15 found
Order:
Disambiguations
Jeffrey Goldsworthy [11]Jeffrey Denys Goldsworthy [5]Jeffrey D. Goldsworthy [1]
  1.  88
    Well-Being and Value.Jeffrey Goldsworthy - 1992 - Utilitas 4 (1):1.
    Something can be said to be good for a particular person, whether or not it is good for anyone else, let alone good ‘overall’ or ‘good simpliciter ’. Sometimes we speak of ‘John's good’ as well as of things that are ‘good for John’. What is ‘good for John’ is whatever enhances his ‘good’ or, to use an apparently synonymous term, his ‘well-being’. But what is a person's well-being: in what does it consist?
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  2.  42
    Externalism, internalism and moral scepticism.Jeffrey Goldsworthy - 1992 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 70 (1):40 – 60.
    In "Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics", David Brink defendsexternalist moral realism against Mackie's sceptical arguments, whichpresuppose some kind of internalism. But Brink confuses the issues by failing to distinguish different kinds of internalism. What he calls conceptual internalism may be false, but Mackie can retreat to sociological internalism, which holds that most people believe moral requirements to be capable of motivating action regardless of pre-existing desires. Brink does not challenge that thesis, which isall that Mackie's sceptical arguments necessarily (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  3. The case for originalism.Jeffrey Goldsworthy - 2011 - In Grant Huscroft & Bradley W. Miller (eds.), The Challenge of Originalism: Essays in Constitutional Theory. Cambridge University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  4. Constitutional interpretation: Originalism.Jeffrey Goldsworthy - 2009 - Philosophy Compass 4 (4):682-702.
    Constitutional interpretation is problematic because it can be difficult to distinguish legitimate interpretation from illegitimate change. The distinction depends largely on what a constitution is. A constitution, like any other law, necessarily has a meaning, which pre-exists judicial interpretation: it is not a set of meaningless marks on paper. Any plausible constitutional theory must offer an account of the nature of that meaning. In doing so, it must address two main questions. The first is whether the meaning of the constitution (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  5.  43
    Legislative Intention Vindicated?Jeffrey Goldsworthy - 2013 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 33 (4):821-842.
    This review article examines Richard Ekins’ attempt to defend the concept of legislative intention from influential criticism, and to demonstrate its indispensable and central role in statutory interpretation. He rejects accounts of legislative intention in terms of the aggregation of the intentions of individual legislators, and instead, draws on recent philosophical work on the nature of group agency to propose a unitary model, in which the relevant intention is that of the legislature itself, although it is supported by the ‘interlocking’ (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6.  32
    The Sovereignty of Parliament: History and Philosophy.Jeffrey Denys Goldsworthy - 1999 - Oxford University Press UK.
    In British constitutional law, the doctrine of parliamentary sovereignty maintains that Parliament has unlimited legislative authority. Critics have recently challenged this doctrine, on historical and philosophical grounds. This book describes its historical origins and development.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  7.  7
    Judicial Power, Democracy and Legal Positivism.Tom Campbell, Jeffrey Goldsworthy & Jeffrey Denys Goldsworthy - 2017 - Routledge.
    In this book, a distinguished international group of legal theorists re-examine legal positivism as a prescriptive political theory and consider its implications for the constitutionally defined roles of legislatures and courts. The issues are illustrated with recent developments in Australian constitutional law.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8. The Sovereignty of Parliament: History and Philosophy.Jeffrey Denys Goldsworthy - 1999 - Oxford University Press UK.
    The doctrine of parliamentary sovereignty has long been regarded as the most fundamental element of the British Constitution. It holds that Parliament has unlimited legislative authority, and that the courts have no authority to judge statutes invalid. This doctrine has now been criticized on historical and philosophical grounds and critics claim that it is a relatively recent invention of academic lawyers that superseded an earlier tradition in which Parliament's authority was limited to common law. The critics also argue that it (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9.  40
    Marmor on Meaning, Interpretation, and Legislative Intention.Jeffrey Goldsworthy - 1995 - Legal Theory 1 (4):439-464.
    In his recent book Interpretation and Legal Theory , Andrei Marmor makes a number of claims about meaning and interpretation, both in general and in law, which I will argue are mistaken. Actually, there is some confusion in his book between what I take to be his “official” view of the nature of meaning and interpretation, and a very different view which keeps surfacing despite his official rejection of it. I will argue that this alternative, rejected view, when properly developed, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10.  45
    Raz on constitutional interpretation.Jeffrey Goldsworthy - 2003 - Law and Philosophy 22 (2):167-193.
  11.  43
    Protecting Human Rights: Instruments and Institutions.Tom Campbell, Jeffrey Denys Goldsworthy & Adrienne Sarah Ackary Stone (eds.) - 2003 - Oxford University Press.
    What should and what should not to be counted as a human right? What does it mean to identify a right as a human right? And what are the most effective and legitimate means of promoting human rights? This book addresses these questions and the complex relationship between the answers to them.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12. Judicial Review, Legislative Override, and Democracy.Jeffrey Goldsworthy - 2003 - In Tom Campbell, Jeffrey Goldsworthy & Adrienne Stone (eds.), Protecting Human Rights: Instruments and Institutions. Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13. Nozick's Libertarianism and the Justification of the State.Jeffrey D. Goldsworthy - 1987 - Ratio (Misc.) 29 (2):180.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  25
    Some Scepticism about Moral Realism.Jeffrey Goldsworthy - 1995 - Law and Philosophy 14 (3/4):357 - 374.
    The lesson is that while externalists avoid devastating objections to internalist moral realism, they thereby sacrifice most of thepractical significance of moral realism as an alternative to noncognitivism. They defend the objectivity of moral beliefs, but are forced to concede that the practical relevance and appeal of those beliefs depends on subjective desires. It is because they correctly reject internalism that they succumb to the non-cognitivists'tu quoque.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  36
    Balkin, Jack. Constitutional Redemption. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2011. Pp. 304. $35.00 .Balkin, Jack. Living Originalism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2011. Pp. 480. $35.00. [REVIEW]Jeffrey Goldsworthy - 2012 - Ethics 122 (4):785-790.