Results for 'Conditional Predications'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  51
    Conditionals, Predicates and Probability.Brian Weatherson - manuscript
    Ernest Adams has claimed that a probabilistic account of validity gives the best account of our intuitive judgements about the validity of arguments. In particular, he claims, it has the best hope of accounting for our judgements about many arguments involving conditionals. Most of the examples in the literature on this topic have been arguments framed in the language of propositional logic. I show that once we consider arguments involving predicates and involving identity, Adams’s strategy is less successful.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Jacques Jayez and Lucia M. tovena/free choiceness and non-individuation 1–71 Michael McCord and Arendse bernth/a metalogical theory of natural language semantics 73–116 Nathan salmon/are general terms rigid? 117–134. [REVIEW]Stefan Kaufmann, Conditional Predications, Yoad Winter & Cross-Categorial Restrictions On Measure - 2005 - Linguistics and Philosophy 28:791-792.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3. Chomskyan Arguments Against Truth-Conditional Semantics Based on Variability and Co-predication.Agustín Vicente - 2021 - Erkenntnis 86 (4):919-940.
    In this paper I try to show that semantics can explain word-to-world relations and that sentences can have meanings that determine truth-conditions. Critics like Chomsky typically maintain that only speakers denote, i.e., only speakers, by using words in one way or another, represent entities or events in the world. However, according to their view, individual acts of denotations are not explained just by virtue of speakers’ semantic knowledge. Against this view, I will hold that, in the typical cases considered, semantic (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  4.  53
    Derivability conditions on Rosser's provability predicates.Toshiyasu Arai - 1990 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 31 (4):487-497.
  5.  14
    Conditionals and Egocentric Mental Predicates.A. Boguslawski - 1998 - Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 62:29-38.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Indexical Color Predicates: Truth Conditional Semantics vs. Truth Conditional Pragmatics.Lenny Clapp - 2012 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 42 (2):71-100.
    Truth conditional semantics is the project of ‘determining a way of assigning truth conditions to sentences based on A) the extension of their constituents and B) their syntactic mode of combination’. This research program has been subject to objections that take the form of underdetermination arguments, an influential instance of which is presented by Travis: … consider the words ‘The leaf is green,’ speaking of a given leaf, and its condition at a given time, used so as to mean (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  7. Modal logic with subjunctive conditionals and dispositional predicates.Lennart Åqvist - 1973 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 2 (1):1 - 76.
  8.  36
    Minimal Predicates. Fixed-Points, and Definability.Johan Van Benthem - 2005 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 70 (3):696 - 712.
    Minimal predicates P satisfying a given first-order description ϕ(P) occur widely in mathematical logic and computer science. We give an explicit first-order syntax for special first-order 'PIA conditions' ϕ(P) which quarantees unique existence of such minimal predicates. Our main technical result is a preservation theorem showing PIA-conditions to be expressively complete for all those first-order formulas that are preserved under a natural model-theoretic operation of 'predicate intersection'. Next, we show how iterated predicate minimization on PIA-conditions yields a language MIN(FO) equal (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  9. Indexical Predicates.Daniel Rothschild & Gabriel Segal - 2009 - Mind and Language 24 (4):467-493.
    We discuss the challenge to truth-conditional semantics presented by apparent shifts in extension of predicates such as ‘red’. We propose an explicit indexical semantics for ‘red’ and argue that our account is preferable to the alternatives on conceptual and empirical grounds.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  10.  41
    A predicate logical extension of a subintuitionistic propositional logic.Ernst Zimmermann - 2002 - Studia Logica 72 (3):401-410.
    We develop a predicate logical extension of a subintuitionistic propositional logic. Therefore a Hilbert type calculus and a Kripke type model are given. The propositional logic is formulated to axiomatize the idea of strategic weakening of Kripke''s semantic for intuitionistic logic: dropping the semantical condition of heredity or persistence leads to a nonmonotonic model. On the syntactic side this leads to a certain restriction imposed on the deduction theorem. By means of a Henkin argument strong completeness is proved making use (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  11. Predication as Ascription.David Liebesman - 2015 - Mind 124 (494):517-569.
