carlos de la Torre, Javier Jareño, José Miguel Aragón-Jurado, Sébastien Varrette & Bernabé Dorronsoro - forthcoming - Logic Journal of the IGPL.
    With the advent of the cloud computing model allowing a shared access to massive computing facilities, a surging demand emerges for the protection of the intellectual property tied to the programs executed on these uncontrolled systems. If novel paradigm as confidential computing aims at protecting the data manipulated during the execution, obfuscating techniques (in particular at the source code level) remain a popular solution to conceal the purpose of a program or its logic without altering its functionality, thus (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Justice without Retribution: An Epistemic Argument against Retributive Criminal Punishment.Gregg D. Caruso - 2018 - Neuroethics 13 (1):13-28.
    Within the United States, the most prominent justification for criminal punishment is retributivism. This retributivist justification for punishment maintains that punishment of a wrongdoer is justified for the reason that she deserves something bad to happen to her just because she has knowingly done wrong—this could include pain, deprivation, or death. For the retributivist, it is the basic desert attached to the criminal’s immoral action alone that provides the justification for punishment. This means that the retributivist position is not reducible (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  12. The mad, the bad, and the psychopath.Heidi L. Maibom - 2008 - Neuroethics 1 (3):167-184.
    It is common for philosophers to argue that psychopaths are not morally responsible because they lack some of the essential capacities for morality. In legal terms, they are criminally insane. Typically, however, the insanity defense is not available to psychopaths. The primary reason is that they appear to have the knowledge and understanding required under the M’Naghten Rules. However, it has been argued that what is required for moral and legal responsibility is ‘deep’ moral understanding, something that psychopaths do not (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  13. Negligence, Mens Rea, and What We Want the Element of Mens Rea to Provide.Marcia Baron - 2020 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 14 (1):69-89.
    It is widely agreed that the top three Model Penal Code culpability levels suffice for criminal liability, but the fourth is controversial. And it isn’t just the particular MPC wording; that negligence should be on the list at all is controversial. My question is: What makes negligence so different? What is it about negligence that gives rise to the view that it should not suffice for criminal liability? In addressing it, I draw attention to how we conduct (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  14.  20
    Responsibility for Reckless Rape.Katrina Sifferd & Anneli Jefferson - 2022 - Humana Mente 15 (42).
    Sometimes persons are legally responsible for reckless behavior that causes criminal harm. This is the case under the newly drafted provisions of the U.S. Model Penal Code (MPC), which holds persons responsible for “simple” rape (nonconsensual sex without proof of force or threats of force), where the offender recklessly disregards the risk that the victim does not consent. In this paper we offer an explanation and corrective critique of the handling of reckless rape cases, with a focus (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15. Justice Without Retribution: Interdisciplinary Perspectives, Stakeholder Views and Practical Implications.Farah Focquaert, Gregg Caruso, Elizabeth Shaw & Derk Pereboom - 2018 - Neuroethics 13 (1):1-3.
    Within the United States, the most prominent justification for criminal punishment is retributivism. This retributivist justification for punishment maintains that punishment of a wrongdoer is justified for the reason that she deserves something bad to happen to her just because she has knowingly done wrong—this could include pain, deprivation, or death. For the retributivist, it is the basic desert attached to the criminal’s immoral action alone that provides the justification for punishment. This means that the retributivist position is not reducible (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  16.  18
    Legal knowledge.James Boyd White - unknown
    What do we know when we know the law? Not a set of rules or theories, but a set of practices that are at bottom practices of reading--reading the texts of the law, reading the world--and writing (including of course speaking), especially writing in news ways in the inherited language of the law. Legal knowledge is a writer's knowledge. It always has as one of its deepest themes the question of justice. These themes are explored through an examination of the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17. Legal Insanity and Executive Function.Katrina Sifferd, William Hirstein & Tyler Fagan - 2016 - In Mark D. White (ed.), The Insanity Defense: Multidisciplinary Views on Its History, Trends, and Controversies. Praeger. pp. 215-242.
