Results for 'Keith Schoville'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  21
    Archaeology and Biblical Interpretation.Keith N. Schoville, Leo G. Purdue, Lawrence E. Toombs & Gary Lance Johnson - 1990 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 110 (3):572.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  17
    Recovering Sarepta, a Phoenician City.Keith N. Schoville & James B. Pritchard - 1981 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 101 (4):440.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3.  11
    B'b edh-Dhr'ʿ: Excavations in the Cemetery Directed by Paul W. Lapp (1965-67)Bab edh-Dhra: Excavations in the Cemetery Directed by Paul W. Lapp. [REVIEW]Keith N. Schoville, R. Thomas Schaub & Walter E. Rast - 1992 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 112 (3):491.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  21
    Sign, Symbol, Script: An Exhibition on the Origins of Writing and the Alphabet.Martin Bernal, Martha L. Carter & Keith Schoville - 1985 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 105 (4):736.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  53
    Reference and definite descriptions.Keith S. Donnellan - 1966 - Philosophical Review 75 (3):281-304.
    Definite descriptions, I shall argue, have two possible functions. 1] They are used to refer to what a speaker wishes to talk about, but they are also used quite differently. Moreover, a definite description occurring in one and the same sentence may, on different occasions of its use, function in either way. The failure to deal with this duality of function obscures the genuine referring use of definite descriptions. The best known theories of definite descriptions, those of Russell and Strawson, (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   751 citations  
  6. Solving the skeptical problem.Keith DeRose - 1995 - Philosophical Review 104 (1):1-52.
  7.  59
    Knowledge: Undefeated justified true belief.Keith Lehrer & Thomas Paxson - 1969 - Journal of Philosophy 66 (8):225-237.
    The recently offered, Purported counter-Examples to justified, True belief analyses of knowledge are looked at with some care and all found to be either incoherent or inconclusive. It is argued that justified, True belief analyses are based on sound insight into the concept of knowledge. The distinction between having been justified in claiming to know something and actually having known it is used in an effort to get the discussion of knowledge back on the right track.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   153 citations  
  8.  29
    Epistemic possibilities.Keith DeRose - 1991 - Philosophical Review 100 (4):581-605.
  9.  40
    Action, Emotion and Will.Keith S. Donnellan - 1965 - Philosophical Review 74 (4):526.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   118 citations  
  10.  8
    Hobbes’ Citizen.Keith Algozin - 1975 - Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 49:198-207.
  11. Hallucination And Imagination.Keith Allen - 2015 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 93 (2):287-302.
    What are hallucinations? A common view in the philosophical literature is that hallucinations are degenerate kinds of perceptual experience. I argue instead that hallucinations are degenerate kinds of sensory imagination. As well as providing a good account of many actual cases of hallucination, the view that hallucination is a kind of imagination represents a promising account of hallucination from the perspective of a disjunctivist theory of perception like naïve realism. This is because it provides a way of giving a positive (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  12. Knowledge, assertion and lotteries.Keith DeRose - 1996 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74 (4):568–580.
    In some lottery situations, the probability that your ticket's a loser can get very close to 1. Suppose, for instance, that yours is one of 20 million tickets, only one of which is a winner. Still, it seems that (1) You don't know yours is a loser and (2) You're in no position to flat-out assert that your ticket is a loser. "It's probably a loser," "It's all but certain that it's a loser," or even, "It's quite certain that it's (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   95 citations  
  13.  31
    Care of Self in Dawn: On Nietzsche’s Resistance to Bio-political Modernity.Keith Ansell-Pearson - 2014 - In Manuel Knoll & Barry Stocker (eds.), Nietzsche as Political Philosopher. Boston: De Gruyter. pp. 269-286.
  14.  14
    Thomas Reid.Keith Lehrer - 1989 - New York: Routledge.
    This book is available either individually, or as part of the specially-priced Arguments of the Philosphers Collection.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  15.  12
    When rational disagreement is impossible.Keith Lehrer - 1976 - Noûs 10 (3):327-332.
