Results for 'Ganganatha Santaraksita'

57 found
Order:
  1. The Tattvasangraha of Santaraksita.Santaraksita, Kamalasila & Ganganatha Jha - 1987 - Oriental Institute.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. The Prābhākara school of Pūrva Mīmāmsā.Ganganatha Jha - 1911 - Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  3. Pūrva-mīmā̇msā in its sources.Ganganatha Jha - 1942 - Varanasi,: Banaras Hindu University]. Edited by Umesha[from old catalog] Mishra.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4. Såaòdholåal Lectures on Nyåaya.Ganganatha Jha - 1994
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Shāṅkara Vedānta.Ganganatha Jha - 1939 - [Allahabad,: The Allahabad law journal press, J. K. Sharma, printer.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6. The philosophical discipline.Ganganatha Jha - 1928 - Varanasi: Bharatiya Pub. House.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  4
    The edition of Śāntarakṣita's Vādanyāyaṭīkā collated with the Kundeling manuscript. Śāntarakṣita & Ernst Steinkellner - 2014 - Wien: Arbeitskreis für tibetische und buddhistische Studien, Universität Wien. Edited by Ernst Steinkellner.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  36
    Purva-Mimamsa in its Sources. [REVIEW]K. P. L. & Ganganatha Jha - 1943 - Journal of Philosophy 40 (21):585.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  22
    Yoga darshana. Patañjali, Sir Ganganatha Jha & S. Subrahmanya Sastri - 1934 - Monghyr, Bihar]: Bihar School of Yoga. Edited by Vishnuprasad V. Baxi.
    YO GA-DARSHAN A Sfitras of Patafijali with Bhaisya ofVy:1sa BY Ganganatha Jha he Yoga-darshana includes the Yoga-sfitras ofPataf1jali, and the ancient commentary thereon by Vyasa. The Yoga-sfitras of Patafijali are the classic?...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. The Chāndogyopaniṣad: a treatise on Vedānta philosophy. Saṅkarācārya, Ganganatha Jha & Umesha Mishra (eds.) - 1942 - Poona: Oriental Book Agency.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  19
    The Khaṇdanakhaṇdakhāḍya of Shri-Harṣa: Comprising parichchheda I. Śrīharṣa & Sir Ganganatha Jha - 1911 - Delhi, India: Indian Books Centre. Edited by Ganganatha Jha.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Vādanyāya: vāda-prakriyā kā tārkika viśleshaṇa Gautamīya evaṃ Bauddha nyāya ke sandarbha meṃ.Ram Chandra Pandeya, Mañju, Dharmakirti & Santaraksita - 1988 - Dillī: Īsṭarna Buka Liṅkarsa. Edited by Raghavendra Pandeya, Mañju, Dharmakīrti & Śāntarakṣita.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  34
    The Tattva-kaumudī. Vācaspati Miśra's Commentary on the Sāṁkhya-kārikāThe Tattva-kaumudi. Vacaspati Misra's Commentary on the Samkhya-karika.L. R., M. M. Ganganatha Jha, M. M. Patkar, Vācaspati Miśra & Vacaspati Misra - 1968 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 88 (2):375.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  7
    Self and Personal Identity in Indian Buddhist Scholasticism: A Philosophical Investigation.Matthew Kapstein, Nyayabhasya Vatsyayana, Uddyotakara, Santaraksita & Kamala Sila - 1987 - Umi.
    The topic of this dissertation is one that has been in the forefront of contemporary metaphysics in the Anglo-American philosophical tradition, namely, the problem of personal identity through time. Although we generally believe that we remain the same persons throughout our lives, the answers to questions concerning just what it is that remains the same about us prove to be elusive. Contemporary debate on the subject has its roots in the challenges posed by Locke and Hume to theories which assert (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Śāntarakṣita: Climbing the Ladder to the Ultimate Truth.Allison Aitken - 2023 - In Sara L. McClintock, William Edelglass & Pierre-Julien Harter (eds.), The Routledge handbook of Indian Buddhist philosophy. New York, NY: Routledge, Taylor & Francis Group. pp. 463–379.