    In this chapter we will argue that the capacities necessary to moral and legal agency can be understood as executive functions in the brain. Executive functions underwrite both the cognitive and volitional capacities that give agents a fair opportunity to avoid wrongdoing: to recognize their acts as immoral and/or illegal, and to act or refrain from acting based upon this recognition. When a person’s mental illness is serious enough to cause severe disruption of executive functions, she is very likely to (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18.  94
    Mensrea.Jean Hampton - 1990 - Social Philosophy and Policy 7 (2):1.
    Accusing, condemning, and avenging are part of our daily life. However, a review of many years of literature attempting to analyze our blaming practices suggests that we do not understand very well what we are doing when we judge people culpable for a wrong they have committed. Of course, everyone agrees that, for example, someone deserves censure and punishment when she is guilty of a wrong, and the law has traditionally looked for a mens rea, or “guilty mind,” in order (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  19.  27
    Responsibility for Reckless Rape.Katrina Sifferd & Anneli Jefferson - 2022 - Humana Mente - Journal of Philosophical Studies 42 (15):119-143.
    Sometimes persons are legally responsible for reckless behavior that causes criminal harm. This is the case under the newly drafted provisions of the U.S. Model Penal Code (MPC), which holds persons responsible for “simple” rape (nonconsensual sex without proof of force or threats of force), where the offender recklessly disregards the risk that the victim does not consent. In this paper we offer an explanation and corrective critique of the handling of reckless rape cases, with a focus (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  13
    Reckless Beliefs.Larry Alexander & Kevin Cole - 2019 - In Larry Alexander & Kimberly Kessler Ferzan (eds.), The Palgrave Handbook of Applied Ethics and the Criminal Law. Springer Verlag. pp. 651-657.
    Existing and proposed provisions of the Model Penal Code refer to believing something “recklessly.” In this chapter, we examine the notion of reckless beliefs and determine what that notion cannot be and what it might be.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  50
    Tēn Tou Aristou Doxan: On the Theory and Practice of Punishment in Plato’s Laws.Lewis Trelawny-Cassity - 2010 - Polis 27 (2):222-239.
    The penal code of the Laws has attracted scholarly attention because it appears to advance a coherent theory of punishment. The Laws' suggestion that legislation follow the model of 'free doctors', as well as its discussion of the Socratic paradox, leads one to expect a theory of punishment that recommends kolasis and nouthetesis rather than timoria. In practice, however, the Laws makes use of the language of timoria and categorizes some crimes as voluntary. While the Laws provides (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22.  3
    Responsibility.Martin P. Golding - 2004 - In Martin P. Golding & William A. Edmundson (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 221–235.
    This chapter contains section titled: Questions About Responsibility The Holmesian Approach: Objective Liability Aristotle on Voluntary Action and Responsibility The Model Penal Code and Voluntariness Responsibility as a Defeasible Concept: H.L.A. Hart Individual Responsibility: Antony Duff Individual Responsibility: Norrie's Critique of Duff The Abandonment of Responsibility: Wootton The General Rationale of Excuses: H.L.A. Hart Conclusion References Further Reading.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  23.  38
    History’s Challenge to Criminal Law Theory.Darryl Brown - 2009 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 3 (3):271-287.
    After briefly sketching an historical account of criminal law that emphasizes its longstanding reach into social, commercial and personal life outside the core areas of criminal offenses, this paper explores why criminal law theory has never succeeded in limiting the content of criminal codes to offenses that fit the criteria of dominant theories, particularly versions of the harm principle. Early American writers on criminal law endorsed no such limiting principles to criminal law, and early American criminal law consequently was substantively (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Putative Self-defense And Rules Of Imputation. In Defense Of The Battered Woman.B. Byrd - 1994 - Jahrbuch für Recht Und Ethik 2.
    This article attemps to provide a good defense for battered women who kill their sleeping husbands, particularly in cases where it is judged that she was mistaken in her assumption of the need to exercise self-defense. Proceeding from the distinction between the imputation of an act to an actor and the imputation of blame to an actor for criminally prohibited conduct , the article moves on to a discussion of the relevance of mistakes as to justifying circumstances under the criminal (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Morality and the law.Richard A. Wasserstrom - 1971 - Belmont, Calif.,: Wadsworth Pub. Co..