    I articulate and defend a necessary and sufficient condition for predication. The condition is that a term or term-occurrence stands in the relation of ascription to its designatum, ascription being a fundamental semantic relation that differs from reference. This view has dramatically different semantic consequences from its alternatives. After outlining the alternatives, I draw out these consequences and show how they favour the ascription view. I then develop the view and elicit a number of its virtues.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  12.  40
    Minimal predicates, fixed-points, and definability.Johan van Benthem - 2005 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 70 (3):696-712.
    Minimal predicates P satisfying a given first-order description φ(P) occur widely in mathematical logic and computer science. We give an explicit first-order syntax for special first-order ‘PIA conditions’ φ(P) which guarantees unique existence of such minimal predicates. Our main technical result is a preservation theorem showing PIA-conditions to be expressively complete for all those first-order formulas that are preserved under a natural model-theoretic operation of ‘predicate intersection’. Next, we show how iterated predicate minimization on PIA-conditions yields a language MIN(FO) equal (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  13. Church-Rosser Property for Conditional Rewriting Systems with Built-in Predicates as Premises.Mauricio Ayala-Rincon - 2000 - In Dov M. Gabbay & Maarten de Rijke (eds.), Frontiers of combining systems 2. Philadelphia, PA: Research Studies Press. pp. 2--17.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  33
    Predicate Logical Extensions of some Subintuitionistic Logics.Ernst Zimmermann - 2009 - Studia Logica 91 (1):131-138.
    The paper presents predicate logical extensions of some subintuitionistic logics. Subintuitionistic logics result if conditions of the accessibility relation in Kripke models for intuitionistic logic are dropped. The accessibility relation which interprets implication in models for the propositional base subintuitionistic logic considered here is neither persistent on atoms, nor reflexive, nor transitive. Strongly complete predicate logical extensions are modeled with a second accessibility relation, which is a partial order, for the interpretation of the universal quantifier.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  26
    Predication and cognitive context: Between minimalism and contextualism.Sandro Balletta & Filippo Domaneschi - 2019 - Ratio 32 (3):182-191.
    In this paper, we suggest a strategy for modelling cognitive context within a truth‐conditional semantics, using Asher's model of predication. This allows us to introduce the notion of type presupposition intended as a lexical constraint to the composition of the truth‐conditional content. More specifically, we suggest that this model of predication produces a notion of truth‐conditional meaning where the cognitive context fixes a set of lexical restrictions and forced modifications. We conclude that this model might offer an (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. Individual and stage-level predicates of personal taste: another argument for genericity as the source of faultless disagreement.Hazel Pearson - 2022 - In Jeremy Wyatt, Julia Zakkou & Dan Zeman (eds.), Perspectives on Taste: Aesthetics, Language, Metaphysics, and Experimental Philosophy. Routledge.
    This chapter compares simple predicates of personal taste (PPTs) such as tasty and beautiful with their complex counterparts (eg tastes good, looks beautiful). I argue that the former differ from the latter along two dimensions. Firstly, simple PPTs are individual-level predicates, whereas complex ones are stage-level. Secondly, covert Experiencer arguments of simple PPTs obligatorily receive a generic interpretation; by contrast, the covert Experiencer of a complex PPT can receive a generic, bound variable or referential interpretation. I provide an analysis of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  17.  98
    Predicates in perspective.Anthony Corsentino - 2012 - Synthese 187 (2):519-545.
    A familiar strategy of argument to the effect that natural-language predicates are semantically context dependent rests on constructing what I term Travis cases: different contexts for the use of a predicate are imagined in which its semantic (typically, truth-conditional) properties are claimed to differ. I propose an account of the semantic properties of predicates that give rise to Travis cases; I then argue that the account underwrites a genuine alternative to the standard explanations of Travis cases to be found (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18. The semantics of mass-predicates.Kathrin Koslicki - 1999 - Noûs 33 (1):46-91.
    Along with many other languages, English has a relatively straightforward grammatical distinction between mass-occurrences of nouns and their countoccurrences. As the mass-count distinction, in my view, is best drawn between occurrences of expressions, rather than expressions themselves, it becomes important that there be some rule-governed way of classifying a given noun-occurrence into mass or count. The project of classifying noun-occurrences is the topic of Section II of this paper. Section III, the remainder of the paper, concerns the semantic differences between (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  19. On the logic of nonmonotonic conditionals and conditional probabilities: Predicate logic. [REVIEW]James Hawthorne - 1998 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 27 (1):1-34.