    This chapter presents an overview of the life, work, and philosophical contributions of Śāntarakṣita (c. 725–788), who is known for his synthesis of Nāgārjuna’s Madhyamaka with elements of the Dignāga-Dharmakīrti tradition of logic and epistemology. His two most important independent treatises, the Compendium of True Principles (Tattvasaṃgraha) and the Ornament of the Middle Way (Madhyamakālaṃkāra), are characterized by an emphasis on the indispensable role of rational analysis on the Buddhist path as well as serious and systematic engagement with competing Buddhist (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16. Śāntarakṣita and Kamalaśīla on the Sāṃkhyas’ Theory of a Self.James Duerlinger & Emily Waddle - 2014 - Indian International Journal of Buddhist Studies 15:45-77.
    Śāntarakṣita was an important 8th century CE Indian Buddhist philosopher who introduced Indian Buddhism to Tibet and is believed to have created what the Tibetans call the Yogācāra-Svātantrika School of Madhyamaka Indian Buddhism. He composed the "Compendium of Reality" (Tattva¬saṃgraha), which is a comprehensive critical examination of the major Indian philosophical theories of his time. Kamalaśīla was Śāntarakṣita’s eminent disciple who wrote a commentary on the "Compendium of Reality", entitled "Commentary on the Difficult Points of the Compendium of Reality" (Tattva¬saṃgraha¬pañjikā), (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  16
    Śāntarakṣita.James Blumenthal - 2009 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18. Śāntarakṣita and Kamalaśīla on the Jain Theory of Self.James Duerlinger, Siddarth Singh & Landon D. C. Elkind - 2015 - Indian International Journal of Buddhist Studies 16:63-89.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  21
    Śāntarakṣita’s Criticism of Causal Activity.Wenli Fan - 2017 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 45 (5):893-909.
    The term nirvyāpāra, which literally means “non-activity”, can be a key point in understanding Śāntarakṣita’s causal theory. It is a necessary step in his argument for the doctrine of Dependent Origination. This paper presents the views of the orthodox Indian schools that endorses the existence of causal activity and examines how Śāntarakṣita establishes the idea of non-activity mainly by discussing his objection to causal activity. In addition, the paper also briefly investigate the history of the concept of “non-activity” in Buddhist (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  6
    Śāntarakṣita and Kamalaśīla: Life and Teaching.Lev I. Titlin - 2020 - RUDN Journal of Philosophy 24 (4):570-589.
    The article details the biography and teachings of Śāntarakṣita, a famous Buddhist scholar and enlightener, a leading figure in the spread of Buddhism in Tibet and his closest student Kamalaśīla. Śāntarakṣita is the author of several treatises, including Compendium of Entities - Tattvasaṃgraha, a monumental work that can rightfully be called the Buddhist Philosophical Encyclopedia, consisting of 26 sections, in which all key philosophical schools of India, namely: Mīmāṃsa, Vedānta, Sāṃkhya, Yoga, Nyāya, Vaiśeṣika, Lokāyata, Jainism and Buddhism of other sects) (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  41
    Śāntarakṣita on Personal Identity: A Comparative Study.Wenli Fan - 2018 - Philosophy East and West 68 (3):663-682.
    There is a perennial and universal concern about the "self." The question of "who I am" is a necessary step on the path of self-awakening. The Ancient Greek aphorism "know thyself" was inscribed in the forecourt of the Temple of Apollo at Delphi and has been widely praised. Within the philosophical scope of the "self," the problem of personal persistence or personal identity has attracted a great deal of attention and has been discussed extensively in the Western philosophical tradition. The (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22. Consciousness and Causal Emergence: Śāntarakṣita Against Physicalism.Christian Coseru - 2017 - In Jonardon Ganeri (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Indian Philosophy. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 360–378.