    On liberty, by J. S. Mill.--Morals and the criminal law, by P. Devlin.--Immorality and treason, by H. L. A. Hart.--Lord Devlin and the enforcement of morals, by R. Dworkin.--Sins and crimes, by A. R. Louch.--Morals offenses and the model penal code, L. B. Schwartz.--Paternalism, by G. Dworkin.--Four cases involving the enforcement of morality: Shaw v. Director of Public Prosecutions; People v. Cohen; Repouille v. United States; Commonwealth v. Donoghue.--Bibliography (p. 149).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  26.  19
    The Trial of Joseph Dotterweich: The Origins of the “Responsible Corporate Officer” Doctrine.Craig S. Lerner - 2018 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 12 (3):493-512.
    This article analyzes the origins of the “responsible corporate officer” doctrine: the trial of Joseph Dotterweich. That doctrine holds that an officer may be personally liable for the criminal act of a subordinate if the officer was, in some indefinite way, able to prevent the violation. Applying this doctrine, the prosecution of Dotterweich entailed strict liability for a strict liability offense. The underlying offenses—the interstate sale of one misbranded and adulterated drug and one misbranded drug—were said to be strict liability (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  91
    Empirical Desert, Individual Prevention, and Limiting Retributivism: A Reply.Paul Robinson, Joshua S. Barton & Matthew J. Lister - 2014 - New Criminal Law Review 17 (2):312-375.
    A number of articles and empirical studies over the past decade, most by Paul Robinson and co-authors, have suggested a relationship between the extent of the criminal law's reputation for being just in its distribution of criminal liability and punishment in the eyes of the community – its "moral credibility" – and its ability to gain that community's deference and compliance through a variety of mechanisms that enhance its crime-control effectiveness. This has led to proposals to have criminal liability and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  40
    Untying the gordian knot of mens Rea requirements for accomplices.Heidi M. Hurd & Michael S. Moore - 2016 - Social Philosophy and Policy 32 (2):161-183.
    :This essay undertakes two tasks: first, to describe the differing mens rea requirements for accomplice liability of both Anglo-American common law and the American Law Institute's Model Penal Code; and second, to recommend how the mens rea requirements of both of these two sources of criminal law in America should be amended so as to satisfy the goals of clarity and consistency and so as to more closely conform the criminal law to the requirements of moral blameworthiness. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  7
    The Governing-Law Anchor in Legal Translation-A Homicide Case Study.Slávka Janigová - 2023 - International Journal for the Semiotics of Law - Revue Internationale de Sémiotique Juridique 36 (4):1655-1676.
    The study is aimed to test the governing-law anchor in the comparative analysis of legal terminology to harmonize the clash of legal cultures in legal translation. It is considered as an adjustment to a juritraductological approach to legal translation which invites legal translators to merge the tools of jurilinguistics, comparative law and traductology in the comparative analysis of legal concepts before selecting a suitable translation solution (Monjean-Decaudin, in: Research methods in legal translation and interpreting, Routledge, 2019). Rather than transposing a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  5
    Criminal Theory in the Twentieth Century.George P. Fletcher - 2001 - Theoretical Inquiries in Law 2 (1).
    The theoretical inquiry into the foundations of criminal law in the twentieth century, in both civil and common law traditions, is assayed by the consideration of seven main currents or trends. First, the structure of offenses is examined in light of the bipartite, tripartite, and quadripartite modes of analysis. Second, competing theories of culpability - normative and descriptive - are weighed in connection with their important ramifications for the presumption of proof and the allocation of the burden of persuasion on (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  47
    Yaffe on attempts.Larry Alexander - 2013 - Legal Theory 19 (2):124-135.
    Gideon Yaffe's Attempts is a masterfully executed philosophical investigation of what it means to attempt something. Yaffe is obviously motivated by the fact that the criminal law punishes attempted crimes, and he believes that his philosophical analysis can shed light on and be used to criticize the law's understanding of those crimes. I focus exclusively on the relevance of Yaffe's philosophical analysis of attempts to the criminal law of attempts. I assume that Yaffe's account of what it is to attempt (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  84
    Causing the Conditions of One’s Defense: A Theoretical Non-problem. [REVIEW]Larry Alexander - 2013 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 7 (3):623-628.