    In a previous paper I described a range of nonmonotonic conditionals that behave like conditional probability functions at various levels of probabilistic support. These conditionals were defined as semantic relations on an object language for sentential logic. In this paper I extend the most prominent family of these conditionals to a language for predicate logic. My approach to quantifiers is closely related to Hartry Field's probabilistic semantics. Along the way I will show how Field's semantics differs from a substitutional (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  20. Possible predicates and actual properties.Roy T. Cook - 2019 - Synthese 196 (7):2555-2582.
    In “Properties and the Interpretation of Second-Order Logic” Bob Hale develops and defends a deflationary conception of properties where a property with particular satisfaction conditions actually exists if and only if it is possible that a predicate with those same satisfaction conditions exists. He argues further that, since our languages are finitary, there are at most countably infinitely many properties and, as a result, the account fails to underwrite the standard semantics for second-order logic. Here a more lenient version of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  21.  85
    Complex Predication and the Metaphysics of Properties.Bryan Pickel - 2014 - Dialectica 68 (2):209-230.
    The existence of complex predicates seems to support an abundant conception of properties. Specifically, the application conditions for complex predicates seem to be explained by the distribution of a sparser base of predicates. This explanatory link might suggest that the existence and distribution of properties expressed by complex predicates are explained by the existence and distribution of a sparser base of properties. Thus, complex predicates seem to legitimize the assumption of a wide array of properties. The additional properties are no (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  60
    Predicate Logics of Constructive Arithmetical Theories.Albert Visser - 2006 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 71 (4):1311 - 1326.
    In this paper, we show that the predicate logics of consistent extensions of Heyting's Arithmetic plus Church's Thesis with uniqueness condition are complete $\Pi _{2}^{0}$. Similarly, we show that the predicate logic of HA*, i.e. Heyting's Arithmetic plus the Completeness Principle (for HA*) is complete $\Pi _{2}^{0}$. These results extend the known results due to Valery Plisko. To prove the results we adapt Plisko's method to use Tennenbaum's Theorem to prove 'categoricity of interpretations' under certain assumptions.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  3
    Categorial predication.E. J. Lowe - 2013 - In David S. Oderberg (ed.), Classifying Reality. Hoboken: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 5–22.
    When, for example, we say of something that it ‘is an object’, or ‘is an event’, or ‘is a property’, we are engaging in categorial predication: we are assigning something to a certain ontological category. Ontologicalcategorization is clearly a type of classification, but it differs radically from the types of classification that are involved in thetaxonomic practices of empirical sciences, as when a physicist saysof a certain particle that it ‘is an electron’, or when a zoologist saysof a certain animal (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  78
    Plural Predication and the Strongest Meaning Hypothesis.Yoad Winter - 2001 - Journal of Semantics 18 (4):333-365.
    The Strongest Meaning Hypothesis of Dalrymple et al (1994,1998), which was originally proposed as a principle for the interpretation of reciprocals, is extended in this paper into a general principle of plural predication. This principle applies to complex predicates that are composed of lexical predicates that hold of atomic entities, and determines the pluralities in the extension of the predicate. The meaning of such a complex predicate is claimed to be the truth-conditionally strongest meaning that does not contradict lexical properties (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  25.  94
    Temporal predication with temporal parts and temporal counterparts.Thomas Sattig - 2003 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 81 (3):355 – 368.
    If ordinary objects have temporal parts, then temporal predications have the following truth conditions: necessarily, ( a is F) at t iff a has a temporal part that is located at t and that is F. If ordinary objects have temporal counterparts, then, necessarily, ( a is F) at t iff a has a temporal counterpart that is located at t and that is F. The temporal-parts account allows temporal predication to be closed under the parthood relation: since all (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  26.  37
    Predicate modifiers in tense logic.J. Butterfield - 1987 - Logique Et Analyse 30 (17):31.
    We explain two ways of revising a tense logic like kripke's (1963) modal logic by adding predicate modifiers. first we show that modifiers allow us to render valid some mixing formulas--conditionals reversing the order of a quantifier and an operator--within a complete bivalent system. then we show how modifiers enable a tense logic to give analyses close to the surface form for sentences with temporal qualifications of singular terms, e.g., 'toby was fatter then than william is today'.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  27. Categorial predication.E. J. Lowe - 2012 - Ratio 25 (4):369-386.