    In challenging the physicalist conception of consciousness advanced by Cārvāka materialists such as Bṛhaspati, the Buddhist philosopher Śāntarakṣita addresses a series of key issues about the nature of causality and the basis of cognition. This chapter considers whether causal accounts of generation for material bodies are adequate in explaining how conscious awareness comes to have the structural features and phenomenal properties that it does. Arguments against reductive physicalism, it is claimed, can benefit from an understanding of the structure of phenomenal (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23. Santaraksita on the Fallacies of Personalistic Vitalism.Matthew Kapstein - 1989 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 17 (1):43.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  24.  9
    Dharmakirti, Santaraksita, Kamalasila, and Husserlian Phenomenology: A Question Concerning Compatability.A. J. Vaidya - 2015 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 22 (9-10):46-54.
  25.  6
    Anātmavāda of Śūnyavāda in Śantarakṣita's Tattvasaṃgraha.Seong-Kwan Kim - 2013 - 동서철학연구(Dong Seo Cheol Hak Yeon Gu; Studies in Philosophy East-West) 1 (68):35-58.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. What are Mādhyamikas Refuting? Śāntarakṣita, Kamalaśīla et alii on Superimpositions (samāropa).Tom Tillemans - 2004 - In Musashi Tachikawa, Shoun Hino & Toshihiro Wada (eds.), Three Mountains and Seven Rivers: Prof. Musashi Tachikawa's Felicitation Volume. Motilal Banarsidass Publishers. pp. 225--237.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  27. Studies on Śāntarakṣita’s Yogācāra Madhyamaka.Marie-Louise Friquegnon & Noé Dinnerstein (eds.) - 2012 - Global Scholarly Publications.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  17
    Dual-Aspect Reflexivism in Śāntarakṣita’s Philosophy of Mind.Matthew MacKenzie - 2021 - Journal of Buddhist Philosophy 3:97-120.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  8
    Сommunicative Discourse of Tattvasaṅgrāha by Śāntarakṣita.Vladimir P. Ivanov & Иванов Владимир Павлович - 2024 - RUDN Journal of Philosophy 28 (1):57-68.
    The study provides an insight into the structural features of the famous VIII century Buddhist treatise Tattvasaṅgrāha by Śāntarakṣita with regard to the text’s main purpose ( prayojana ) as it is treated in Kamalaśīla’s commentary Pañjikā. Any text along with its referential (representational) function of conveying message - meaning to the addressee, or its expressive function, reflecting the author's attitude to what is communicated, also performs the ‘appellative’ function, encouraging the recipient of the message to act. This function which (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  15
    Tattvasaṁgraha of Śāntarakṣita, with the Commentary of KamalaśīlaTattvasamgraha of Santaraksita, with the Commentary of Kamalasila.Franklin Edgerton & Embar Krishnamacharya - 1929 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 49:66.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  10
    When Did Svatantra Inference Gain Its Autonomy? Śāntarakṣita and Kamalaśīla as Sources for a Tibetan Distinction.Kevin Vose - 2020 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 48 (4):703-750.
    This article examines Śāntarakṣita’s and Kamalaśīla’s understandings of svatantra and prasaṅga proofs in the attempt to clarify how and why Tibetan Prāsaṅgikas came to portray svatantra inference as an instance of the very thing Madhyamaka rejects. The article proceeds in four parts. A brief comparison of Patsap Nyimadrak’s portrayal of svatantra inference with Bhāviveka’s and Candrakīrti’s employment of this expression shows that Patsap expanded the meaning of it, charging its users with embracing a realism at odds with Madhyamaka emptiness. Patsap’s (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  51
    A Buddhist Theory of Persistence: Śāntarakṣita and Kamalaśīla on Rebirth.Itsuki Hayashi - 2019 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 47 (5):979-1001.