  16. Why Not Scepticism?Keith Lehrer - 1971 - Philosophical Forum 2 (3):283.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  17.  17
    How reasons give us knowledge, or the case of the gypsy lawyer.Keith Lehrer - 1971 - Journal of Philosophy 68 (10):311-313.
  18.  37
    Self-Trust: A Study of Reason, Knowledge and Autonomy.Keith Lehrer - 1999 - Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 59 (4):1049-1055.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  19.  23
    Single scoreboard semantics.Keith DeRose - 2004 - Philosophical Studies 119 (1-2):1-21.
    What happens to the "conversational score" when speakers in a conversation push the score for a context-sensitive term in different directions? In epistemology, contextualists are often construed as holding that both the skeptic ("You don't know!") and her opponent ("Oh, yes I do!") speak truthfully when they debate. This assumes a "multiple scoreboards" version of contextualism. But contextualists themselves typically opt for "single scoreboard" views on which such apparently competing claims really do conflict. This paper explores several single scoreboard options (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  20. The Value of Perception.Keith Allen - 2019 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 100 (3):633-656.
    This paper develops a form of transcendental naïve realism. According to naïve realism, veridical perceptual experiences are essentially relational. According to transcendental naïve realism, the naïve realist theory of perception is not just one theory of perception amongst others, to be established as an inference to the best explanation and assessed on the basis of a cost-benefit analysis that weighs performance along a number of different dimensions: for instance, fidelity to appearances, simplicity, systematicity, fit with scientific theories, and so on. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  21.  62
    Matter and Consciousness: A Contemporary Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind.Keith Gunderson - 1986 - Philosophy of Science 53 (1):145-148.
  22.  41
    Epistemic injustice in Climate Adaptation.Morten Byskov & Keith Hyams - 2022 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 25 (4):613-634.
    Indigenous peoples are disproportionally vulnerable to climate change. At the same time, they possess valuable knowledge for fair and sustainable climate adaptation planning and policymaking. Yet Indigenous peoples and knowledges are often excluded from or underrepresented within adaptation plans and policies. In this paper we ask whether the concept of epistemic injustice can be applied to the context of climate adaptation and the underrepresentation of Indigenous knowledges within adaptation policies and strategies. In recent years, the concept of epistemic injustice has (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  18
    Freedom and Determinism. Contributors: Roderick M. Chisholm And Others.Keith Lehrer (ed.) - 1966 - New York,: Random House.
  24.  50
    Good Without Knowing it: Subtle Contextual Cues can Activate Moral Identity and Reshape Moral Intuition.Keith Leavitt, Lei Zhu & Karl Aquino - 2016 - Journal of Business Ethics 137 (4):785-800.
    The role of moral intuition has been increasingly implicated in business decisions and ethical business behavior. But troublingly, because implicit processes often operate outside of conscious awareness, decision makers are generally unaware of their influence. We tested whether subtle contextual cues for identity can alter implicit beliefs. In two studies, we found that contextual cues which nonconsciously prime moral identity weaken the implicit association between the categories of “business” and “ethical,” an implicit association which has previously been linked to unethical (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  25. Colour Physicalism, Naïve Realism, and the Argument from Structure.Keith Allen - 2015 - Minds and Machines 25 (2):193-212.
    Colours appear to instantiate a number of structural properties: for instance, they stand in distinctive relations of similarity and difference, and admit of a fundamental distinction into unique and binary. Accounting for these structural properties is often taken to present a serious problem for physicalist theories of colour. This paper argues that a prominent attempt by Byrne and Hilbert to account for the structural properties of the colours, consistent with the claim that colours are types of surface spectral reflectance, is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  26.  73
    Unnatural Doubts: Epistemological Realism and the Basis of Scepticism.Keith DeRose & Michael Williams - 1993 - Philosophical Review 102 (4):604.