    When, for example, we say of something that it ‘is an object’, or ‘is an event’, or ‘is a property’, we are engaging in categorial predication: we are assigning something to a certain ontological category. Ontological categorization is clearly a type of classification, but it differs radically from the types of classification that are involved in the taxonomic practices of empirical sciences, as when a physicist says of a certain particle that it ‘is an electron’, or when a zoologist says (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  28.  40
    Comments on Predicative Logic.Fernando Ferreira - 2006 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 35 (1):1-8.
    We show how to interpret intuitionistic propositional logic into a predicative second-order intuitionistic propositional system having only the conditional and the universal second-order quantifier. We comment on this fact. We argue that it supports the legitimacy of using classical logic in a predicative setting, even though the philosophical cast of predicativism is nonrealistic. We also note that the absence of disjunction and existential quantifications allows one to have a process of normalization of proofs that avoids the use of "commuting (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  29.  2
    On Predicating a Diagnosis as an Attribute of a Person.Douglas W. Maynard - 2004 - Discourse Studies 6 (1):53-76.
    This article explores the relation between ‘citing the evidence’, or implicating a particular diagnosis, and ‘asserting the condition’, or overtly predicating the diagnosis as an attribute of a person. Clinicians regularly postpone or delay asserting the condition, which is interactionally more confrontational and presumptive. They regularly do the postponement by citing the evidence prior to asserting the condition, using the evidence as kind of predecessor account for predicating the diagnosis as an attribute of the person. Citing the evidence as leading (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  30. The Completeness of Some Modal Logics with Circumstantials, Subjunctive Conditionals, Transworld Identity and Dispositional Predicates a Study in the Prolegomena to the Logic of Science.Lennart Åqvist - 1971 - Uppsala Universitet].
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. The completeness of some modal logics with circumstantials, subjunctive conditionals, transworld identity and dispositional predicates.Lennart Åqvist - 1971 - [Uppsala,: Uppsala universitet].
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  18
    Predicates of personal taste and normative meaning.Marián Zouhar - 2022 - Synthese 200 (6).
    The main aim of the paper is to reject the idea that predicates of personal taste express normative meanings. According to a recent theory proposed by Daniel Gutzmann, predicates of personal taste express both a truth-conditional content and a use-conditional content, the latter being normative. The purported normativity of predicates of personal taste is supposed to consist in that when producing utterances containing such predicates, their speakers suggest how other people ought to experience the objects of taste under (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  37
    Predicative Names.Pierre Baumann - 2018 - Cadernos Do Pet Filosofia 9 (18):95-108.
    This paper argues that proper names may have literal non-referential truth-conditional values, thereby undermining the notion of semantic reference.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  56
    Meinongian extensions of predicates.Anna Sierszulska - 2005 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 14 (2):145-163.
    The paper analyses the contemporary notion of an extension of apredicate from the perspective of semantics typical for Meinongian logics, andin opposition to the traditional notion of extension. This leads to a discussionof the types of properties that can be predicated about objects as belonging tothe sets of properties ascribed to them, and such that can be predicated aboutthem only ‘externally’. It is also problematic in which sense nonexistentobjects possess the properties ascribed to them. The concluding remarksconcern some issues related (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. That-clauses in attitude predicates: Giving syntax its due.Robert J. Matthews - 2020 - Theoretical Linguistics 46 (3-4):289-245.
    Abstract: In this brief commentary, I focus on two issues, first on Moltmann’s proposed Davidsonian event semantics for transitive verb attitude predicates, and second on the import of what she calls ‘the underspecification of content’ for the proper semantic interpretation of that-clauses. With respect to the first of these issues, I question the empirical justification of her proposed semantics, suggesting that she needs a syntactic rationale for her semantics. With respect to the second issue, I question whether, as she claims, (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  23
    Geach, Aristotle and Predicate Logics.Alex Orenstein - 2015 - Philosophical Investigations 38 (1-2):96-114.
