Results for 'Distinguish Recklessness'

967 found
Order:
  1. Rational Capacities, or: How to.Distinguish Recklessness & Michael Smith - 2003 - In Sarah Stroud & Christine Tappolet (eds.), Weakness of will and practical irrationality. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 17.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Rational Capacities, or: How to Distinguish Recklessness, Weakness, and Compulsion.Michael Smith - 2003 - In Sarah Stroud & Christine Tappolet (eds.), Weakness of will and practical irrationality. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 17-38.
    We ordinarily suppose that there is a difference between having and failing to exercise a rational capacity on the one hand, and lacking a rational capacity altogether on the other. This is crucial for our allocations of responsibility. Someone who has but fails to exercise a capacity is responsible for their failure to exercise their capacity, whereas someone who lacks a capacity altogether is not. However, as Gary Watson pointed out in his seminal essay ’Skepticism about Weakness of Will’, the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   130 citations  
  3.  23
    Culpable Carelessness: Recklessness and Negligence in the Criminal Law.Findlay Stark - 2016 - Cambridge University Press.
    The question of when a person is culpable for taking an unjustified risk of harm has long been controversial in Anglo-American criminal law doctrine and theory. This survey of the approaches adopted in England and Wales, Canada, Australia, the United States, New Zealand and Scotland argues that they are converging, to differing extents, around a 'Standard Account' of culpable unjustified risk-taking. This Standard Account distinguishes between awareness-based culpability and inadvertence-based culpability for unjustified risk-taking. With reference to criminal law theory and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  4.  34
    Two Models of Criminal Fault.R. A. Duff - 2019 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 13 (4):643-665.
    I discuss two problems for the standard Anglo-American account of recklessness, and the distinctions between intention, recklessness, and negligence. One problem concerns the over-breadth of recklessness as thus defined—that it covers agents whose actions display different kinds of culpability. The other problem concerns the importance attached to awareness of risk in distinguishing recklessness from negligence—that one who is unaware of the risk that he takes or creates sometimes displays just the same kind of fault as an (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  5. Intellectual courage and inquisitive reasons.Will Fleisher - 2023 - Philosophical Studies 180 (4):1343-1371.
    Intellectual courage requires acting to promote epistemic goods despite significant risk of harm. Courage is distinguished from recklessness and cowardice because the expected epistemic benefit of a courageous action outweighs (in some sense) the threatened harm. Sometimes, however, inquirers pursue theories that are not best supported by their current evidence. For these inquirers, the expected epistemic benefit of their actions cannot be explained by appeal to their evidence alone. The probability of pursuing the true theory cannot contribute enough to (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6. Whistleblowing as civil disobedience.William E. Scheuerman - 2014 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 40 (7):609-628.
    The media hoop-la about Edward Snowden has obscured a less flashy yet more vital – and philosophically relevant – part of the story, namely the moral and political seriousness with which he acted to make the hitherto covert scope and scale of NSA surveillance public knowledge. Here I argue that we should interpret Snowden’s actions as meeting most of the demanding tests outlined in sophisticated political thinking about civil disobedience. Like Thoreau, Gandhi, King and countless other grass-roots activists, Snowden has (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  7.  17
    Prohibited Risks and Culpable Disregard or Inattentiveness: Challenge and Confusion in the Formulation of Risk-Creation Offenses.Paul H. Robinson - 2003 - Theoretical Inquiries in Law 4 (1).
    Because they track the Model Penal Code, current criminal law formulations of risk offenses typically fail to distinguish the rule of conduct question—What risks does the criminal law prohibit?—from the adjudication question — When is a particular violator’s conscious disregard of, or his inattentiveness to, a risk in a particular situation sufficiently condemnable to deserve criminal liability? Instead, the formulations address only the second question — through their definition of reckless and negligent culpability — and fail to provide a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  8.  1
    The Actual Infinite in Aristotle.John King-Farlow - 1988 - The Thomist 52 (3):427-444.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:THE ACTUAL INFINITE IN ARISTOTLE Prolegomena: Philosophy and Theology Related HENEVER PHILOSOPHY is taken to be the handmaiden of theology, then the autonomy of reason is destroyed." Such a daim should be distinguished from a still 1stronger thesis. Compare: " A philosopher may not legitimately try to fortify an argument by bringing in new premises from another discipline which has a special aura of authority." Quite how Aristotle would (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  39
    Promises Schmomises.Heidi M. Hurd - 2017 - Law and Philosophy 36 (3):279-343.
