Results for 'Conclusion'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  18
    \Large {\bf.Conclusion Iii - unknown
    PARANORMAL IS ABNORMAL ACTION OF MIND ON MATTER.\\ ONE NEEDS FIRST A THEORY OF NORMAL ACTION OF MIND ON MATTER.\\ CLASSICAL THEORY INADEQUATE: NO `MIND' IN THE DYNAMICS.\\ QUANTUM THEORY IS FORMULATED AS A THEORY OF MIND-MATTER INTERPLAY!\\ SIMPLER THAN CLASSICAL PHYSICS!\\ I SHALL:\\ 1. SHOW HOW QUANTUM THEORY OF MIND-MATTER IS CONSTRUCTED.\\ 2. DO TWO IMPORTANT MIND-MATTER CALCULATIONS.\\ 3. LOOK AT RAMIFICATIONS FOR PARANORMAL.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Pièces justificatives I.Conclusions des Commissaires Instructeurs & de Jacques Spifame du Procès - forthcoming - Bibliothèque d'Humanisme Et Renaissance.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Young Citizens for a Sustainable Planet.Matthew Giuseppe Marasco, Jennifer Rudkin, Geci Karuri-Sebina & A. Conclusion by Bayo Akomolafe - 2018 - In Riel Miller (ed.), Transforming the future: anticipation in the 21st century. New York, NY: Routledge.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  28
    The Monstrous Conclusion.Luca Stroppa - forthcoming - Synthese.
    This paper introduces the Monstrous Conclusion, according to which, for any population, there is a better population consisting of just one individual (the Monster). The Monstrous Conclusion is deeply counterintuitive. I defend a version of Prioritarianism as a particularly promising population axiology that does not imply the Monstrous Conclusion. According to this version of Prioritarianism, which I call Asymptotic Prioritarianism, there is diminishing marginal moral importance of individual welfare that can get close to, but never quite reach, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  77
    Kant's Conclusions in the Transcendental Aesthetic.W. Clark Wolf - forthcoming - Journal of the History of Philosophy.
    In the Transcendental Aesthetic (TA), Kant is typically held to make negative assertations about “things in themselves,” namely that they are not spatial or temporal. These negative assertions stand behind the “neglected alternative” problem for Kant’s transcendental idealism. According to this problem, Kant may be entitled to assert that spatio-temporality is a subjective element of our cognition, but he cannot rule out that it may also be a feature of the objective world. In this paper, I show in a new (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Conclusion: Stories and Morals.Colin McGinn - 1997 - In Ethics, evil, and fiction. New York: Oxford University Press.
    In the conclusion, McGinn distinguishes the ‘commandment’ paradigm and the ‘parable’ paradigm of ethical reflection, and argues that analytical moral philosophy, despite its emphasis on moral language, tends to follow the former. In this book, McGinn has argued that the latter, as exemplified in fictional narrative, with its appeal to our aesthetic sensibility, is the true vehicle of moral thought and persuasion. The fictional world is ideal for the exploration of ethical questions and the acquisition of ethical knowledge.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Conclusion : Metaphysics and violence.Gianni Vattimo - 2007 - In Santiago Zabala (ed.), Weakening philosophy: essays in honour of Gianni Vattimo. Ithaca: McGill-Queen's University Press.
  8.  6
    11. Conclusion.Adi Shmueli - 1975 - In Adi Shmuëli (ed.), Kierkegaard and consciousness. Presses Universitaires de France. pp. 190-194.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Conclusion.Michelle Kosch - 2006 - In Freedom and reason in Kant, Schelling, and Kierkegaard. New York: Oxford University Press.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Multiple Conclusions.Greg Restall - 2005 - In Petr Hájek, Luis Valdés-Villanueva & Dag Westerståhl (eds.), Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science. College Publications.