    My contribution to this symposium is short and negative: There are no theoretical problems that attach to one’s causing the conditions that permit him to claim a defense to some otherwise criminal act. If one assesses the culpability of an actor at each of the various times he acts in a course of conduct, then it is obvious that he can be nonculpable at T2 but culpable at T1, and that a nonculpable act at T2 has no bearing on whether (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  33.  5
    Polygyny Amongst Muslims in the Russian Federation.Izabela Kończak - 2018 - International Studies. Interdisciplinary Political and Cultural Journal 21 (1):141-155.
    Polygynous families had been living legally in Russia in the areas inhabited by Muslims from the October Revolution to the mid-twentieth century. However, such a family model was not common among the followers of Islam. An act penalizing bigamy or polygamy was introduced into the Penal Code in 1960. During perestroika, and later changes in the political system, imams who came from abroad began to visit areas inhabited by Muslims. They contributed to the rebirth of religion and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Penal Code for India.John Robson - 1990 - In Writings on India. University of Toronto Press. pp. 17-30.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  47
    A draft model aggregated code of ethics for bioethicists.Robert Baker - 2005 - American Journal of Bioethics 5 (5):33 – 41.
    Bioethicists function in an environment in which their peers - healthcare executives, lawyers, nurses, physicians - assert the integrity of their fields through codes of professional ethics. Is it time for bioethics to assert its integrity by developing a code of ethics? Answering in the affirmative, this paper lays out a case by reviewing the historical nature and function of professional codes of ethics. Arguing that professional codes are aggregative enterprises growing in response to a field's historical experiences, it (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  36.  20
    Plato’s Penal Code[REVIEW]Harvey Yunis - 1994 - Ancient Philosophy 14 (1):168-173.
  37. Plato's Penal Code. Tradition, Controversy, and Reform in Greek Penology.Trevor J. Saunders - 1993 - Utopian Studies 4 (1):190-191.
  38. Plato's Penal Code: Tradition, Controversy, and Reform in Greek Penology.J. Saunders Trevor - 1994 - Clarendon Press.
    This is a fascinating and important study of ideas of justice and punishment held by the ancient Greeks. The author traces the development of these ideas from Homer to Plato, analysing in particular the completely radical new system of punishment put forward by Plato in his dialogue the Laws. From traditional Greek ideas of cursing and pollution through to Plato's views on homicide and poisoning by doctors, this enlivening book has a wealth of insights to interest both ancient historians and (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  39. What Can She Know?: Feminist Theory and the Construction of Knowledge.Lorraine Code - 1991 - Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
    In this lively and accessible book Lorraine Code addresses one of the most controversial questions in contemporary theory of knowledge, a question of fundamental concern for feminist theory as well: Is the sex of the knower epistemologically significant? Responding in the affirmative, Code offers a radical alterantive to mainstream philosophy's terms for what counts as knowledge and how it is to be evaluated. Code first reviews the literature of established epistemologies and unmasks the prevailing assumption in Anglo-American (...)
  40.  12
    What Can She Know?: Feminist Theory and the Construction of Knowledge.Lorraine Code - 1991 - Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
    In this lively and accessible book Lorraine Code addresses one of the most controversial questions in contemporary theory of knowledge, a question of fundamental concern for feminist theory as well: Is the sex of the knower epistemologically significant? Responding in the affirmative, Code offers a radical alterantive to mainstream philosophy's terms for what counts as knowledge and how it is to be evaluated. Code first reviews the literature of established epistemologies and unmasks the prevailing assumption in Anglo-American (...)
  41.  21
    Plato’s Penal Code[REVIEW]Harvey Yunis - 1994 - Ancient Philosophy 14 (1):168-173.
  42.  36
    Statutory Disclosure in Article 280 of the Turkish Penal Code.Erhan Büken, Serap Sahinoğlu & Nüket Örnek Büken - 2006 - Nursing Ethics 13 (6):573-580.