    Geach's account of the Aristotelian logic of categorical sentences supplemented the views shared by Frege, Russell, Quine and others. I argue that this particular predicate logic approach and Geach's points apply to only one variety of natural language categorical sentences. For example, it takes the universal categorical as a universal conditional “If anything is a man, then it is mortal”. A different natural language form can and should be invoked: “Every man is a mortal.” Employing special restricted quantifiers in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37. What Tipper is Ready for: A Semantics for Incomplete Predicates.Christopher Gauker - 2012 - Noûs 46 (1):61-85.
    This paper presents a precise semantics for incomplete predicates such as “ready”. Incomplete predicates have distinctive logical properties that a semantic theory needs to accommodate. For instance, “Tipper is ready” logically implies “Tipper is ready for something”, but “Tipper is ready for something” does not imply “Tipper is ready”. It is shown that several approaches to the semantics of incomplete predicates fail to accommodate these logical properties. The account offered here defines contexts as structures containing an element called a proposition (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  38.  50
    Goodness: Attributive and predicative.Michael-John Turp - 2016 - Les ateliers de l'éthique/The Ethics Forum 11 (2-3):70-87.
    Michael-John Turp | : There is little consensus concerning the truth or reference conditions for evaluative terms such as “good” and “bad.” In his paper “Good and Evil,” Geach proposed that we distinguish between attributive and predicative uses of “good.” Foot, Thomson, Kraut, and others have put this distinction to use when discussing basic questions of value theory. In §§1-2, I outline Geach’s proposal and argue that attributive evaluation depends on a prior grasp of the kind of thing that is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. Leibniz on Natural Predication.Ezio Vailati - 1985 - Dissertation, University of California, San Diego
    The central focus of my dissertation is the study of the naturality in Leibniz's philosophy. Leibniz makes a number of statements concerning natural predication, including: the soul is naturally immortal; personal identity naturally presupposes the identity of the soul; reflective apperception cannot naturally deceive; matter cannot naturally think or act at a distance. These claims are not only central to Leibniz's philosophy of mind, but to his system as a whole; moreover, some of them constitute the basis of his criticism (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  10
    Enriching a predicate and tame expansions of the integers.Gabriel Conant, Christian D’Elbée, Yatir Halevi, Léo Jimenez & Silvain Rideau-Kikuchi - forthcoming - Journal of Mathematical Logic.
    Journal of Mathematical Logic, Ahead of Print. Given a structure [math] and a stably embedded [math]-definable set [math], we prove tameness preservation results when enriching the induced structure on [math] by some further structure [math]. In particular, we show that if [math] and [math] are stable (respectively, superstable, [math]-stable), then so is the theory [math] of the enrichment of [math] by [math]. Assuming simplicity of [math], elimination of hyperimaginaries and a further condition on [math] related to the behavior of algebraic (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41. Temporal parts and complex predicates.Thomas Sattig - 2002 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 102 (3):279–286.
    Those who believe that ordinary things have temporal as well as spatial parts must give an account of the truth conditions of temporally modified predications of the form ‘a is F at t ’ in terms of temporal parts. I will argue that the friend of temporal parts is committed to an account of temporal predication that is incompatible with the classical principle of predicate abstraction.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  42.  23
    Truth Conditions and Behaviourism.Kai Michael Büttner - 2015 - Polish Journal of Philosophy 9 (2):41-57.
    Quine tries to combine truth conditional semantics with linguistic behaviourism. To this end, he identifies the truth conditions of a sentence with the conditions that prompt speakers to assign truth or falsity to the sentence. The first problem with this conception is that truth conditions determine not when truth-value assignments are made, but when they are correct. This fact vitiates Quine’s account of observation sentences (section 2). A second difficulty pertains only to theoretical sentences. The correctness of truth-value assignments (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. Denied Conditionals Are Not Negated Conditionals.Joseph Fulda - 1995 - Sorites 2:45-45.
    This note addresses the problems that arise from denying conditionals in classical logic and concludes that such problems result from using propositional logic where predicate logic with quantification over cases is indicated.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  49
    Polarity in Natural Language: Predication, Quantification and Negation in Particular and Characterizing Sentences.Sebastian Löbner - 2000 - Linguistics and Philosophy 23 (3):213-308.