  27. Thomas Reid.Keith LEHRER - 1989 - Philosophy 66 (256):252-254.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  28.  19
    Conditional assertions and "biscuit" conditionals.Keith DeRose & Richard E. Grandy - 1999 - Noûs 33 (3):405-420.
    kind of joke to ask what is the case if the antecedent is false—“And where are the biscuits if I don’t want any?”, “And what’s on PBS if I’m not interested?”, “And who shot Kennedy if that’s not what I’m asking?”. With normal indicative conditionals like.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  29. How Can We Know that We're Not Brains in Vats?Keith DeRose - 2000 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 38 (S1):121-148.
    This should be fairly close to the text of this paper as it appears in The Southern Journal of Philosophy 38 (2000), Spindel Conference Supplement: 121-148.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  30.  15
    Locating The Unique Hues.Keith Allen - 2010 - Rivista di Estetica 43:13-28.
    Variations in colour perception have featured prominently in recent attempts to argue against the view that colours are objective mind-independent properties of the perceptual environment. My aim in this paper is to defend the view that colours are mind-independent properties in response to worries arising from one type of empirically documented case of perceptual variation: variation in the perception of the «unique hues». §1 sets out the challenge raised by variation in the perception of the unique hues. I argue in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  31.  6
    What Intentionality Is Like.Keith Lehrer - 2011 - Acta Analytica 26 (1):3-14.
    Intentionality is a mark of the mental, as Brentano (1874) noted. Any representation or conception of anything has the feature of intentionality, which informally put, is the feature of being about something that may or may not exist. Visual artworks are about something, whether something literal or abstract. The artwork is a mentalized physical object. Aesthetic experience of the artwork illustrates the nature of intentionality as we focus attention on the phenomenology of the sensory exemplar. This focus of attention on (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  32.  16
    Time, truth and modalities.Keith Lehrer & Richard Taylor - 1965 - Mind 74 (295):390-398.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  33.  38
    How to use imaginary cases in normative theory.Keith Dowding - 2022 - Metaphilosophy 53 (4):512-525.
    This paper defends the use of imaginary cases in normative theorizing. Imaginary cases are used as a part of an argument and should be assessed in terms of the role they play within arguments. The paper identifies five ways in which they are used and then uses some of the best examples to bring out how they contribute to debates. While not directly akin to empirical experiments, criticisms of imaginary cases can be represented in terms of the well‐known distinction between (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34. Metamind.Keith Lehrer - 1992 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 182 (4):547-547.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  35.  18
    “Marked” Bodies, Medical Intervention, and Courageous Humility: Spiritual Identity Formation in Nathaniel Hawthorne’s The Birthmark.Keith Dow - 2022 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 47 (5):625-637.
    Nathaniel Hawthorne’s The Birthmark offers a sharp lens through which to examine power, purity, and personal identity. Scientist and spiritual idealist, Aylmer, is obsessed with “correcting” the only flaw he perceives in his wife Georgina, the imprint of a small red hand on her pale cheek. For Alymer, this one “imperfection” reaches deep into Georgina’s heart, a sign of sin, decay, and mortality. It is the natural that must be overcome with science. Drawing on Hawthorne’s tragic fiction, this paper questions (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  36
    Manipulation in politics and public policy.Keith Dowding & Alexandra Oprea - forthcoming - Economics and Philosophy:1-26.
    Many philosophical accounts of manipulation are blind to the extent to which actual people fall short of the rational ideal, while prominent accounts in political science are under-inclusive. We offer necessary and sufficient conditions – Suitable Reason and Testimonial Honesty – distinguishing manipulative from non-manipulative influence; develop a ‘hypothetical disclosure test’ to measure the degree of manipulation; and provide further criteria to assess and compare the morality of manipulation across cases. We discuss multiple examples drawn from politics and from public (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  41
    Learning During Processing: Word Learning Doesn't Wait for Word Recognition to Finish.S. Apfelbaum Keith & McMurray Bob - 2017 - Cognitive Science 41 (S4):706-747.
