Results for ' Legislative Intent'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. “Soames, Legislative Intent, and the Meaning of a Statute,”.Barbara Baum Levenbook - 2014 - In Lind Graham Hubbs and Douglas (ed.), Pragmatism, Law, and Language, Routledge Studies in Contemporary Philosophy vol. 11. Routledge. pp. 40-55.
    A familiar jurisprudential view is that statutes have the content the legislature intended. Scott Soames has challenged this view in one form while giving credence to it in another. The burden of his recent publications on the subject is that while legislative intent in the form of legislative purpose does not determine statutory content, some legislative intentions do. I maintain that Soames inflates the role of legislative intentions and ignores a source of pragmatic information that (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  6
    Defending Aggregated Legislative Intent.David Tan - forthcoming - Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence:1-30.
    Theories of aggregated legislative intent posit that the legislative intent of parliament is what a significant enough proportion of legislators intended (e.g., legislative intent is p if a majority intend that p). After all, many think the same way about democracy (‘votes reveal the will of the people’) and about courts (‘a court decision is based on judicial voting’). The existing literature on aggregated legislative intent, however, tends to make two undefended assumptions: (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  9
    Legislative Intentions and Counterfactu‐als: Or, What One Can Still Learn from Dworkin's Critique of Legal Positivism.Damiano Canale & Giovanni Tuzet - 2023 - Ratio Juris 36 (1):26-47.
    Riggs v. Palmerhas become famous since Dworkin used it to show that legal positivism is defective. The debate over the merits of Dworkin's claims is still very lively. Yet not enough attention has been paid to the fact that the content of the statute at issue inRiggswas given by thecounterfactual intentionof the legislature. According to arguments from legislative intent, a judicial decision is justified if it is based on the lawmaker's intention. But can legislative intentions be determined (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  6
    Legislative Intent/Essays.Gerald Cushing MacCallum - 1993 - University of Wisconsin Press.
    In the last years of his life, Gerald C. MacCallum, Jr., defied illness to continue his work on the philosophy of law. This book is a monument to MacCallum’s effort, containing fourteen of his essays, five of them published here for the first time. Two of those previously published are widely admired and reprinted: “Legislative Intent,” certainly one of the best papers ever published on its topic, and “Negative and Positive Freedom,” which offered a new way of looking (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  5.  15
    Legislative Intention Vindicated?Jeffrey Goldsworthy - 2013 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 33 (4):821-842.
    This review article examines Richard Ekins’ attempt to defend the concept of legislative intention from influential criticism, and to demonstrate its indispensable and central role in statutory interpretation. He rejects accounts of legislative intention in terms of the aggregation of the intentions of individual legislators, and instead, draws on recent philosophical work on the nature of group agency to propose a unitary model, in which the relevant intention is that of the legislature itself, although it is supported by (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6.  2
    Legislative Intent in Law's Empire.Richard Ekins - 2011 - Ratio Juris 24 (4):435-460.
    This article considers Dworkin's influential argument against legislative intent in chapter 9 of Law's Empire. The argument proves much less than is often assumed for it fails to address the possibility that the institution of the legislature may form and act on intentions. Indeed, analysis of Dworkin's argument lends support to that possibility. Dworkin aims to refute legislative intent in order to elucidate his own theory of statutory interpretation. That theory fails to explain plausibly legislative (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  3
    Legislative Intent and Legislative Supremacy: A Reply to Professor Allan.P. P. Craig - 2004 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 24 (4):585-596.
    Ten years on and the debate about the foundations of judicial review continues. Two themes have remained constant throughout. The species of legislative intent have multiplied to include specific, general and constructive intent, and who knows what further ‘adjectival variants’ remain to be discovered. Those opposed to the common law model advance dire warnings of the dangers of ignoring their preferred adjectival version. In Allan's case my previous analytical criticism of constructive legislative intent, henceforth CLI, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  4
    The Nature of Legislative Intent.Richard Ekins - 2012 - Oxford University Press.