    Our topic is the notion of logical consequence: the link between premises and conclusions, the glue that holds together deductively valid argument. How can we understand this relation between premises and conclusions? It seems that any account begs questions. Painting with very broad brushtrokes, we can sketch the landscape of disagreement like this: “Realists” prefer an analysis of logical consequence in terms of the preservation of truth [29]. “Anti-realists” take this to be unhelpful and o:er alternative analyses. Some, like Dummett, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   118 citations  
  11.  4
    Cómo no evitar la conclusión muy repugnante.Mat Rozas - 2024 - Análisis Filosófico 1.
    En ética de poblaciones, se apela a ciertas perspectivas léxicas y de nivel crítico totalistas para evitar la conclusión repugnante. Dado que la conclusión muy repugnante es una condición de adecuación más débil, podría pensarse que estas perspectivas también nos permitirán evitar esta conclusión. En este artículo argumento que no es así. Primero, muestro que estas perspectivas léxicas no evitan la conclusión muy repugnante. Después, muestro que las perspectivas de rango crítico totalistas tampoco la evitan. Finalmente, aclaro qué perspectivas nos (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  74
    Multiple Conclusion Logic.D. J. Shoesmith & Timothy Smiley - 1978 - Cambridge, England / New York London Melbourne: Cambridge University Press. Edited by T. J. Smiley.
    Multiple -conclusion logic extends formal logic by allowing arguments to have a set of conclusions instead of a single one, the truth lying somewhere among the conclusions if all the premises are true. The extension opens up interesting possibilities based on the symmetry between premises and conclusions, and can also be used to throw fresh light on the conventional logic and its limitations. This is a sustained study of the subject and is certain to stimulate further research. Part I (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   110 citations  
  13.  4
    8. Conclusion.Christian Wildberg - 1988 - In John Philoponus‘ Criticism of Aristotle‘s Theory of Aether. De Gruyter. pp. 234-246.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  6
    Conclusion: The Four Packages.Timothy H. Pickavance & Robert C. Koons - 2017 - In The Atlas of Reality. Wiley. pp. 624–632.
    This chapter discusses four packages, including Ludovician, Aristotelian, Fortibracchian, and Quietist. There are two quite coherent packages of answers to the some issues: a neo‐Humeist or Ludovician package, and a neo‐Aristotelian package. Ludovicians put little weight on common sense beliefs, especially when they are embedded in ethical and legal practices, and they do not rely heavily on the "manifest image of the world". Aristotelians rely more heavily on the semantic intuition about what could possibly be the truthmakers for familiar kinds (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  95
    Why Conclusions Should Remain Single.Florian Steinberger - 2011 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 40 (3):333-355.
    This paper argues that logical inferentialists should reject multiple-conclusion logics. Logical inferentialism is the position that the meanings of the logical constants are determined by the rules of inference they obey. As such, logical inferentialism requires a proof-theoretic framework within which to operate. However, in order to fulfil its semantic duties, a deductive system has to be suitably connected to our inferential practices. I argue that, contrary to an established tradition, multiple-conclusion systems are ill-suited for this purpose because (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  16. Conclusion.David Lewis - 2002 - In Convention. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 203–208.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  1
    Conclusion.Alan Patten - 1999 - In Hegel's idea of freedom. New York: Oxford University Press.
    The final chapter recapitulates the main puzzles considered in the book and summarizes how the book proposes to solve them. It also raises several problems with Hegel's project.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Conclusion: Marx's “Liberalism,” Rawls's “Labor Theory of Justice”.Jeffrey Reiman - 2012 - In As Free and as Just as Possible. Oxford, UK: Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 210–220.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  5
    Conclusion.Paul C. Taylor - 2016 - In Black is Beautiful. Chichester, UK: Wiley. pp. 182–185.
    White men pretending to be black men by blackening their faces and performing, on stage, the peculiar antics that constituted their vision of blackness. This chapter explores how black people sustain themselves under conditions of racial terror, exclusion, and oppression. Eric Lott's point goes beyond shaming and repudiation, though, to suggest that minstrelsy is more, and more interesting, than a garden variety expression of racism. The men who donned blackface did so in an attempt to work out their own identities (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  7
    Conclusion. For a “good enough” justice.Ernst Wolff - 2011 - In Political Responsibility for a Globalised World: After Levinas' Humanism. Columbia University Press. pp. 267-286.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Virtue ethics and repugnant conclusions.Matt Zwolinski & David Schmidtz - 2005 - In Philip Cafaro & Ronald Sandler (eds.), Environmental Virtue Ethics. Oxford: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. pp. 107--17.
