Results for ' parental refusal of treatment'

994 found
Order:
  1. Parental refusals of medical treatment: The harm principle as threshold for state intervention.Douglas Diekema - 2004 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 25 (4):243-264.
    Minors are generally considered incompetent to provide legally binding decisions regarding their health care, and parents or guardians are empowered to make those decisions on their behalf. Parental authority is not absolute, however, and when a parent acts contrary to the best interests of a child, the state may intervene. The best interests standard is the threshold most frequently employed in challenging a parent''s refusal to provide consent for a child''s medical care. In this paper, I will argue (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   115 citations  
  2.  59
    Parental Refusal of Life‐Saving Treatments for Adolescents: Chinese Familism in Medical Decision‐Making Re‐Visited.Edwin Hui - 2008 - Bioethics 22 (5):286-295.
    This paper reports two cases in Hong Kong involving two native Chinese adolescent cancer patients (APs) who were denied their rights to consent to necessary treatments refused by their parents, resulting in serious harm. We argue that the dynamics of the ‘AP‐physician‐family‐relationship’ and the dominant role Chinese families play in medical decision‐making (MDM) are best understood in terms of the tendency to hierarchy and parental authoritarianism in traditional Confucianism. This ethic has been confirmed and endorsed by various Chinese writers (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  3.  47
    understandings and uses of ‘culture’ in bioethics deliberations over parental refusal of treatment: Children with cancer.Ben Gray & Fern Brunger - 2017 - Clinical Ethics 13 (2):55-66.
    We developed this study to examine the issue of parental refusal of treatment, looking at the issue through a cultural competence lens. Recent cases in Canada where courts have declined applications by clinicians for court orders to overrule parental refusal of treatment highlight the dispute in this area. This study analyses the 16 cases of a larger group of 24 cases that were selected by a literature review where cultural or religious beliefs or ethnic (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  4.  45
    Parental refusal of life-saving treatments for adolescents: Chinese familism in medical decision-making re-visited.H. U. I. Edwin - 2008 - Bioethics 22 (5):286–295.
    This paper reports two cases in Hong Kong involving two native Chinese adolescent cancer patients (APs) who were denied their rights to consent to necessary treatments refused by their parents, resulting in serious harm. We argue that the dynamics of the 'AP-physician-family-relationship' and the dominant role Chinese families play in medical decision-making (MDM) are best understood in terms of the tendency to hierarchy and parental authoritarianism in traditional Confucianism. This ethic has been confirmed and endorsed by various Chinese writers (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  5.  30
    Should Parental Refusal of Puberty-Blocking Treatment be Overridden? The Role of the Harm Principle.Lauren Notini, Rosalind McDougall & Ken C. Pang - 2019 - American Journal of Bioethics 19 (2):69-72.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6.  32
    Differing Thresholds for Overriding Parental Refusals of Life-Sustaining Treatment.Hannah Gerdes & John Lantos - 2020 - HEC Forum 32 (1):13-20.
    When should doctors seek protective custody to override a parent’s refusal of potentially lifesaving treatment for their child? The answer to this question seemingly has different answers for different subspecialties of pediatrics. This paper specifically looks at different thresholds for physicians overriding parental refusals of life-sustaining treatment between neonatology, cardiology, and oncology. The threshold for mandating treatment of premature babies seems to be a survival rate of 25–50%. This is not the case when the (...) in question is open heart surgery for a child with congenital heart disease. Most cardiologists would not pursue legal action when parents refuse treatment, unless the anticipated survival rate after surgery is above 90%. In pediatric oncology, there are case reports of physicians requesting and obtaining protective custody for cancer treatment when the reported mortality rates are 40–50%. Such differences might be attributed to differences in care, a reasonable prioritization of quality of life over survival, or the role uncertainty plays on prognoses, especially for the extremely young. Nonetheless, other, non-medical factors may have a significant effect on inconsistencies in care across these pediatric subspecialties and require further examinations. (shrink)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  14
    A Quality of Life Quandary: A Framework for Navigating Parental Refusal of Treatment for Co-Morbidities in Infants with Underlying Medical Conditions.Douglas J. Opel, Douglas S. Diekema, Ryan M. McAdams & Sarah N. Kunz - 2015 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 26 (1):16-23.