    The idea of legislative intent plays a central role in legal interpretation and constitutional theory, yet is repeatedly challenged as being an illusion. Refuting these challenges, this book develops a robust account of how and why legislatures form intentions, and the importance of these intentions to understanding law and parliamentary democracy.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  9.  11
    Uncommon Legislative Attitudes: Why a Theory of Legislative Intent Needs Nontrivial Aggregation.David Tan - 2021 - Ratio Juris 34 (2):139-160.
    Since the publication of Ekins’ The Nature of Legislative Intent, significant attention has been paid to common attitude models of legislative intention, that is, models that require unanimity among its group members. A common interpretation of Ekins is that these common attitudes are to be preferred over aggregated attitudes. I argue that any feasible theory of legislative attitudes will require non-trivial aggregation (ie. not based on unanimity rules alone). Two arguments are put forward in this regard: (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10.  3
    Legislative Supremacy and Legislative Intent: A Reply to Professor Craig.T. R. S. Allan - 2004 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 24 (4):563-583.
    My analysis of the constitutional foundations of judicial review has been criticized by Paul Craig; but his objections confuse the ‘constructive’ account of legislative intent I defend with the ‘literal’ conception (reflecting the views of individual legislators) I expressly repudiate. He thinks we must choose between legislative intent, literally conceived, and common law principle. This mistake exemplifies the peculiar character of Craig's ‘common law model’ of judicial review, in which the requirements of the rule of law, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  37
    Authority, Democracy, and Legislative Intent.Cosmin Vraciu - 2024 - Law and Philosophy 43 (1):89-130.
    On one account, courts ought to enforce legislative intent only when the public meaning of the text of the statute is unclear, and on another account, they should enforce the intent even when the public meaning is clear. In this paper, I argue against both approaches. My argument rests on considerations related to the moral authority of the democratically made law. More specifically, I argue that those considerations which make democratic law morally authoritative entail that judges ought (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  2
    Legislative Intent and Other Essays on Law, Politics and Morality.David Estlund - 1995 - Philosophical Review 104 (4):605.
    Gerald MacCallum taught philosophy at the University of Wisconsin from 1961 until 1977. The stroke he suffered in that year prevented him from further teaching. He continued to write, even through the crippling effects of a second stroke, until his death in 1987. His final project was the Prentice Hall Foundations in Philosophy book, Political Philosophy. The present collection brings together papers, published and unpublished, spanning his writing career. I hope in this short space to convey some bigger, largely tacit (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  2
    Legislative Intention and the CISG.Olaf Meyer & André Janssen - 2009 - In Olaf Meyer & André Janssen (eds.), Cisg Methodology. Sellier de Gruyter.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  9
    From the ideal legislator to the competent speaker: uncovering the deception in legislative intent.Francesca Poggi & Francesco Ferraro - forthcoming - Jurisprudence:1-18.
    Central to the legal positivism of the nineteenth and the first half of the twentieth century was the dogma of the Ideal Legislator. Legal materials were to be interpreted as the work of an omniscient, coherent, consistent legislator. We argue that this dogma persists in the different guise of the competent speaker model, on which legal materials are the work of a competent speaker, who follows all the pertinent semantic and pragmatic rules. We will first lay out the Ideal Legislator (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. The problem of legislative intent.Eerik Lagerspetz - 2002 - In Georg Meggle (ed.), Social Facts and Collective Intentionality. Philosophische Forschung / Philosophical research. Dr. Haensel-Hohenhausen. pp. 1--167.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  5
    PHILOSOPHY OF LAW Legislative Intent and Other Essays on Law, Politics, and Morality.Deirdre Golash - 1996 - Philosophical Books 37 (2):130-131.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  19
    Marmor on Meaning, Interpretation, and Legislative Intention.Jeffrey Goldsworthy - 1995 - Legal Theory 1 (4):439-464.
    In his recent book Interpretation and Legal Theory , Andrei Marmor makes a number of claims about meaning and interpretation, both in general and in law, which I will argue are mistaken. Actually, there is some confusion in his book between what I take to be his “official” view of the nature of meaning and interpretation, and a very different view which keeps surfacing despite his official rejection of it. I will argue that this alternative, rejected view, when properly developed, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18.  6
    Statutory interpretation and the counterfactual test for legislative intention.Win-Chiat Lee - 1989 - Law and Philosophy 8 (3):383-404.