    A new Turkish Penal Code came into effect on 1 June 2005. Article 280 concerns health care workers’ failure to report a crime. This article removes the responsibility from health care workers to maintain confidentiality, but also removes patients’ right to confidentiality. It provides for up to one year of imprisonment for a health care worker who, while on duty, finds an indication that a crime might have been committed by a patient and who does not inform the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  14
    Codification of Islamic Criminal Law in the Sudan: Penal Codes and Supreme Court Case Law under Numayrī and al-Bashīr. By Olaf Köndgen.Christina Jones-Pauly - 2022 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 140 (4).
    The Codification of Islamic Criminal Law in the Sudan: Penal Codes and Supreme Court Case Law under Numayrī and al-Bashīr. By Olaf Köndgen. Studies in Islamic Law and Society, vol. 43. Leiden: Brill, 2018. Pp. xii + 480. $171, €149.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  72
    Plato's Theory of Punishment and Penal Code in the Laws.Matthew Adams - 2019 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 97 (1):1-14.
    ABSTRACTI argue that the degree to which a criminal should be punished is determined by three elements: a baseline amount that proportionally compensates the victim and an additional penalty that, first, reforms the criminal and, second, deters others from becoming unjust. My interpretation provides a solution to the interpretive puzzle that has most vexed commentators: the alleged tension between Plato's philosophical theory of punishment and the content of his penal code. I defend a two-step solution to the puzzle. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. What Is Natural about Epistemology Naturalized?Lorraine Code - 1996 - American Philosophical Quarterly 33 (1):1 - 22.
    I evaluate post-Quinean naturalized epistemology as a resource for postcolonial and feminist epistemology. I argue that naturalistic inquiry into material conditions and institutions of knowledge production has most to offer epistemologists committed to maintaining continuity with the knowledge production of specifically located knowers. Yet naturalistic denigrations of folk epistemic practices and stereotyped, hence often oppressive, readings of human nature challenge the naturalness of the nature they claim to study. I outline an ecologically modelled epistemology that focuses on questions of epistemic (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  46.  45
    An Ecology of Epistemic Authority.Lorraine Code - 2011 - Episteme 8 (1):24-37.
    I offer an examination of trust relations in scientific inquiry as they seem to contrast with a lack of trust in an example of knowledge imposed from above by an unaccountable institutional power structure. On this basis I argue for a re-reading of John Hardwig's account of the place of trust in knowledge, and suggest that it translates less well than social epistemologists and others have assumed into a model for democratic epistemic practice.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47.  21
    Plato's Penal Code by Trevor J. Saunders. [REVIEW]John Bussanich - 1993 - Classical World: A Quarterly Journal on Antiquity 86:359-360.
  48.  38
    Commentary on "Loopholes, Gaps, and What is Held Fast".Lorraine Code - 1996 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 3 (4):255-260.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Commentary on “Loopholes, Gaps, and What Is Held Fast”Lorraine Code (bio)Keywordsepistemology, incredulity, knowing other people, memory, testimonyNancy Potter’s compelling essay points to some of the limitations of the theoretical apparatus that the post-positivist empiricist epistemologies of the Anglo-American mainstream make available for evaluating experiential memory claims in general, and “false memory syndrome” in particular. The loopholes and gaps in these theories of knowledge push urgent questions about testimony, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  38
    Solon's Penal Code Eberhard Ruschenbusch: Untersuchungen zur Geschichte des athenischen Strafrechts. (Gräzistische Abhandlungen, 4.) Pp. 96. Cologne and Graz: Böhlau-Verlag, 1968. Paper. DM 18. [REVIEW]P. J. Rhodes - 1970 - The Classical Review 20 (03):358-359.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  41
    Plato on Punishment Trevor J. Saunders: Plato's Penal Code: Tradition, Controversy, and Reform in Greek Penology. Pp. xvii + 414. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991. £50. [REVIEW]Michael Gagarin - 1993 - The Classical Review 43 (01):82-84.
1 — 50 / 991