    The so-called Buddhist momentarists, such as Dharmakīrti and his followers, defend the momentariness of all things. However, with equal force they also defend the persistence of all things, not just within a single lifetime but over an indefinite cycle of rebirth. Naturally, they have an interesting theory of persistence, according to which things persist without being self-identical over time. The theory is best presented in the Lokāyatāparīkṣā chapter of Śāntarakṣita’s Tattvasaṃgraha and Kamalaśīla’s Paṅjikā, as they clearly articulate the criteria of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  33.  77
    Is svasaṃvitti transcendental? A tentative reconstruction following Śāntarakṣita.Dan Arnold - 2005 - Asian Philosophy 15 (1):77 – 111.
    There has emerged in recent years the recognition that the characteristically Buddhist doctrine of svasa vitti 2 (‘apperception’, as I will render it for reasons to become clear presently) was vari...
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  34.  7
    Omniscience and the Rhetoric of Reason: Rationality, Argumentation, and Religious Authority in Śāntarakṣita's Tattvasaṅgraha and Kamalaśīla's Pañjikā.Sara L. McClintock - 2010 - Wisdom Publications.
    The great Buddhist writer Santaraksita (725-88) was central to the Buddhist traditions spread into Tibet. He and his disciple Kamalasila were among the most influential thinkers in classical India. They debated ideas not only within the Buddhist tradition but also with exegetes of other Indian religions, and they both traveled and nurtured Buddhism in Tibet during its infancy there. Their views, however, have been notoriously hard to classify. The present volume examines Santaraksita's encyclopedic Tattvasamgraha and Kamalasila's detailed commentary (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  14
    Descriptive Catalogue of Sanskrit Manuscripts in Ganganatha Jha Research Institute, Allahabad.Ernest Bender & Umesha Mishra - 1971 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 91 (1):162.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  35
    Dynamic and Syncretic Dimensions to Śāntarakṣita's Presentation of the Two Truths.James Blumenthal - 2009 - Asian Philosophy 19 (1):51-62.
    It is common for philosophers from the Madhyamaka school of Indian Buddhist thought to offer a presentation of the two truths, ultimate truth ( param rthasatya ) and conventional truth ( sa v tisatya ), as a vehicle for presenting their views on the ontological status of entities. Though there is some degree of variance, generally ultimate truths are described as objects known by an awareness of knowing things as they are. Conventional truths are objects as conceived by a mistaken (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  18
    Cittamātra as Conventional Truth from Śāntarakṣita to Mipham.Jay L. Garfield - 2016 - Journal of Buddhist Philosophy 2:263-280.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  6
    Nichts bleibt Nichts. Der buddhistische Zurückweisung von Kumarilas abhavapramana. Übersetzung und Interpretation von Santaraksitas Tattvasamgraha vv.1647-1690 mit Kamalasilas Tattvasamgrahapanjika. Birgit Kellner. [REVIEW]Chr Lindtner - 1999 - Buddhist Studies Review 16 (1):107-109.
    Nichts bleibt Nichts. Der buddhistische Zurückweisung von Kumarilas abhavapramana. Übersetzung und Interpretation von Santaraksitas Tattvasamgraha vv.1647-1690 mit Kamalasilas Tattvasamgrahapanjika. Birgit Kellner. Vienna 1997. xxxiii, 154 pp. No price/ISBN given.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  33
    Much Ado about Nothing: Kumārila, Śāntarakṣita, and Dharmakīrti on the Cognition of Non-Being. [REVIEW]John Taber - 2001 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 121 (1):72-88.