    In this paper I examine the counterfactual test for legislative intention as used in Riggs v. Palmer. The distinction between the speaker's meaning approach and the constructive interpretation approach to statutory interpretation, as made by Dworkin in Law's Empire, is explained. I argue that Dworkin underestimates the potential of the counterfactual test in making the speaker's meaning approach more plausible. I also argue that Dworkin's reasons for rejecting the counterfactual test, as proposed in Law's Empire, are either too weak (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  5
    Review of MacCallum, Marcus G. Singer and Rex Martin: Legislative Intent and Other Essays on Law, Politics, and Morality.[REVIEW]James W. Nickel - 1996 - Ethics 106 (2):466-467.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  17
    Ekins, Richard. The Nature of Legislative Intent.Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012. Pp. 303. $70.00.Gregory Bassham - 2014 - Ethics 124 (2):403-406.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  9
    Intentions and Values in Animal Welfare Legislation and Standards.Frida Lundmark, C. Berg, O. Schmid, D. Behdadi & H. Röcklinsberg - 2014 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 27 (6):991-1017.
    The focus on animal welfare in society has increased during the last 50 years. Animal welfare legislation and private standards have developed, and today many farmers within animal production have both governmental legislation and private standards to comply with. In this paper intentions and values are described that were expressed in 14 animal welfare legislation and standards in four European countries; Sweden, United Kingdom, Germany and Spain. It is also discussed if the legislation and standards actually accomplish what they, in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  22.  5
    Review: Richard Ekins, The Nature of Legislative Intent[REVIEW]Gregory Bassham - forthcoming - Philosophical Explorations.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  1
    Review: Richard Ekins, The Nature of Legislative Intent[REVIEW]Review by: Gregory Bassham - 2014 - Ethics 124 (2):403-406,.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  3
    Review of MacCallum, Marcus G. Singer and Rex Martin: Legislative Intent and Other Essays on Law, Politics, and Morality.[REVIEW]Gerald C. MacCallum - 1996 - Ethics 106 (2):466-467.
  25.  4
    Criminal Legislation against Illegal Income and Corruption: Between Good Intentions and Legitimacy.Oleg Fedosiuk - 2012 - Jurisprudencija: Mokslo darbu žurnalas 19 (3):1215-1233.
    Recently (2010–2011) new criminal legislation to combat illegal income and corruption was passed and publicly discussed in Lithuania. Within the list of the new legal measures, special attention should be paid to criminalisation of illicit enrichment, establishment of a model of extended property confiscation, reinforcement of responsibility for corruption-related offenses, a provision that not only property but also personal benefits may constitute a bribe. It can be seen from the explanatory letters attached to the draft laws and the political debate (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. Three kinds of intention in lawmaking.Marcin Matczak - 2017 - Law and Philosophy 36 (6):651-674.
    The nature of legislative intent remains a subject of vigorous debate. Its many participants perceive the intent in different ways. In this paper, I identify the reason for such diverse perceptions: three intentions are involved in lawmaking, not one. The three intentions correspond to the three aspects of a speech act: locutionary, illocutionary and perlocutionary. The dominant approach in legal theory holds that legislative intent is a semantic (locutionary) one. A closer examination shows that it (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  7
    Strategic Maneuvering with the Intention of the Legislator in the Justification of Judicial Decisions.Eveline T. Feteris - 2008 - Argumentation 22 (3):335-353.
    The author gives an analysis of the strategic manoeuvring in the justification of legal decisions from a pragma-dialectical perspective by showing how a judge tries to reconcile dialectical and rhetorical aims. On the basis of an analysis and evaluation of the argumentation given by the US Supreme Court in the famous Holy Trinity case, it is shown how in a case in which the judge wants to make an exception to a legal rule for the concrete case tries to meet (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  28.  3
    Persistent legislative state: Law, education, and the well-intentioned healthcare ethics committee. [REVIEW]Kenneth W. Goodman - 2001 - HEC Forum 13 (1):32-40.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  4
    Traités de Législation Civile Et Pénale (Classic Reprint).Jeremy Bentham & Etienne Dumont - 2017 - Forgotten Books.