    Parental refusal of a recommended treatment is not an uncommon scenario in the neonatal intensive care unit. These refusals may be based upon the parents’ perceptions of their child’s projected quality of life. The inherent subjectivity of quality of life assessments, however, can exacerbate disagreement between parents and healthcare providers. We present a case of parental refusal of surgical intervention for necrotizing enterocolitis in an infant with Bartter syndrome and develop an ethical framework in which (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  82
    Parental refusal of medical treatment for a newborn.John J. Paris, Michael D. Schreiber & Michael P. Moreland - 2007 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 28 (5):427-441.
    When there is a conflict between parents and the physician over appropriate care due to an infant whose decision prevails? What standard, if any, should guide such decisions?This article traces the varying standards articulated over the past three decades from the proposal in Duff and Campbell’s 1973 essay that these decisions are best left to the parents to the Baby Doe Regs of the 1980s which required every life that could be salvaged be continued. We conclude with support for the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  26
    Parental refusal of transfusion on religious grounds: an exception to the standard approach.M. R. Mercurio - 2007 - Clinical Ethics 2 (3):146-148.
    The standard approach to parental refusal of transfusion on religious grounds in many newborn intensive care units and paediatric services is to override the refusal and provide the transfusion, usually with court intervention if time allows. This approach is justified by the child's right to effective treatment, seen to outweigh the parents' right to religious freedom and their right to decide for their child. That justification, however, may be limited by the predicted effectiveness of the transfusion (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Overriding Adolescent Refusals of Treatment.Anthony Skelton, Lisa Forsberg & Isra Black - 2021 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 20 (3):221-247.
    Adolescents are routinely treated differently to adults, even when they possess similar capacities. In this article, we explore the justification for one case of differential treatment of adolescents. We attempt to make philosophical sense of the concurrent consents doctrine in law: adolescents found to have decision-making capacity have the power to consent to—and thereby, all else being equal, permit—their own medical treatment, but they lack the power always to refuse treatment and so render it impermissible. Other parties, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  33
    Should Parental Refusals of Newborn Screening Be Respected?Newson Ainsley - 2006 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 15 (2):135-146.
    For over four decades, knowledge that symptoms of some inherited diseases can be prevented or reduced via early detection and treatment in newborns has underpinned state-funded screening programs in most developed countries. Conditions for which newborn screening is now a recognized preventative public health initiative include phenylketonuria, congenital hypothyroidism, and, more recently, cystic fibrosis and sickle cell disorder. The use of tandem mass spectrometry to detect conditions such as amino-acidopathies and fatty-acid oxidation defects is also becoming increasingly prevalent. a.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  12. Parents refusing treatment of the child: A discussion about child’s health right and parental paternalism.Cemal Hüseyin Güvercin & Berna Arda - 2013 - Clinical Ethics 8 (2-3):52-60.
    In recent years, decision-making processes related to medical practices have undergone a change from physician paternalism towards patient autonomy. However, it has been put forward that this situation has changed into or strengthened the parent paternalism for children. Parental paternalism might bring along decisions of refusing the child’s treatment, in such a way to occasionally violate the health right of the child. Paternalistic attitude of parents may also cause physicians to direct towards defensive medicine practices and to display (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  8
    At the Intersection of Faith, Culture, and Family Dynamics: A Complex Case of Refusal of Treatment for Childhood Cancer.Amy E. Caruso Brown - 2017 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 28 (3):228-235.