    Both utilitarian and deontological moral theories locate the source of our moral beliefs in the wrong sorts of considerations. One way this failure manifests itself, we argue, is in the ways these theories analyze the proper human relationship toward the non-human environment. Another, more notorious, manifestation of this failure is found in Derek Parfit's Repugnant Conclusion. Our goal is to explore the connection between these two failures, and to suggest that they are failures of act-centered moral theories in general. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  22. Hume’s practically epistemic conclusions?Hsueh Qu - 2014 - Philosophical Studies 170 (3):501-524.
    The inoffensive title of Section 1.4.7 of Hume’s Treatise of Human Nature, ‘Conclusion of this Book’, belies the convoluted treatment of scepticism contained within. It is notoriously difficult to decipher Hume’s considered response to scepticism in this section, or whether he even has one. In recent years, however, one line of interpretation has gained popularity in the literature. The ‘usefulness and agreeableness reading’ (henceforth U&A) interprets Hume as arguing in THN 1.4.7 that our beliefs and/or epistemic policies are justified (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  23. Conclusive Reasons.Fred I. Dretske - 2000 - In Sven Bernecker & Fred I. Dretske (eds.), Knowledge: Readings in Contemporary Epistemology. Oxford University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   169 citations  
  24.  12
    Conclusion.Neil Pickering - 2013 - Asian Bioethics Review 5 (3):222-223.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:ConclusionNeil PickeringAs mentioned in my Introduction, and I am delighted to repeat now, the commentaries provided by Calvin Ho and Chua Hong Choon are both excellent. In reading them, some further thoughts were raised for me, and I briefly reflect on these now.In his legal commentary, Calvin Ho makes a plausible argument that Mr. T has the capacity (and hence the right) to make decisions in his current state (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Conclusive reasons.Fred I. Dretske - 1971 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 49 (1):1-22.
  26.  99
    Multiple-conclusion lp and default classicality.Jc Beall - 2011 - Review of Symbolic Logic 4 (2):326-336.
    Philosophical applications of familiar paracomplete and paraconsistent logics often rely on an idea of . With respect to the paraconsistent logic LP (the dual of Strong Kleene or K3), such is standardly cashed out via an LP-based nonmonotonic logic due to Priest (1991, 2006a). In this paper, I offer an alternative approach via a monotonic multiple-conclusion version of LP.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  27.  28
    Repugnant Conclusions.Mark Budolfson - 2021 - Social Choice and Welfare 57.
    The population ethics literature has long focused on attempts to avoid the repugnant conclusion. We show that a large set of social orderings that are conventionally understood to escape the repugnant conclusion do not in fact avoid it in all instances. As we demonstrate, prior results depend on formal definitions of the repugnant conclusion that exclude some repugnant cases, for reasons inessential to any "repugnance" (or other meaningful normative properties) of the repugnant conclusion. In particular, the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  28. The conclusion of practical reasoning: the shadow between idea and act.Sarah K. Paul - 2013 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 43 (3):287-302.
    There is a puzzle about how to understand the conclusion of a successful instance of practical reasoning. Do the considerations adduced in reasoning rationalize the particular doing of an action, as Aristotle is sometimes interpreted as claiming? Or does reasoning conclude in the formation of an attitude – an intention, say – that has an action-type as its content? This paper attempts to clarify what is at stake in that debate and defends the latter view against some of its (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  29. Scientific Conclusions Need Not Be Accurate, Justified, or Believed by their Authors.Haixin Dang & Liam Kofi Bright - 2021 - Synthese 199:8187–8203.
