History’s Challenge to Criminal Law Theory

Criminal Law and Philosophy 3 (3):271-287 (2009)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

After briefly sketching an historical account of criminal law that emphasizes its longstanding reach into social, commercial and personal life outside the core areas of criminal offenses, this paper explores why criminal law theory has never succeeded in limiting the content of criminal codes to offenses that fit the criteria of dominant theories, particularly versions of the harm principle. Early American writers on criminal law endorsed no such limiting principles to criminal law, and early American criminal law consequently was substantively broad. But even with the rise of theories in the mid-nineteenth century that sought to limit criminal law’s reach, codified offenses continued to widely and deeply regulate social life and exceed the limits of those normative arguments. This essay suggests that this practical failure of criminal law theory occurred because it was never adopted by an institutional actor that could limit offense definitions in accord with normative commitments. Legislatures are institutionally unsuited to having their policy actions limited by principled arguments, and courts passed on the opportunity to incorporate a limiting principle for criminal law once they began, in the Lochner era, actively regulating legislative decisions through Constitutional law. The one avenue through which criminal law theory has had some success in affecting criminal codes is through the influence of specialized bodies that influence legislation, especially the American Law Institute advocacy of the Model Penal Code. But the institutional structure of American criminal law policymaking permits an unusually small role for such specialized bodies, and without such an institutional mechanism, criminal law theory is likely to continue to have little effect on actual criminal codes.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 93,069

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

The Wages of Criminal Law Exceptionalism.Alice Ristroph - 2023 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 17 (1):5-15.
Criminal Theory in the Twentieth Century.George P. Fletcher - 2001 - Theoretical Inquiries in Law 2 (1).
Criminal Law Exceptionalism: Introduction.Christoph Burchard & Antony Duff - 2023 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 17 (1):3-4.
Criminal Law Theory: Introduction.Mark Dsouza, Alon Harel & Re’em Segev - 2024 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 18 (2):493-496.
Terrorizing Criminal Law.Lucia Zedner - 2014 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 8 (1):99-121.
Reclamation: A Liberal Theory of Criminal Justice.Lindsey Jo Schwartz - 2023 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 17 (1):247-248.
The Concept of Criminal Law.Sandra G. Mayson - 2020 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 14 (3):447-464.
Criminal law theory.Douglas Husak - 2004 - In Martin P. Golding & William A. Edmundson (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 107–121.

Analytics

Added to PP
2010-09-13

Downloads
38 (#432,849)

6 months
6 (#587,779)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

The moral limits of the criminal law.Joel Feinberg - 1984 - New York: Oxford University Press.
The moral limits of the criminal Law.Joël Feinberg - 1984 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 93 (2):279-279.
General principles of criminal law.Jerome Hall - 1960 - Clark, N.J.: Lawbook Exchange.
Intention, Agency, and Criminal Liability.Michael Corrado - 1992 - Law and Philosophy 11 (3):265-281.

View all 7 references / Add more references