    Refusing treatment for potentially curable childhood cancers engenders much discussion and debate. I present a case in which the competent parents of a young Amish child with acute myeloid leukemia deferred authority for decision making to the child’s maternal grandfather, who was vocal in his opposition to treatment. I analyze three related concerns that distinguish this case from other accounts of refused treatment.First, I place deference to grandparents as decision makers in the context of surrogate decision making (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  14. The zone of parental discretion: An ethical tool for dealing with disagreement between parents and doctors about medical treatment for a child.Lynn Gillam - 2016 - Clinical Ethics 11 (1):1-8.
    Dealing with situations where parents’ views about treatment for their child are strongly opposed to doctors’ views is one major area of ethical challenge in paediatric health care. The traditional approach focuses on the child’s best interests, but this is problematic for a number of reasons. The Harm Principle test is regarded by many ethicists as more appropriate than the best interests test. Despite this, use of the best interests test for intervening in parental decisions is still very (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  15.  34
    Determining a Child’s Best Interests when Parents Refuse Medical Treatment—CAHS v Kiszko & Anor [2016] FCWA 19.Michaela Okninski - 2016 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 13 (3):365-368.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  16.  15
    Parents refuse to allow life-saving treatment for newborn: our moral obligation.M. Otten - 1997 - Princeton Journal of Bioethics 1 (1):61-64.
  17.  23
    Minority report: can minor parents refuse treatment for their child?Helen Lynne Turnham, Ariella Binik & Dominic Wilkinson - 2020 - Journal of Medical Ethics 46 (6):355-359.
    Infants are unable to make their own decisions or express their own wishes about medical procedures and treatments. They rely on surrogates to make decisions for them. Who should be the decision-maker when an infant’s biological parents are also minors? In this paper, we analyse a case in which the biological mother is a child. The central questions raised by the case are whether minor parents should make medical decisions on behalf of an infant, and if so, what are the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18.  6
    When Should Society Override Parental Decisions? A Proposed Test to Mediate Refusals of Beneficial Treatments and of Life-Saving Treatments for Children.Allan J. Jacobs - 2021 - In Nico Nortjé & Johan C. Bester (eds.), Pediatric Ethics: Theory and Practice. Springer Verlag. pp. 421-436.
    Health care workers or others may wish to override parental decisions because of their impact on the health or safetySafety of a child or others. Justification of such an action requires two types of principle: an authorityAuthority principle that designates the process for reversal, and anPrincipal, interventionintervention principleIntervention principle that specifies the grounds for reversal. It is generally accepted that states may overruleOverruleparentsParents’ decisions for good cause. I argue that the role of the state is to provide sufficient protection (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  87
    Rawls and the Refusal of Medical Treatment to Children.D. Robert MacDougall - 2010 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 35 (2):130-153.
    That Jehovah's Witnesses cannot refuse life-saving blood transfusions on behalf of their children has acquired the status of virtual “consensus” among bioethicists. However strong the consensus may be on this matter, this article explores whether this view can be plausibly defended on liberal principles by examining it in light of one particularly well worked-out liberal political theory, that of Rawls. It concludes that because of the extremely high priority Rawls attributes to “freedom of conscience,” and the implication from the original (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  20.  44
    Ethics of refusing parental requests to withhold or withdraw treatment from their premature baby.R. J. Boyle - 2004 - Journal of Medical Ethics 30 (4):402-405.
    In the United Kingdom women have access to termination of pregnancy for maternal reasons until 24 weeks’ completed gestation, but it is accepted practice for children born at or beyond 25 weeks’ gestation to be treated according to the child’s perceived best interests even if this is not in accordance with parental wishes. The authors present a case drawn from clinical practice which highlights the discomfort that parents may feel about such an abrupt change in their rights over their (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  21.  9
    Parens patriae jurisdiction and religious beliefs of parents in medical treatment of a minor: Examining the Supreme Court’s decision in Tega Esabunor v Faweya & Ors (2019) LPELR 46961 (SC) in light of international practice. [REVIEW]U. Anyamele - 2023 - South African Journal of Bioethics and Law 16 (1):29-31.