    We argue that the main results of scientific papers may appropriately be published even if they are false, unjustified, and not believed to be true or justified by their author. To defend this claim we draw upon the literature studying the norms of assertion, and consider how they would apply if one attempted to hold claims made in scientific papers to their strictures, as assertions and discovery claims in scientific papers seem naturally analogous. We first use a case study of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  30. Conclusion. Plato - 1984 - In R. Allen (ed.), The Dialogues of Plato, Volume 4: Plato’s Parmenides, Revised Edition. Yale University Press. pp. 338-340.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Conclusion.Michael Slote - 1992 - In From morality to virtue. New York: Oxford University Press.
    A commonsense virtue ethics can contribute to moral education by pointing out the importance of self‐regarding virtues. That importance is often ignored or neglected in school ”values” curricula.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  7
    Leaping to Conclusions: Why Premise Relevance Affects Argument Strength.Keith J. Ransom, Andrew Perfors & Daniel J. Navarro - 2016 - Cognitive Science 40 (7):1775-1796.
    Everyday reasoning requires more evidence than raw data alone can provide. We explore the idea that people can go beyond this data by reasoning about how the data was sampled. This idea is investigated through an examination of premise non‐monotonicity, in which adding premises to a category‐based argument weakens rather than strengthens it. Relevance theories explain this phenomenon in terms of people's sensitivity to the relationships among premise items. We show that a Bayesian model of category‐based induction taking premise sampling (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  33. The Conclusion of Practical Reasoning.John Brunero - 2021 - The Journal of Ethics 25 (1):13-37.
    According to the Aristotelian Thesis, the conclusion of practical reasoning is an action. Critics argue against it by pointing to cases in which some interference or inability prevents the production of action, yet in which that interference or inability doesn’t impugn the success of an agent’s reasoning. Some of those critics suggest instead that practical reasoning concludes in an intention, while others suggest it concludes in a belief with normative content, such as a belief about what one has conclusive, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34.  1
    Foregone Conclusions: Against Apocalyptic History.Michael André Bernstein - 1994 - University of California Press.
    We are continually trying to make sense of our world through the stories we tell and are told, but in our search for coherence, we often sacrifice our freedom and the rich randomness of life. In this passionate and lucid book, Michael André Bernstein challenges our practice of "foreshadowing," in which we see our lives as moving toward a predetermined goal or as controlled by fate. Foreshadowing, he argues, demeans the variety and openness that exist in even the most ordinary (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  35.  34
    Causal Conclusions that Flip Repeatedly and Their Justification.Kevin T. Kelly & Conor Mayo-Wilson - 2010 - Proceedings of the Twenty Sixth Conference on Uncertainty in Artificial Intelligence 26:277-286.
    Over the past two decades, several consistent procedures have been designed to infer causal conclusions from observational data. We prove that if the true causal network might be an arbitrary, linear Gaussian network or a discrete Bayes network, then every unambiguous causal conclusion produced by a consistent method from non-experimental data is subject to reversal as the sample size increases any finite number of times. That result, called the causal flipping theorem, extends prior results to the effect that causal (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  36. 9 9 Conclusion.Jason Stanley - 2005 - In Knowledge and practical interests. New York: Oxford University Press.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  76
    Repugnant Conclusion.Gustaf Arrhenius - 2013 - In Hugh LaFollette (ed.), The International Encyclopedia of Ethics. Hoboken, NJ: Blackwell.
  38.  22
    Warrant, Conclusive Reason, and Failure-Of-Transfer-Of-Warrant.Murali Ramachandran - 2018 - Problemos 94:35.
    [full article, abstract in English; abstract in Lithuanian] Fred Dretske motivates his denial of epistemic closure by way of the thought that the warrant for the premises of a valid argument need not transfer to the argument’s conclusion. The failure-of-transfer-of-warrant strategy has also been used by advocates of epistemic closure as a foil to Michael McKinsey’s argument against the compatibility of first person authority and semantic externalism, and also to illuminate, more generally, why certain valid arguments appear ill-suited for (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. The Conclusion of Practical Reason.Sergio Tenenbaum - 2007 - Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 94:323-343.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  40.  45
    Conclusions from color vision of insects.Werner Backhaus & Randolf Menzel - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):28-30.