    In this piece, I argue that promises need not be kept just because they were made. This is not to say, however, that unwise, unhappy, and unfortunate promises do not generate obligations. When broken promises will result either in wrongful gains to promisors or wrongful losses to promisees, obligations of corrective justice will demand that such promises be kept if their breach cannot be fully repaired. Thus, when a broken promise will constitute a deliberate loss transfer for personal gain, the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  10.  21
    Slavoj Žižek.Tony Myers - 2003 - New York: Routledge.
    Slavoj Zizek is no ordinary philosopher. Approaching critical theory and psychoanalysis in a recklessly entertaining fashion, Zizek's critical eye alights upon a bewildering and exhilarating range of subjects, from the political apathy of contemporary life, to a joke about the man who thinks he's a chicken, from the ethicial heroism of Keanu Reeves in speed , to what toilet designs reveal about the national psyche. Tony Myers provides a clear and engaging guide to Zizek's key ideas, explaining the main influences (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  11. Collateral Damage and the Principle of Due Care.Anne Schwenkenbecher - 2014 - Journal of Military Ethics 13 (1):94-105.
    This article focuses on the ethical implications of so-called ‘collateral damage’. It develops a moral typology of collateral harm to innocents, which occurs as a side effect of military or quasi-military action. Distinguishing between accidental and incidental collateral damage, it introduces four categories of such damage: negligent, oblivious, knowing and reckless collateral damage. Objecting mainstream versions of the doctrine of double effect, the article argues that in order for any collateral damage to be morally permissible, violent agents must comply with (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  12. The Moral-Conventional Distinction in Mature Moral Competence.Bryce Huebner, James Lee & Marc Hauser - 2010 - Journal of Cognition and Culture 10 (1-2):1-26.
    Developmental psychologists have long argued that the capacity to distinguish moral and conventional transgressions develops across cultures and emerges early in life. Children reliably treat moral transgressions as more wrong, more punishable, independent of structures of authority, and universally applicable. However, previous studies have not yet examined the role of these features in mature moral cognition. Using a battery of adult-appropriate cases (including vehicular and sexual assault, reckless behavior, and violations of etiquette and social contracts) we demonstrate that these (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  13.  11
    The Ethics of Revenge and the Meanings of the Odyssey by Alexander C. Loney.Emily P. Austin - 2022 - American Journal of Philology 143 (3):535-537.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:The Ethics of Revenge and the Meanings of the Odyssey by Alexander C. LoneyEmily P. AustinAlexander C. Loney. The Ethics of Revenge and the Meanings of the Odyssey. New York: Oxford University Press, 2019. Pp. xii +265. Hardcover, $78.00. ISBN 978-0-190-90967-3.The Ethics of Revenge and the Meanings of the Odyssey places Odysseus' climactic act of revenge where it belongs: at the center of our interpretation of the Odyssey. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  16
    Promesses et périls de la nouvelle économie : Fractures dans la société de la connaissance.Adrian Mihalache - 2006 - Hermes 45:69.
    Comprendre les mécanismes sous-jacents de la «nouvelle économie» permet d'augmenter ses chances de gagner au jeu. Un rapide survol des conditions de naissance et de développement de la nouvelle économie montre que le passage de l'économie industrielle à l'économie du savoir a été accompagné par des malentendus similaires à ceux qu'a soulevés l'avènement de l'industrie dans les sociétés agraires. Dans cet article, nous montrons qu'il faut bien distinguer la nouvelle économie, l'économie des services et l'économie du don. Nous évaluons la (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  40
    Dimensions of Negligence in Criminal and Tort Law.Kenneth W. Simons - 2002 - Theoretical Inquiries in Law 3 (2).
    This article explores different dimensions of the concept of negligence in the law. The first sections focus on the fundamental distinction between conduct negligence, a conception that dominates tort law; and cognitive negligence, a conception that is much more important in criminal law. The last major section identifies five significant institutional functions served by a legal negligence standard: expressing a legal norm in the form of a standard rather than a rule; personifying fault; empowering the trier of fact to give (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  16. Willfully Blind for Good Reason.Deborah Hellman - 2009 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 3 (3):301-316.