    Recently, the Supreme Court of Nigeria in Tega Esabunor v Faweya & Ors (2019) LPELR 46961 (SC) dismissed an appeal seeking to quash the order of a magistrate court for the transfusion of blood to a baby. The appellants contended that the court had no jurisdiction to make theorder. The crux of the case was whether the parents’ right to consent to the child’s treatment based on religious beliefs supersedes the child’s right to live, thus reflecting the tension between (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  66
    Settling for second best: when should doctors agree to parental demands for suboptimal medical treatment?Tara Nair, Julian Savulescu, Jim Everett, Ryan Tonkens & Dominic Wilkinson - 2017 - Journal of Medical Ethics 43 (12):831-840.
    Background Doctors sometimes encounter parents who object to prescribed treatment for their children, and request suboptimal substitutes be administered instead. Previous studies have focused on parental refusal of treatment and when this should be permitted, but the ethics of requests for suboptimal treatment has not been explored. Methods The paper consists of two parts: an empirical analysis and an ethical analysis. We performed an online survey with a sample of the general public to assess respondents’ (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  23.  49
    Conflicts Between Parents and Health Professionals About a Child’s Medical Treatment: Using Clinical Ethics Records to Find Gaps in the Bioethics Literature.Rosalind McDougall, Lauren Notini & Jessica Phillips - 2015 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 12 (3):429-436.
    Clinical ethics records offer bioethics researchers a rich source of cases that clinicians have identified as ethically complex. In this paper, we suggest that clinical ethics records can be used to point to types of cases that lack attention in the current bioethics literature, identifying new areas in need of more detailed bioethical work. We conducted an analysis of the clinical ethics records of one paediatric hospital in Australia, focusing specifically on conflicts between parents and health professionals about a child’s (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  24.  55
    Parental choice and selective non-treatment of deformed newborns: a view from mid-Atlantic.J. K. Mason & D. W. Meyers - 1986 - Journal of Medical Ethics 12 (2):67-71.
    This paper traces the development of parental rights to accept or to refuse treatment for a defective newborn infant in the United Kingdom and in the United States of America; its main purpose is to explore the common trends from which an acceptable policy may be derived. It is probable that the British law on parental decision-making in respect of infants suffering from Down's syndrome is to be found in the civil case of In Re B rather (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  25.  12
    Not All Disagreements Are Treatment Refusals: The Need for New Paradigms for Considering Parental Treatment Requests.Jonathan M. Marron - 2018 - American Journal of Bioethics 18 (8):56-58.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  22
    Parental Refusals of Blood Transfusions from COVID-19 Vaccinated Donors for Children Needing Cardiac Surgery.Daniel H. Kim, Emily Berkman, Jonna D. Clark, Nabiha H. Saifee, Douglas S. Diekema & Mithya Lewis-Newby - forthcoming - Narrative Inquiry in Bioethics.
    There is a growing trend of refusal of blood transfusions from COVID-19 vaccinated donors. We highlight three cases where parents have refused blood transfusions from COVID-19 vaccinated donors on behalf of their children in the setting of congenital cardiac surgery. These families have also requested accommodations such as explicit identification of blood from COVID-19 vaccinated donors, directed donation from a COVID19 unvaccinated family member, or use of a non-standard blood supplier. We address the ethical challenges posed by these issues. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  5
    Parental Refusals of Blood Transfusions from COVID-19 Vaccinated Donors for Children Needing Cardiac Surgery.Daniel H. Kim, Emily Berkman, Jonna D. Clark, Nabiha H. Saifee, Douglas S. Diekema & Mithya Lewis-Newby - 2023 - Narrative Inquiry in Bioethics 13 (3):215-226.