    The present paper is an attempt at the investigation of the nature of polarity contrast in natural languages. Truth conditions for natural language sentences are incomplete unless they include a proper definition of the conditions under which they are false. It is argued that the tertium non datur principle of classical bivalent logical systems is empirically invalid for natural languages: falsity cannot be equated with non-truth. Lacking a direct intuition about the conditions under which a sentence is false, we need (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  45.  29
    Hermann Dishkant. The first order predicate calculus based on the logic of quantum mechanics. Reports on mathematical logic, no. 3 , pp. 9–17. - G. N. Georgacarakos. Orthomodularity and relevance. Journal of philosophical logic, vol. 8 , pp. 415–432. - G. N. Georgacarakos. Equationally definable implication algebras for orthomodular lattices. Studia logica, vol. 39 , pp. 5–18. - R. J. Greechie and S. P. Gudder. Is a quantum logic a logic?Helvetica physica acta, vol. 44 , pp. 238–240. - Gary M. Hardegree. The conditional in abstract and concrete quantum logic. The logico-algehraic approach to quantum mechanics, volume II, Contemporary consolidation, edited by C. A. Hooker, The University of Western Ontario series in philosophy of science, vol. 5, D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Boston, and London, 1979, pp. 49–108. - Gary M. Hardegree. Material implication in orthomodular lattices. Notre Dame journal of formal logic, vol. 22 , pp. 163–182. - J. M. Jauch and C. Piron. What is “q. [REVIEW]Alasdair Urquhart - 1983 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 48 (1):206-208.
  46. Truth-conditions and the nature of truth: Re-solving mixed conjunctions.Douglas Edwards - 2009 - Analysis 69 (4):684-688.
    Alethic pluralism, on one version of the view , is the idea that truth is to be identified with different properties in different domains of discourse. 1 Whilst we operate with a univocal concept of truth, and a uniform truth predicate, the thought is that the truth property changes from one domain to the next. So the truth property for talk about the nature and state of the material world may be different from the truth property for moral discourse .Tappolet (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  47.  13
    Are thick aesthetic predicates assessment-sensitive?Ramiro Caso & Eleonora Orlando - 2024 - Synthese 203 (4):1-30.
    The aim of the paper is to evaluate the prospects for an aesthetically informed assessment-sensitive semantic account of thick aesthetic predicates (TAPs) such as 'intense', 'sombre', ‘balanced’, ‘harmonious’, etc. We distinguish two meaning dimensions concerning TAPs, truth-conditional and use-conditional or expressive, and provide a dualist semantics that posits assessment sensitivity at both levels. Then we evaluate the extent to which assessment sensitivity is an apt rendition of aesthetic discourse involving TAPs. We distinguish between experiential TAPs (‘intense’, ‘sombre’) and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Plato, Sophist 259C7–D7: Contrary Predication and Genuine Refutation.John D. Proios - 2023 - Classical Quarterly 73 (1):66-77.
    This paper defends an interpretation of Plato, Soph. 259c7–d7, which describes a distinction between genuine and pretender forms of ‘examination’ or ‘refutation’ (ἔλεγχος). The passage speaks to a need, throughout the dialogue, to differentiate the truly philosophical method from the merely eristic method. But its contribution has been obscured by the appearance of a textual problem at 259c7–8. As a result, scholars have largely not recognized that the Eleatic Stranger recommends accepting contrary predication as a condition of genuine refutation. After (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  47
    Assertability conditions of epistemic (and fictional) attitudes and mood variation.Mari Alda - unknown - Proceedings of SALT 26.
    Italian is a well-known exception to the cross-linguistic generalization according to which `belief' predicates are indicative selectors across languages. We newly propose that languages that select the subjunctive with epistemic predicates allow us to see a systematic polysemy between what we call an expressive-`belief' (featuring only a doxastic dimension) and an inquisitive-`belief' (featuring both a doxastic and an epistemic dimension conveying doxastic certainty (in the assertion) and epistemic uncertainty (in the presupposition)). We offer several previously unseen contrasts proving this distinction (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50.  64
    Deflationism And The Truth Conditional Theory of Meaning.Douglas Patterson - 2005 - Philosophical Studies 124 (3):271-294.
    Controversy has arisen of late over the claim that deflationism about truth requires that we explain meaning in terms of something other than truth-conditions. This controversy, it is argued, is due to unclarity as to whether the basic deflationary claim that a sentence and a sentence that attributes truth to it are equivalent in meaning is intended to involve the truth- predicate of the object language for which we develop an account of meaning, or is intended to involve the truth- (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000