    Willful blindness is not an appropriate substitute for knowledge in crimes that require a mens rea of knowledge because an actor who contrives his own ignorance is only sometimes as culpable as a knowing actor. This paper begins with the assumption that the classic willfully blind actor—the drug courier—is culpable. If so, any plausible account of willful blindness must provide criteria that find this actor culpable. This paper then offers two limiting cases: a criminal defense lawyer defending a client he (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  17.  52
    Going above and beneath the call of duty: the luck egalitarian claims of healthcare heroes, and the accomodation of professionally-motivated treatment refusal.Thomas Douglas - 2017 - Journal of Medical Ethics 43 (12):801-802.
    In 2014, American doctor Ian Crozier chose to travel to Sierra Leone to help fight the West African Ebola epidemic. He contracted Ebola himself and was evacuated to the US, where he received hospital treatment for 40 days. Crozier knowingly chose to expose himself to a risk of contracting Ebola, and thus appears to be at least somewhat morally responsible for his infection. Did this responsibility weaken his justice-based claim to publicly funded treatment? On one influential view—luck egalitarianism—the answer is (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  16
    Prudence: Classical Virtue, Postmodern Practice (review).Francis A. Beer - 2004 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 37 (2):176-180.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Prudence: Classical Virtue, Postmodern PracticeFrancis A. BeerPrudence: Classical Virtue, Postmodern Practice. Ed. Robert Hariman. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 2003. Pp. xi + 337. $65.00, cloth."Would it be prudent?" The phrase echoes in memory, linking Dana Carvey from Saturday Night Live to the presidency of the first George Bush. Robert Hariman has been wrestling with prudence for over a decade, and he has now produced a powerful (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  13
    Line Drawing in the Dark.Adam J. Kolber - 2021 - Theoretical Inquiries in Law 22 (1):111-136.
    The law inevitably draws lines. These lines distinguish, for example, whether certain conduct reflects ordinary recklessness constituting manslaughter or more extreme recklessness constituting murder. There is no way to meaningfully draw such lines, however, absent shared ways of representing amounts of recklessness or at least knowledge of the consequences of drawing lines in particular places. Yet legal actors frequently draw lines in the dark, establishing cutoffs along a spectrum with little or none of the information required (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  12
    Two types of legal wrongdoing.M. E. Newhouse - 2016 - Legal Theory 22 (1):59-75.
    ABSTRACTThere are two distinct types of legal wrongdoing: civil and criminal. This article demonstrates in three ways that Immanuel Kant's Universal Principle of Right, properly interpreted, offers a plausible and resilient account of this important distinction. First, Kant's principle correctly identifies attempted crimes as crimes themselves even when they do not violate the rights of any individual. Second, it justifies our treatment of reckless endangerment as a crime by distinguishing it from ordinary negligence, traditionally thought to be only civilly wrong. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  49
    Dynamics in Action: Intentional Behavior as a Complex System. [REVIEW]Muhammad Ali Khalidi & Alicia Juarrero - 2001 - Philosophical Review 110 (3):469.
    Action theory has given rise to some perplexing puzzles in the past half century. The most prominent one can be summarized as follows: What distinguishes intentional from unintentional acts? Thanks to the ingenuity of philosophers and their thought experiments, we know better than to assume that the difference lies in the mere presence of an intention, or in its causal efficacy in generating the action. The intention might be present and may also cause the intended behavior, yet the behavior may (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  22.  24
    Medical accountability and the criminal law: New Zealand vs the world.Alexander McCall Smith & Alan Merry - 1996 - Health Care Analysis 4 (1):45-54.
    There can be no disputing the proposition that doctors and nurses should be held accountable for their professional activities. In most circumstances this accountability should be achieved through appropriate and effective complaints and disciplinary procedures, but there will be cases where the criminal law should become involved. The criminal law, however, is a serious weapon, and should only be used to punish those whose conduct is truly criminal; it should not be used against those who have merely made a human (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  33
    Transparency, Values and Trust in Science.Konstantina Antiochou & Stathis Psillos - 2022 - Ruch Filozoficzny 77 (4):73-94.