    There is a growing trend of refusal of blood transfusions from COVID-19 vaccinated donors. We highlight three cases where parents have refused blood transfusions from COVID-19 vaccinated donors on behalf of their children in the setting of congenital cardiac surgery. These families have also requested accommodations such as explicit identification of blood from COVID-19 vaccinated donors, directed donation from a COVID-19 unvaccinated family member, or use of a non-standard blood supplier. We address the ethical challenges posed by these issues. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  35
    State Authority, Parental Authority, and the Rights of Mature Minors.Mark Tunick - 2023 - The Journal of Ethics 27 (1):7-29.
    When mature minors face a decision with important consequences, such as whether to undergo a risky but potentially life-saving medical procedure, who should decide? Relying on liberal political theory’s account of the importance of decisional autonomy for adults, and given the scalar nature of the capacities needed to exercise decisional autonomy, I argue that mature minors with the requisite capacities and commitments have a right to decisional autonomy though they are not yet 18. I argue for this right using a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  54
    Parenting and the Best Interests of Minors.R. S. Downie & F. Randall - 1997 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 22 (3):219-231.
    The treatment decisions of competent adults, especially treatment refusals, are generally respected. In the case of minors something turns on their age, and older minors ought increasingly to make their own decisions. On the other hand, parents decide on behalf of infants and young children. Their right to do so can best be justified in terms of the importance of preserving intimate family relationships, rather than in terms of the child's best interests, although the child's best interests will (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  30.  16
    Parental Refusal of Newborn Screening for Congenital Hearing Loss.Danton Char - 2016 - American Journal of Bioethics 16 (1):33-35.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Refusal of treatment by patients.Anne-Marie Slowther - 2007 - Clinical Ethics 2 (3):121-123.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32.  7
    Refusals of treatment and requests for death.Tom L. Beauchamp - 1996 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 6 (4):371-374.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Refusals of Treatment and Requests for DeathTom L. Beauchamp (bio)It would be hard to overestimate the importance of two decisions on physician-assisted suicide delivered recently by the Ninth and Second Circuit Courts (Compassion in Dying v. State of Washington, 79 F.3d 790 (9th Cir. 1996) (en banc), aff’g 850 F.Supp. 1454 (W.D. Wash. 1994), rev’g 49 F.3d 586 (9th Cir. 1995); Quill v. Vacco, 80 F.3d 716 (2nd (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. George Khushf.The Domain of Parental Discretion in Treatment - 2002 - In Julia Lai Po-Wah Tao (ed.), Cross-Cultural Perspectives on the (Im) Possibility of Global Bioethics. Kluwer Academic.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Refusal of treatment and decision-making capacity.S. -L. Bingham - 2012 - Nursing Ethics 19 (1):167-172.
    This article explores refusal of medical treatment by adult patients from ethical and legal perspectives. Initially, consequentialist and deontological ethical theory are outlined. The concepts of autonomy, paternalism and competence are described and an overview of Beauchamp and Childress’s principle-based approach to moral reasoning is given. Relevant common law is discussed and the provisions of the Mental Capacity Act 2005 in assessing competence is evaluated. In order to demonstrate the consideration of moral issues in clinical practice, ethical theory (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  22
    Attitudes of prehospital emergency care professionals toward refusal of treatment.Hasan Erbay, Sultan Alan & Selim Kadioglu - 2014 - Nursing Ethics 21 (5):530-539.
    Introduction:Prehospital emergency medicine is a specific field of emergency medicine. The basic approach of prehospital emergency medicine is to provide patients with medical intervention at the scene of the incident. This special environment causes health professionals to encounter various problems. One of the most important problems in this field is ethics, in particular questions involving refusal of treatment and the processes associated with it.Objective:The objective of this study is to identify emergency health professionals’ views regarding refusal of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  36.  45
    The Persistence of Physician–Parent Conflicts.Amnon Goldworth - 2010 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 19 (4):563-566.