    Excerpt from Traites de Legislation Civile Et PenaleMais ce n'est pas un panegyrique que je fais. Il faut bien avouer que le soin d'arranger et de polir a peu d' attraits pour le genie de l'auteur. Tant qu'il est pousse par une force creatrice, il ne sent que le plaisir de la composition. S'agit-il de donner des formes, de rediger, de finir, il n'en sent plus que la fatigue. Que l'ouvrage soit interrompu, le mal est irreparable: le charme disparait, le (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  30.  3
    Elements of Legislation.Neil Duxbury - 2012 - Cambridge University Press.
    In Elements of Legislation, Neil Duxbury examines the history of English law through the lens of legal philosophy in an effort to draw out the differences between judge-made and enacted law and to explain what courts do with the laws that legislatures enact. He presents a series of rigorously researched and carefully rehearsed arguments concerning the law-making functions of legislatures and courts, the concepts of legislative supremacy and judicial review, the nature of legislative intent and the core (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  31.  9
    Legislation as commitment – a defence of the ‘Standard Picture’ of statutory law on the basis of a commitment-based theory of communication.Marat Shardimgaliev - 2022 - Dissertation, University of Reading
    According to the Standard Picture of how law works, the content of the law that is created by legal texts such as statutes and constitutional provisions is determined by the meaning of these texts. Most proponents of this picture claim more specifically that the relevant notion of meaning in play is the communicative content of legal texts and that communicative content is itself determined by considerations of the intentions of legal authorities. In recent years, the Standard Picture has become the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  25
    The role of parliamentary intention in adjudication under the human rights act 1998.Kavanagh Aileen - 2006 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 26 (1):179-206.
    This essay gives more detailed content to the widespread view that the Human Rights Act 1998 (HRA) has changed the traditional role of parliamentary intention in statutory interpretation. It begins by outlining the various ways in which legislative intent has featured in traditional (pre-HRA) statutory interpretation. This is followed by an examination of the interpretive principles developed by the senior judiciary under the HRA case-law, focusing on the extent to which they seem to depart from traditional principles. It (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  5
    Retraction Note to: Comments on ‘Strategic Manoeuvring with the Intention of the Legislator in the Justification of Judicial Decisions’.Peter J. Schulz - 2015 - Argumentation 29 (4):493-493.
  34.  5
    Traités de Législation Civile Et Pénale (Classic Reprint).Jeremy Bentham & Etienne Dumont - 2017 - Forgotten Books.
    Excerpt from Traites de Legislation Civile Et PenaleMais ce n'est pas un panegyrique que je fais. Il faut bien avouer que le soin d'arranger et de polir a peu d' attraits pour le genie de l'auteur. Tant qu'il est pousse par une force creatrice, il ne sent que le plaisir de la composition. S'agit-il de donner des formes, de rediger, de finir, il n'en sent plus que la fatigue. Que l'ouvrage soit interrompu, le mal est irreparable: le charme disparait, le (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  35.  9
    Retracted article: Comments on ‘strategic manoeuvring with the intention of the legislator in the justification of judicial decisions’.Peter J. Schulz - 2008 - Argumentation 22 (3):355-357.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  3
    Bioethics, Legislation and Non-Human Animals.Željko Kaluđerović - 2022 - Filozofska Istrazivanja 42 (2):217-228.
    The author analyses normative acts regulating the protection of animals, both at the national level (especially in the Republic of Serbia) and at the level of supranational organisations and state unions (the Council of Europe and the European Union), but also attempts to conceptualise the terms used in the documents observing the protection of animals. From the practical and philosophical perspective, this paper considers the terms (I) “animal” (“any vertebrate animal capable of experiencing pain, suffering, fear and stress”), (II) “welfare” (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  16
    Intentionally Encouraging or Assisting Others to Commit an Offence: The Anatomy of a Language Crime.Nicci MacLeod - 2024 - International Journal for the Semiotics of Law - Revue Internationale de Sémiotique Juridique 37 (2):677-694.
