Mensrea

Social Philosophy and Policy 7 (2):1 (1990)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Accusing, condemning, and avenging are part of our daily life. However, a review of many years of literature attempting to analyze our blaming practices suggests that we do not understand very well what we are doing when we judge people culpable for a wrong they have committed. Of course, everyone agrees that, for example, someone deserves censure and punishment when she is guilty of a wrong, and the law has traditionally looked for a mens rea, or “guilty mind,” in order to convict someone of a criminal wrongdoing. But philosophers and legal theorists have found it interestingly difficult to say what mens rea is. For example, noting the way in which we intuitively think people aren't culpable for a crime if they disobey the law by mistake, or under duress, or while insane, theorists such as H.L.A. Hart have tried to define mens rea negatively, as that which an agent has if he is not in what we consider to be an excusing state. But such an approach only circumscribes and does not unravel the central mystery; it also fails to explain why the law recognizes any excusing states as mitigating or absolving one of guilt, much less why all and only the excusing states that are recognized by the law are the right ones. Moreover, the Model Penal Code, which gives a very detailed account of the kinds of mental states which justify criminal conviction, does not tell us why these states of mind are relevant to an assessment of legal guilt

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,672

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Hampton on Forgiveness.Linda Radzik - 2011 - APA Newsletter on Philosophy and Law 10 (2):1-6.
Justice in the family: A defence of feminist contractarianism.Linda Radzik - 2005 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 22 (1):45–54.
Hobbes's state of war.Jean Hampton - 1985 - Topoi 4 (1):47-60.
Hobbes and ethical naturalism.Jean Hampton - 1992 - Philosophical Perspectives 6:333-353.
The Nature of Immorality.Jean Hampton - 1989 - Social Philosophy and Policy 7 (1):22.
Rethinking Reason.Jean Hampton - 1992 - American Philosophical Quarterly 29 (3):219 - 236.
Can We Agree on Morals? [REVIEW]Jean Hampton - 1988 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 18 (2):331-355.
Cooperating and Contracting.Jean Hampton - 1991 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (3):603-609.
The Contractarian Explanation of the State.Jean Hampton - 1990 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 15 (1):344-371.
Review: Can We Agree on Morals? [REVIEW]Jean Hampton - 1988 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 18 (2):331 - 355.
The moral education theory of punishment.Jean Hampton - 1984 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 13 (3):208-238.

Analytics

Added to PP
2010-08-31

Downloads
93 (#183,851)

6 months
15 (#164,417)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Citations of this work

National Insecurity Crime.Josh R. Klein - 2015 - Criminal Justice Ethics 34 (1):1-17.
The Footnote to Athens: Comments on René Foqué.Sandra Marshall - 2008 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 2 (3):235-240.
Constitutionalizing the Harm Principle.Dennis J. Baker - 2008 - Criminal Justice Ethics 27 (2):3-28.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Moral saints.Susan Wolf - 1982 - Journal of Philosophy 79 (8):419-439.
Virtues and Vices.Philippa Foot - 1983 - Noûs 17 (1):117-121.
Culpable ignorance.Holly Smith - 1983 - Philosophical Review 92 (4):543-571.
Religion within the Limits of Reason alone.Immanuel Kant & Theodore M. Greene - 1936 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 43 (1):11-12.
Motivated Irrationality.D. F. Pears & David Pugmire - 1982 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 56 (1):157-196.

View all 8 references / Add more references