    In 1985, after a long university career teaching philosophy and humanities, in which my only serious worries over the years were centered on such things as getting promoted, course preparations, and faculty affairs, I found myself confronted, as a medical ethics committee member, with a life and death issue. It concerned the care of an infant suffering from posthemorrhagic hydrocephalus, for which there appeared to be no permanently effective treatment. The parents refused to consider the discontinuing of aggressive care (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  14
    Hearing Parents’ Voices: Parental Refusal of Cochlear Implants and the Zone of Parental Discretion.Owen M. Bradfield - 2021 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 19 (1):143-150.
    It has been forty years since the first multi-channel cochlear implant was used in Australia. While heralded in the hearing world as one of the greatest inventions in modern medicine, not everyone reflects on this achievement with enthusiasm. For many people in the Deaf community, they see the cochlear implant as a tool that reinforces a social construct that pathologizes deafness and removes Deaf identity. In this paper, I set out the main arguments for and against cochlear implantation. While I (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  10
    Fostering medical staff reflection on the technological alienation of parents in the NICU.Abram Brummett & Annie B. Friedrich - 2022 - Clinical Ethics 17 (4):449-451.
    We describe a case of parents refusing a tracheostomy for an otherwise healthy newborn. The refusal was not honored because permitting the refusal would have violated state law, which required a child to have a qualifying condition (e.g. a terminal diagnosis, permanent unconsciousness, incurable condition with severe suffering) to remove or withhold life-sustaining treatment. However, this case strained the relationship between the parents and medical staff, who worried about sending the newborn home with a tracheostomy where she (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  97
    Methods and principles in biomedical ethics.T. L. Beauchamp - 2003 - Journal of Medical Ethics 29 (5):269-274.
    The four principles approach to medical ethics plus specification is used in this paper. Specification is defined as a process of reducing the indeterminateness of general norms to give them increased action guiding capacity, while retaining the moral commitments in the original norm. Since questions of method are central to the symposium, the paper begins with four observations about method in moral reasoning and case analysis. Three of the four scenarios are dealt with. It is concluded in the “standard” Jehovah’s (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  40.  31
    When Parents Refuse: Resolving Entrenched Disagreements Between Parents and Clinicians in Situations of Uncertainty and Complexity.Janine Penfield Winters - 2018 - American Journal of Bioethics 18 (8):20-31.
    When shared decision making breaks down and parents and medical providers have developed entrenched and conflicting views, ethical frameworks are needed to find a way forward. This article reviews the evolution of thought about the best interest standard and then discusses the advantages of the harm principle (HP) and the zone of parental discretion (ZPD). Applying these frameworks to parental refusals in situations of complexity and uncertainty presents challenges that necessitate concrete substeps to analyze the big picture and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  41.  10
    Should an Incapacitated Patient’s Refusal of Treatment Be Respected? Discussion of a Hypothetical Case.Hiroko Ishimoto, Sakiko Masaki & Atsushi Asai - 2015 - Eubios Journal of Asian and International Bioethics 25 (4):112-118.
    In the present super-aging society, issues concerning what treatment should be given for incapacitated patients have become more important than ever before. This paper discusses whether or not an incapacitated patient’s refusal of treatment should be respected. The authors present a complete hypothetical scenario involving a 75-year-old moderately demented man suffering from malignant lymphoma. Of primary importance are the respect for patient dignity and the protection of human rights. Acts such as coercion, disregard, restriction, and surveillance can (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  21
    Challenging Medical Authority The Refusal of Treatment by Christian Scientists.Larry May - 1995 - Hastings Center Report 25 (1):15-21.
    Christian Scientists' refusal of medical care for their children illustrates the kind of conflict over moral and practical authority that can arise between groups in a pluralistic society. While consensus may not be possible, changes in the way both groups socialize members may allow the medical and Christian Science communities to achieve a compromise that is respectful to both.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  43.  29
    Euthanasia, consensual homicide, and refusal of treatment.Eduardo Rivera-López - 2024 - Bioethics 38 (4):292-299.