    Current debates over inductive risk and the role of values in science have largely revolved around the question of the moral responsibilities of scientists: Do scientists have the duty to consider the potential non-epistemic consequences of theories they advocate and, if yes, what values should be taken into account in decision-making? The paper discusses two different – though potentially complementary – responses to this question: a) H. Douglas’s view that scientists should avoid causing reckless or negligent harm to others as (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  10
    Dana S. Scott.Distinguished Guests Frolov - 1989 - In Jens Erik Fenstad, Ivan Timofeevich Frolov & Risto Hilpinen (eds.), Logic, methodology, and philosophy of science VIII: proceedings of the Eighth International Congress of Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science, Moscow, 1987. New York, NY, U.S.A.: Sole distributors for the U.S.A. and Canada, Elsevier Science.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  3
    Rachel Henley, University of Sussex, Palmer, Brighton rachelhe@ biols. susx. ac. uk.Distinguishing Insight From Intuition - 1999 - In Jonathan Shear & Francisco J. Varela (eds.), The view from within: first-person approaches to the study of consciousness. Bowling Green, OH: Imprint Academic.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  7
    about utterances and later, rejected it. In his earlier formulation, he distinguished.Why to Distinguish Performai Ive - 2001 - Indian Philosophical Quarterly 28 (3).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  7
    Religion and Practical Reason: New Essays in the Comparative Philosophy of Religions.Frank Reynolds, David Tracy & Andrew Thomas Greeley and Grace McNichols Greeley Distinguished Service Professor Emeritus of Catholic Studies David Tracy - 1994 - SUNY Press.
    This book contains programmatic essays that focus on broad-ranging proposals for re-envisioning a discipline of comparative philosophy of religions. It also contains a number of case studies focussing on the interpretation of particular religio-historical data from comparatively oriented philosophical perspectives.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28. Animals As Objects, or Subjects, of Rights.Richard A. Epstein, James Parker Hall Distinguished Professor of Law, University of Chicago Law School, Peter, Kirsten Senior Fellow & The Hoover Institution - 2004 - In Cass R. Sunstein & Martha Craven Nussbaum (eds.), Animal rights: current debates and new directions. New York: Oxford University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  29.  15
    Sex and Gender in Medieval and Renaissance Texts: The Latin Tradition.Barbara K. Gold, Barbara H. Gold, Carolina Distinguished Professor of Classics and Comparative Literature Paul Allen Miller, Paul Allen Miller & Charles Platter - 1997 - SUNY Press.
    Examines interrelated topics in Medieval and Renaissance Latin literature: the status of women as writers, the status of women as rhetorical figures, and the status of women in society from the fifth to the early seventeenth century.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Taking Animal Interests Seriously.Gary L. Francione, Professor of Law, Nicholas de B. Katzenbach Distinguished Scholar of Law, Philosophy & Rutgers University School of Law--Newark - 2004 - In Cass R. Sunstein & Martha Craven Nussbaum (eds.), Animal rights: current debates and new directions. New York: Oxford University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Rape, Recklessness, and Sexist Ideology.Elinor Mason - 2021 - In George I. Pavlakos & Veronica Rodriguez-Blanco (eds.), Agency, Negligence and Responsibility. New York, NY, USA: Cambridge University Press.
    Moral responsibility theorists and legal theorists both worry about what negligence is, and how it might be a ground of blameworthiness. In this paper I argue that negligence suitably understood, can be an appropriate grounds for mens rea in rape cases. I am interested in cases where someone continues with sex in the mistaken belief that the other person consents. Such a mistaken belief is often unreasonable: a wilfully blind agent, one who deliberately ignores evidence that there is no consent, (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32. Recklessness and Uncertainty: Jackson Cases and Merely Apparent Asymmetry.Claire Https://Orcidorg Field - 2019 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 16 (4):391-413.
    Is normative uncertainty like factual uncertainty? Should it have the same effects on our actions? Some have thought not. Those who defend an asymmetry between normative and factual uncertainty typically do so as part of the claim that our moral beliefs in general are irrelevant to both the moral value and the moral worth of our actions. Here I use the consideration of Jackson cases to challenge this view, arguing that we can explain away the apparent asymmetries between normative and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  33.  27
    Reckless Enabling.Christopher Cowley - 2020 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 14 (1):51-67.