  40.  28
    Much Ado about Nothing: Kumārila, Śāntarakṣita, and Dharmakīrti on the Cognition of Non-BeingNichts bleibt nichts: Die Buddhistische Zurückweisung von Kumārila's Abhāvapramāṇa; Übersetzung und Interpretation von Śāntarakṣita's Tattvasaṅgraha vv. 1647-1690 mit Kamalaśīla's Tattvasaṅgrahapañjikā sowie Ansätze und Arbeitshypothese zur Geschichte negativer Erkenntnis in der indischen PhilosophieMuch Ado about Nothing: Kumarila, Santaraksita, and Dharmakirti on the Cognition of Non-BeingNichts bleibt nichts: Die Buddhistische Zuruckweisung von Kumarila's Abhavapramana; Ubersetzung und Interpretation von Santaraksita's Tattvasangraha vv. 1647-1690 mit Kamalasila's Tattvasangrahapanjika sowie Ansatze und Arbeitshypothese zur Geschichte negativer Erkenntnis in der indischen Philosophie. [REVIEW]John Taber & Birgit Kellner - 2001 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 121 (1):72.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  41.  37
    Ratnākaraśānti’s Theory of Cognition with False Mental Images and the Neither-One-Nor-Many Argument.Shinya Moriyama - 2014 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 42 (2-3):339-351.
    The paper aims to clarify Ratnākaraśānti?s epistemological theory that mental images in a cognition are false (*alīkākāravāda) in comparison with Śāntarakṣita?s criticism of the Yogācāra position. Although Ratnākaraśānti frequently uses the neither-one-nor-many argument for explaining his Yogācāra position, the argument, unlike Śāntarakṣita?s original one, does not function for refuting the existence of awareness itself as the basis of mental images. This point is examined in the first two sections of this paper by analyzing Ratnākaraśānti?s proof of the selflessness of entities (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  42.  32
    On the Buddha’s Cognition of Other Minds in the Bahirarthaparīkṣā of the Tattvasaṅgraha.Hiroko Matsuoka - 2014 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 42 (2-3):297-307.
    This paper aims at examining the arguments between Śubhagupta (c.720–780) and Śāntarakṣita (c.725–788) over the Buddha’s cognition of other minds and shows how the question of the Buddha’s cognition of other mindsis incorporated into the proof of vijñaptimātratā or “consciousness-only” by Śāntarakṣita. According to Śāntarakṣita, Śubhagupta assumes that the Buddha’s cognition, which is characterized as “the cognition [of the Blessed One] which follows the path of cognition” (aupalambhikadarśana), grasps other minds when the Buddha’s cognition is similar (sārūpya) to other minds. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  37
    Can Flux Bring About Flux? An Appraisal of the Buddhist Momentarist’s Response to the Causal Objection.Itsuki Hayashi - 2017 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 45 (1):49-71.
    The doctrine of radical impermanence expresses the temporal dimension of Buddhist metaphysics, especially in the philosophy of Dharmakīrti and his successors. Most straightforwardly, the doctrine says that everything that exists is momentary; we are not impermanent in the sense that we perish eventually, say when our brain ceases functioning, but rather we perish immediately upon conception. The person who begins to write this sentence and the person who completes it are, strictly speaking, different entities. However, there is a devastating problem (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  24
    Śubhagupta on the Cognitive Process.Margherita Serena Saccone - 2014 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 42 (2-3):377-399.
    In his *Bāhyārthasiddhikārikā (BASK), “Verses on the Establishment of the External Object”—extant only in Tibetan translation—Śubhagupta (720–780 CE), a philosopher connected with the logical-epistemological school of Buddhism, argues the reality of external objects of cognitions. In this article, I shall provide an account of Śubhagupta's theory of the cognitive process, as expressed in BASK 35–44, particularly in light of his view that the images (ākāra) of those objects do not appear in cognition. BASK is part of an internal Buddhist debate (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45.  31
    Kamalaśīla on the Nature of Phenomenal Content (ākāra) in Cognition: A Close Reading of TSP ad TS 3626 and Related Passages.Sara McClintock - 2014 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 42 (2-3):327-337.