    Consensual homicide remains a crime in jurisdictions where active voluntary euthanasia has been legalized. At the same time, both jurisdictions, in which euthanasia is legal and those in which it is not, recognize that all patients (whether severely ill or not) have the right to refuse or withdraw medical treatment (including life-saving treatment). In this paper, I focus on the tensions between these three norms (the permission of active euthanasia, the permission to reject life-saving treatment, and the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  11
    Physicians Must Honor Refusal of Treatment to Restore Competency by Non-Dangerous Inmates on Death Row.Howard Zonana - 2010 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 38 (4):764-773.
    The vignette described in the introduction of this symposium raises a number of ethical and legal problems for physicians who work for correctional institutions and death row inmates. They are not confined to correctional physicians, however, as states have requested aid from practicing physicians in the community, and even from other states, when conflicts have arisen in the treatment of death row inmates as they near the date of execution. As outlined, the case involves a 48-year-old man with a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45. Free and informed consent, refusal of treatment and the health care team.H. T. Engelhardt - forthcoming - Foundations of Bioethics Vol 1.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  37
    Physicians Must Honor Refusal of Treatment to Restore Competency by Non-Dangerous Inmates on Death Row.Howard Zonana - 2010 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 38 (4):764-773.
    The role of physicians in death penalty cases has provoked discussion in both the legal system as well as in professional organizations. Professional groups have responded by developing ethical guidelines advising physicians as to current ethical standards. Psychiatric dilemmas as a subspecialty with unique roles have required more specific guidelines. A clinical vignette provides a focus to explicate the conflicts.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  41
    Rationality, religion and refusal of treatment in an ambulance revisited.Kate McMahon-Parkes - 2013 - Journal of Medical Ethics 39 (9):587-590.
    In their recent article, Erbay et al considered whether a seriously injured patient should be able to refuse treatment if the refusal was based on a (mis)interpretation of religious doctrine. They argued that in such a case ‘what is important…is whether the teaching or philosophy used as a reference point has been in fact correctly perceived’ (p 653). If it has not been, they asserted that this eroded the patient's capacity to make an autonomous decision and that therefore, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48.  14
    J. Skelly wright and refusal of treatment.Michael Wreen - 1982 - Journal of Bioethics 4 (1-2):11-28.
    This article is a critical analysis of Judge J. Skelly Wright's “Application of President and Directors of Georgetown College.” Wright's paper concerns the refusal of a Mrs. Jones to allow a blood transfusion needed to save her life and Wright's decision, based on a number of social, medical, legal, religious, and psychological facts, to permit the transfusion. The presentation is a close paraphrase of Wright's own case write-up. Critical expositions of five arguments explicitly advanced by Wright for his decision (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  18
    J. Skelly Wright And Refusal Of Treatment.Michael Wreen - 1982 - Journal of Medical Humanities 4 (1):11-28.
    This article is a critical analysis of Judge J. Skelly Wright's “Application of President and Directors of Georgetown College.” Wright's paper concerns the refusal of a Mrs. Jones to allow a blood transfusion needed to save her life and Wright's decision, based on a number of social, medical, legal, religious, and psychological facts, to permit the transfusion. The presentation is a close paraphrase of Wright's own case write-up. Critical expositions of five arguments explicitly advanced by Wright for his decision (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  73
    Legal and Ethical Considerations in Allowing Parental Exemptions From Newborn Critical Congenital Heart Disease (CCHD) Screening.Lisa A. Hom, Tomas J. Silber, Kathleen Ennis-Durstine, Mary Anne Hilliard & Gerard R. Martin - 2016 - American Journal of Bioethics 16 (1):11-17.
    Critical congenital heart disease screening is rapidly becoming the standard of care in the United States after being added to the Recommended Uniform Screening Panel in 2011. Newborn screens typically do not require affirmative parental consent. In fact, most states allow parents to exempt their baby from receiving the required screen on the basis of religious or personally held beliefs. There are many ethical considerations implicated with allowing parents to exempt their child from newborn screening for CCHD. Considerations include (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
1 — 50 / 994