    The 2016, the UK Supreme Court case of Jogee confirmed a long-standing convention in English law. In cases where D is assisting or encouraging P to commit an offence, D will only be liable as an accessory for that offence if she intentionally assists or encourages P and if she knows the essential features of the offence. In this paper, I discuss and develop some of the arguments from Sanford Kadish’s 1996 article “Reckless Complicity.” I argue that a special sub-category (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  55
    Recklessness, Willful Ignorance, and Exculpation.Michael J. Zimmerman - 2018 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 12 (2):327-339.
    In Ignorance of Law, Douglas Husak’s main thesis is that ignorance of the law typically provides an excuse for breaking the law, but in the case of recklessness he claims that the excuse it provides is only a partial one, and in the case of willful ignorance he claims that it provides no excuse at all. In this paper I argue that, given the general principle to which Husak appeals in order to support his main thesis, he should revise (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  35.  13
    Reckless Beliefs.Larry Alexander & Kevin Cole - 2019 - In Larry Alexander & Kimberly Kessler Ferzan (eds.), The Palgrave Handbook of Applied Ethics and the Criminal Law. Springer Verlag. pp. 651-657.
    Existing and proposed provisions of the Model Penal Code refer to believing something “recklessly.” In this chapter, we examine the notion of reckless beliefs and determine what that notion cannot be and what it might be.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  37
    Recklessness and Circumstances in Criminal Attempts.Di Yang - 2023 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 17 (2):359-380.
    Criminal attempts require intent to commit an offence. But what constitutes such intent? Some cases are fairly straightforward. I act with intent to convert stolen goods if I intend that the goods I purchase be stolen. A man acts with intent to commit rape if he intends that the sexual intercourse be non-consensual. Other cases leave room for reasonable disagreement. Did a man intend to convert criminal property when he purchased goods which he suspected might be stolen? And did a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. The Reasonableness in Recklessness.Findlay Stark - 2020 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 14 (1):9-29.
    Recklessness involves unreasonable/unjustified risk-taking. The argument here is that recklessness in the criminal law is best understood as nevertheless containing an element of reasonableness. To be reckless, on this view, the defendant must reasonably believe that she is exposing others to a risk of harm. If the defendant’s belief about the risk being imposed by her conduct is unreasonable, she should not be considered reckless. This point is most important in relation to offences of endangerment where recklessness (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  38.  21
    Gratuitous risk: danger and recklessness perception of adventure sports participants.Philip A. Ebert, Ian Durbach & Claire Field - 2024 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 51 (2):267-284.
    Since the 1970’s there has been a major increase in adventure sports participation but it seems that engagement in such sports comes with a stigma: adventure sports participants are often regarded as reckless ‘daredevils’. We approach the questions about people’s perception of risk and recklessness in adventure sports by combining empirical research with philosophical analysis. First, we provide empirical evidence that suggests that laypeople tend to assess the danger of adventure sports as greater than more mundane sports and judge (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  99
    “Reckless Inaccuracies Abounding”: André Malraux and the Birth of a Myth.Derek Allan - 2009 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 67 (2):147-158..
    After an initial period of popularity in the 1960s and 1970s, André Malraux’s works on the theory of art, "The Voices of Silence" and "The Metamorphosis of the Gods", lapsed into relative obscurity. A major factor in this fall from grace was the frosty reception given to these works by a number of leading art historians, including E.H. Gombrich, who accused Malraux of an irresponsible approach to art history and of "reckless inaccuracies". This essay examines a representative sample of the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  28
    Recklessness Without the Risk.David Prendergast - 2020 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 14 (1):31-50.