    Since at least as far back as the infamous Derek Bentley case of the 1950s in which an unarmed 19-year-old was convicted and executed for murder based on his alleged uttering of the words _let him have it_ to his gun-wielding accomplice, the issue of incitement has been positioned firmly as an object of interest for forensic linguists. An example of a language crime—i.e. an unlawful speech act (as reported by Shuy in Language crimes: The use and abuse of language (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  30
    Legislative intentionalism and proxy agency.James A.. E. Macpherson - 2010 - Law and Philosophy 29 (1):1-29.
    Intentionalism is the view that statutes should be interpreted in accordance with the intentions of the legislatures that produce them. As a theory of legislative interpretation, intentionalism has been very influential, but it has also been subject to much critical attention. It is claimed that legislatures will seldom have any relevant intentions, and that even if they did, we could not come to know them. I propose a modification of intentionalism that significantly mitigates the severity of these problems. I (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  39.  23
    Comments on 'Strategic Manoeuvring with the Intention of the Legislator in the Justification of Judicial Decisions'.Peter J. Schulz - 2008 - Argumentation 22 (3):355-357.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. On the Possibility of Non-Literal Legislative Speech.Asgeirsson Hrafn - 2017 - In Alessandro Capone & Francesca Poggi (eds.), Pragmatics and Law: Theoretical and Practical Perspectives. Springer. pp. 67–101.
    The existing literature on indeterminacy in the law focuses mostly on the use of vague terms in legislation – terms the use of which makes the content of the relevant utterance to some extent indeterminate. As I aim to show, however, not only is the content of a legislative utterance often indeterminate, it is often indeterminate what the content of such an utterance is. In the first two sections of the paper, I discuss in some detail the conditions for (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  18
    Abortion policies at the bedside: incorporating an ethical framework in the analysis and development of abortion legislation.Alicia E. Hersey, Jai-Me Potter-Rutledge & Benjamin P. Brown - 2024 - Journal of Medical Ethics 50 (1):2-5.
    About 6% of women in the world live in countries that ban all abortions, and 34% in countries that only allow abortion to preserve maternal life or health. In the USA, over the last decades—even before Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Organization overturned the federal right to abortion—various states have sought to restrict abortion access. Often times, this legislation has been advanced based on legislators’ personal moral values. At the bedside, in contrast, provision of abortion care should adhere to the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  42. Machine generated contents note: Introduction / Eve Grace and Christopher Kelly; Part I. Politics and Economics: 1. Rousseau and the illustrious Montesquieu / Christopher Kelly; 2. Political economy and individual liberty / Ryan Patrick Hanley; Part II. Science and Epistemology: 3. The presence of sciences in Rousseau's trajectory and works / Bruno Bernardi and Bernadette Bensaud-Vincent; 4. Epistemology and political perception in the case of Rousseau / Terence Marshall; Part III. The Modern or Classical, Theological or Philosophical, Foundations of Rousseau's System: 5. On the intention of Rousseau / Leo Strauss; 6. On Strauss on Rousseau / Victor Gourevitch; 7. Built on sand: moral law in Rousseau's Second Discourse / Victor Gourevitch; 8. Rousseau and Pascal / Matthew W. Maguire; Part IV. Rousseau as Educator and Legislator: 9. The measure of the possible: imagination in Rousseau's philosophical pedagogy / Richard Velkley; 10. Rousseau's French revolution / Pamela K. Jensen; 11. Ro. [REVIEW]Pierre Manent - 2012 - In Eve Grace & Christopher Kelly (eds.), The Challenge of Rousseau. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  4
    Intention in Hybrid Organizations: The Diffusion of the Business Metaphor in Swedish Laws.Jan Bröchner, Karsten Åström & Stefan Larsson - 2015 - International Journal for the Semiotics of Law - Revue Internationale de Sémiotique Juridique 28 (2):371-386.
    Recent studies of conceptual metaphors in a legal context have often dealt with the power of embodiment. However, the connotations of culturally originated metaphors could be different when they appear in laws and regulations. In particular, the role of metaphor when the legislator wishes to define intention in hybrid organizations is investigated here. The case studied is how a conceptual metaphor of ‘business’ manifesting itself in the Swedish simile adjective affärsmässig has spread over 40 years. ‘Business’ early on acquired connotations (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  2
    Paradigm intention.A. P. Simester - 1992 - Law and Philosophy 11 (3):235 - 263.