  41. Conclusive Reasons and Epistemic Luck.Tamar Lando - 2016 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 94 (2):378-395.
    What is it to have conclusive reasons to believe a proposition P? According to a view famously defended by Dretske, a reason R is conclusive for P just in case [R would not be the case unless P were the case]. I argue that, while knowing that P is plausibly related to having conclusive reasons to believe that P, having such reasons cannot be understood in terms of the truth of this counterfactual condition. Simple examples show that it is possible (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  42.  9
    Irrelevant Conclusion.Steven Barbone - 2018-05-09 - In Robert Arp, Steven Barbone & Michael Bruce (eds.), Bad Arguments. Wiley. pp. 172–173.
    This chapter focuses on one of the common fallacies in Western philosophy called 'irrelevant conclusion'. The fallacy of irrelevant conclusion, also known as the ignoratio elenchi (“ignorance of the proof”) fallacy, is, in effect, the parent of all other fallacies since every fallacy yields a conclusion that even if it be true is not related – that is, is irrelevant – to the premises of the argument. Arguments that commit the irrelevant conclusion fallacy all end with (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. The conclusion of practical reason.Sergio Tenenbaum - 2007 - In New Trends in Philosophy: Moral Psychology. Rodopi. pp. 323-343.
  44.  61
    Conclusive reasons that we perceive sets.David MacCallum - 2000 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 14 (1):25 – 42.
    Penelope Maddy has defended a modified version of mathematical platonism that involves the perception of some sets. Frederick Suppe has developed a conclusive reasons account of empirical knowledge that, when applied to the sets of interest to Maddy, yields that we have knowledge of these sets. Thus, Benacerraf's challenge to the platonist to account for mathematical knowledge has been met, at least in part. Moreover, it is argued that the modalities involved in Suppe's conclusive reasons account of knowledge can be (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  45.  15
    Floating conclusions and zombie paths: Two deep difficulties in the “directly skeptical” approach to defeasible inheritance nets.David Makinson & Karl Schlechta - 1991 - Artificial Intelligence 48 (2):199-209.
  46.  34
    Drawing Conclusions from Aristotelian Syllogisms.James Duerlinger - 1968 - The Monist 52 (2):229-236.
    Aristotle characterizes a syllogism as “discourse in which, certain things being stated, something other than what is stated follows of necessity from their being so.” This characterization of the syllogism does not require us to include as one of its constituent propositions the conclusion of a syllogism. When what are now called the premisses of a syllogism are stated, “something other than what is stated follows of necessity,” but what necessarily follows need not be a proposition in a syllogism (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47. Vers une impossible conclusion.Pierre Watté - 1980 - In Ethique et sociologie des valeurs: conflit ou complémentarité?: séminaire. Leuven: Peeters.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Skeptical Conclusions.Linton Wang & Oliver Tai - 2010 - Erkenntnis 72 (2):177-204.
    For a putative knower S and a proposition P , two types of skepticism can be distinguished, depending on the conclusions they draw: outer skepticism , which concludes that S does not know that P , and inner skepticism , which concludes that S does not know whether P . This paper begins by showing that outer skepticism has undesirable consequences because that S does not know that P presupposes P , and inner skepticism does not have this undesirable consequence (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  49.  20
    Drawing conclusions: Representing and evaluating competing explanations.Alice Liefgreen & David A. Lagnado - 2023 - Cognition 234 (C):105382.
  50.  8
    Conclusion. Le projet scientifique de la psychologie associationniste.Stéphane Madelrieux - 2014 - Astérion 12.
    Cette conclusion cherche à restituer la psychologie associationniste du xixe siècle dans son projet épistémologique au-delà de la diversité des positions de l’époque. On y défend l’idée que l’importance de l’association des idées fut de permettre de prétendre fonder la psychologie comme science empirique de l’esprit. C’est la nouvelle fonction de l’association, dégagée en réalité dès l’œuvre de Hume, qui a permis un tel projet : non plus simple transition habituelle d’une idée à une autre, mais principe génétique de (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000