    Traditional as well as contemporary interpreters of Indian Yogācāra divide that tradition into a variety of doxographical camps depending on whether awareness is understood tobe endowed with phenomenal content (ākāra) and, if so, whether that content is understood to be real or true. Kamalaśīla’s extensive commentary on his teacher Śāntarakṣita’s Tattvasaṃgraha contains passages that throw into question certain doxographical equivalencies, especially the equivalencies sometimes proposed betweenthe doctrine that awareness is endowed with phenomenal content (sākāravāda) and the doctrine that such content (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  23
    Rhetoric and the Reception Theory of Rationality in the Work of Two Buddhist Philosophers.Sara L. McClintock - 2008 - Argumentation 22 (1):27-41.
    Although rhetoric is not a category of ancient Indian philosophy, this paper argues that Śāntarakṣita and Kamalaśīla, 2 eighth-century Indian Buddhist philosophers, can nonetheless be seen to embrace a rhetorical conception of rationality. That is, while these thinkers are strong proponents of rational analysis and philosophical argumentation as tools for attaining certainty, they also uphold the contingent nature of all such processes. Drawing on the categories of the New Rhetoric, this paper argues that these Buddhist thinkers understand philosophical argumentation to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  47. Animal cognition.Kristin Andrews & Susana Monsó - 2021 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Philosophical attention to animals can be found in a wide range of texts throughout the history of philosophy, including discussions of animal classification in Aristotle and Ibn Bâjja, of animal rationality in Porphyry, Chrysippus, Aquinas and Kant, of mental continuity and the nature of the mental in Dharmakīrti, Telesio, Conway, Descartes, Cavendish, and Voltaire, of animal self-consciousness in Ibn Sina, of understanding what others think and feel in Zhuangzi, of animal emotion in Śāntarakṣita and Bentham, and of human cultural uniqueness (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  48. Reflexivity, Subjectivity, and the Constructed Self: A Buddhist Model.Matthew MacKenzie - 2015 - Asian Philosophy 25 (3):275-292.
    The aim of this article is to take up three closely connected questions. First, does consciousness essentially involve subjectivity? Second, what is the connection, if any, between pre-reflective self-consciousness and subjectivity? And, third, does consciousness necessarily involve an ego or self? I will draw on the Yogācāra–Madhyamaka synthesis of Śāntarakṣita to develop an account of the relation between consciousness, subjectivity, and the self. I will argue, first, that phenomenal consciousness is reflexive or self-illuminating. Second, I will argue that consciousness necessarily (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  49.  30
    Christian Coseru, Perceiving Reality: Consciousness, Intentionality, and Cognition in Buddhist Philosophy. Reviewed by.Rick Repetti - 2015 - Philosophy in Review 35 (4):191-193.
    This work focuses on a narrow Buddhist epistemological tradition that begins with the Abhidharma philosopher Vasubandhu’s analyses of perception and is developed by Dignāga, Dharmakīrti, Kamalaśīla, and Śāntarakṣita. Coseru explains how Buddhist epistemology evolved in dialogue with competing conceptions internal to Buddhism and against orthodox Indian philosophies, particularly Nyāya and Mīmāṃsā. Coseru’s main argument is that although widespread interpretations of Buddhist epistemology are foundationalist, a more useful way to understand it is as a form of phenomenology consistent with enactivism and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  11
    Anti-Realism and Realism About the Past: A Present for Mark Siderits.Arindam Chakrabarti - 2023 - In Christian Coseru (ed.), Reasons and Empty Persons: Mind, Metaphysics, and Morality: Essays in Honor of Mark Siderits. Springer. pp. 283-293.
    Nyāya realists drew an important distinction between absence and non-existence. Perished particulars, such as Aristotle, emperor Ashoka, or the Bamiyan Buddha statues in Afghanistan are absent now but they are not non-existent in the sense of having become unreal or fictional. By dying, my grandmother did not become nonexistent like Snow White, though she suffered post-cessation absence. In order to be really dead, one could aptly remark, she has to be real. Can we therefore be realists about now deceased individuals (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 57