    Antony Duff's recent account of intended action has aroused considerable interest, particularly amongst English commentators, as an attempt to provide criteria that might be utilised by a judge or legislator. While Duff's analysis is instructive, and although it may be desirable to find conditions capturing the central notion of intention in action, this paper demonstrates that the specific conditions proposed by Duff are unsatisfactory. They require extensive modification in order to circumvent a number of difficulties presented here.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  11
    Inspiring Respect for Animals Through the Law? Current Development in the Norwegian Animal Welfare Legislation.Ellen-Marie Forsberg - 2011 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 24 (4):351-366.
    Over the last years, Norway has revised its animal welfare legislation. As of January 1, 2010, the Animal Protection Act of 1974 was replaced by a new Animal Welfare Act. This paper describes the developments in the normative structures from the old to the new act, as well as the main traits of the corresponding implementation and governance system. In the Animal Protection Act, the basic animal ethics principles were to avoid suffering, treat animals well, and consider their natural needs (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  46.  8
    The Authoritative Intention Thesis.Torben Spaak - unknown
    Joseph Raz defends the authoritative intention thesis, which has it that to the extent that law derives from deliberate law-making, its interpretation should reflect the intention of the law-maker. The idea is that as a matter of conceptual necessity, if one follows legislation, then one interprets the relevant piece of legislation in such a way that it reflects the intention of the law-maker. Raz’s position, then, is that legal content (as well as form) that is the result of deliberate law-making (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  38
    Vagueness, counterfactual intentions, and legal interpretation.Natalie Stoljar - 2001 - Legal Theory 7 (4):447-465.
    "My argument is as follows. In the first section, I sketch briefly the ways in which intentionalism might provide a solution to the problem of vagueness. The second section describes the different areas in which counterfactuals must be invoked by intentionalism. In the third section I point out that on a classic analysis of counterfactuals - that of David Lewis and Robert Stalnaker - the truth conditions of counterfactuals depend on relations of similarity among possible worlds. Since similarity is vague, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  48.  1
    Foucault’s functional justice and its relationship to legislators and popular illegalism.Sylvain Lafleur - 2018 - Foucault Studies 24:58-76.
    This article presents two of Foucault’s lesser known notions, “justice fonctionnelle" and “stratégie du pourtour”, in order to interrogate the role of legislators in regard to the policing of political dissent. This article contains three parts. First, I present the two lesser known notions referred to above. Then, I provide my understanding of the role of law for Foucault. Finally, in the third part, I explain how a consensual relationship between the police and legislators is established. I present briefly the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  7
    Euthanasia, Intentions, and the Doctrine of Killing and Letting Die.Kai-Yee Wong - 2007 - In A. Yeung & H. Li (eds.), New Essays in Applied Ethics: Animal Rights, Personhood, and the Ethics of Killing. New York: Palgrave McMillan.
    In 1996, the 9th Circuit Court of Appeal of United States ruled that a Washington law banning physician-assisted suicide was unconstitutional. In the same year, the 2nd Circuit found a similar law in New York unconstitutional. One year later, the U.S. Supreme Court reversed both rulings, saying that there was no constitutional right to assisted suicide. However, the Court also made plain that they did not reject such a right in principle and that “citizens are free to press for permissive (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  14
    The Effects of Contextual and Wrongdoing Attributes on Organizational Employees' Whistleblowing Intentions Following Fraud.Shani N. Robinson, Jesse C. Robertson & Mary B. Curtis - 2012 - Journal of Business Ethics 106 (2):213-227.
    Recent financial fraud legislation such as the Dodd–Frank Act and the Sarbanes–Oxley Act (U.S. House of Representatives, Dodd-Frank Wall Street Reform and Consumer Protection Act of 2010, [H.R. 4173], 2010 ; U.S. House of Representatives, The Sarbanes–Oxley Act of 2002, Public Law 107-204 [H.R. 3763], 2002 ) relies heavily on whistleblowers for enforcement, and offers protection and incentives for whistleblowers. However, little is known about many aspects of the whistleblowing decision, especially the effects of contextual and wrongdoing attributes on organizational (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000