    Risk is at the core of criminal recklessness, but its exact constitution comes into focus only in unusual cases. In rethinking criminal law, Larry Alexander and Kimberley Kessler Ferzan say that risk in criminal recklessness ought to be constituted by the subjective belief of the person whose action is being evaluated: the gravity of the harm risked and its probability of resulting is what the person believed it to be, not what it actually was. This means that (...) can be found in the absence of any “real” risk. This article critiques the authors’ argument for subjective risk in recklessness. They exaggerate the arbitrariness in identifying risk non-subjectively and do not sufficiently acknowledge risk as an inter-subjectively constituted practical concept. Fixing risk subjectively, as advocated by the authors, nonetheless may appear useful for inchoate criminal liability. The article considers and rejects this idea of occasionally subjectivising risk in recklessness. (shrink)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  8
    Recklessness Without the Risk.David Prendergast - 2020 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 14 (1):31-50.
    Risk is at the core of criminal recklessness, but its exact constitution comes into focus only in unusual cases. In rethinking criminal law, Larry Alexander and Kimberley Kessler Ferzan say that risk in criminal recklessness ought to be constituted by the subjective belief of the person whose action is being evaluated: the gravity of the harm risked and its probability of resulting is what the person believed it to be, not what it actually was. This means that (...) can be found in the absence of any “real” risk. This article critiques the authors’ argument for subjective risk in recklessness. They exaggerate the arbitrariness in identifying risk non-subjectively and do not sufficiently acknowledge risk as an inter-subjectively constituted practical concept. Fixing risk subjectively, as advocated by the authors, nonetheless may appear useful for inchoate criminal liability. The article considers and rejects this idea of occasionally subjectivising risk in recklessness. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  6
    Reckless Minds or Democracy's Helpers? Intellectuals and Politics in the Twentieth Century.Michael Kenny - 2004 - Contemporary Political Theory 3 (1):89-103.
  43.  27
    Responsibility for Reckless Rape.Katrina Sifferd & Anneli Jefferson - 2022 - Humana Mente - Journal of Philosophical Studies 42 (15):119-143.
    Sometimes persons are legally responsible for reckless behavior that causes criminal harm. This is the case under the newly drafted provisions of the U.S. Model Penal Code (MPC), which holds persons responsible for “simple” rape (nonconsensual sex without proof of force or threats of force), where the offender recklessly disregards the risk that the victim does not consent. In this paper we offer an explanation and corrective critique of the handling of reckless rape cases, with a focus on the U.S. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  48
    Recklessness.James B. Brady - 1996 - Law and Philosophy 15 (2):183 - 200.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45. Gallipoli: Reckless Valour [Book Review].Tracey Schmidt - 2010 - Agora (History Teachers' Association of Victoria) 45 (4):62.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Reckless or pioneering? Public health genetics services in Israel.Aviad E. Raz - 2018 - In Hagai Boas, Shai Joshua Lavi, Yael Hashiloni-Dolev, Dani Filc & Nadav Davidovitch (eds.), Bioethics and biopolitics in Israel: socio-legal, political and empirical analysis. Cambridge, United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Recklessness and the Duty to Take Care.Victor Tadros - 2002 - In Stephen Shute & Andrew Simester (eds.), Criminal law theory: doctrines of the general part. New York: Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  28
    Recklessness, Agent-Relative Prerogatives, and Latent Obligations: Does Belief-Relativity Trump Fact-Relativity with Respect to Our Rights?Larry Alexander - 2023 - Philosophia 51 (5):2639-2655.
    Are our rights—to our bodily integrity, to our possessions, to the goods and services promised us, and so on—matters of fact, or are our rights functions of others’ beliefs about how their acts will affect our rights? The conventional view states that subjective oughts—based on what we believe—determine culpability, whereas objective oughts—based on the facts—determine permissibility. After all, the idea that our beliefs about how our acts would affect others’ rights might affect the contours of those rights themselves appears deeply (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  42
    Special Issue on Recklessness and Negligence.Christopher Cowley & Beatrice Krebs - 2020 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 14 (1):5-8.
    This paper introduces the Special Issue on Recklessness and Negligence. It highlights the main issues and controversies that surround these concepts and then briefly introduces each of the papers that comprise the Special Issue.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Reckless trials? the criminalization of the sexual transmission of HIV.Daniel Monk, Helen Reece, C. Hunt, Tim Reynolds, H. Rishi, A. Buzian, E. Hill, G. Barker, Matthew Weait & J. Lazarus - 2009 - Radical Philosophy 156:2-6.
1 — 50 / 967