    Previous research on associative learning has uncovered detailed aspects of the process, including what types of things are learned, how they are learned, and where in the brain such learning occurs. However, perceptual processes, such as stimulus recognition and identification, take time to unfold. Previous studies of learning have not addressed when, during the course of these dynamic recognition processes, learned representations are formed and updated. If learned representations are formed and updated while recognition is ongoing, the result of learning (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  38.  15
    Relevant Alternatives and the Content of Knowledge Attributions.Keith Derose - 1996 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (1):193-197.
    In “Contextualism and Knowledge Attributions,” I argue that advocates of the “Relevant Alternatives” theory of knowledge fall into certain mistakes result if they tie the content of a knowledge attribution, on a given occasion of use, too tightly to what the range of relevant alternatives is on that occasion, and I sketch an alternative approach to the issues involved that avoids such mistakes. In “The Shifting Content of Knowledge Attributions,” Anthony Brueckner charges that my own account of these matters falls (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  39. Lewis on ‘Might’ and ‘Would’ Counterfactual Conditionals.Keith DeRose - 1994 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 24 (3):413-418.
    Letting denote ‘would’ counterfactual conditionals like If I had looked in my pocket, I would have found a penny and letting denote ‘might’ counterfactual conditionals like If I had looked in my pocket, I might have found a penny,David Lewis’s thesis regarding the connection between these two types of conditionals is that.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  40.  4
    Personal and social knowledge.Keith Lehrer - 1987 - Synthese 73 (1):87 - 107.
    This paper is an investigation of the relation between personal and social conditions of knowledge. A coherence theory of knowledge and justification is assumed, according to which incoming information is evaluated in terms of background information. The evaluation of incoming information in terms of background information is a higher order or metamental activity. Personal knowledge and justification is based on the coherent integration of individual information. Social knowledge and justification is based on the coherent aggregation of social information, that is, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  41. The Coherence Theory of Knowledge.Keith Lehrer - 2000 - In Sven Bernecker & Fred I. Dretske (eds.), Knowledge: readings in contemporary epistemology. New York: Oxford University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  42.  31
    Being coloured and looking coloured.Keith Allen - 2009 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 39 (4):pp. 647-670.
    What is the relationship between being coloured and looking coloured? According to Alva Noë, to be coloured is to manifest a pattern of apparent colours as the perceptual conditions vary. I argue that Noë’s ‘phenomenal objectivism’ faces similar objections to attempts by traditional dispositionalist theories of colour to account for being coloured in terms of looking coloured. Instead, I suggest that to be coloured is to look coloured in a ‘non-perspectival’ sense, where non-perspectival looks transcend specific perceptual conditions.
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  43.  11
    Sensitivity, Indiscernibility and Knowledge.Keith Lehrer - 2000 - Philosophical Issues 10 (1):33-37.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  44.  11
    Sosa, Safety, Sensitivity, and Skeptical Hypotheses.Keith DeRose - 2004 - In John Greco (ed.), Ernest Sosa and His Critics. Malden, MA, USA: Blackwell. pp. 22–41.
    This chapter contains section titled: Sensitivity Accounts — Direct and Indirect The Attack by Counterexample on Sensitivity Accounts — And Why SCA Seems on the Right Track Nonetheless Sosa's Safety Account Sosa's Account as a Sensitivity Account — and His Counterexamples Safety and the Problem of True/True Subjunctives Other Formulations of Safety Safety and Strength of Epistemic Position Contextualist Solutions to Skepticism Intuitive Complexity: Do We Know that We're Not Brains in Vats?
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  45. Locke and the Nature of Ideas.Keith Allen - 2010 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 92 (3):236-255.
    What, according to Locke, are ideas? I argue that Locke does not give an account of the nature of ideas. In the Essay, the question is simply set to one side, as recommended by the “Historical, plain Method” that Locke employs. This is exemplified by his characterization of ‘ideas’ in E I.i.8, and the discussion of the inverted spectrum hypothesis in E II.xxxii. In this respect, Locke's attitude towards the nature of ideas in the Essay is reminiscent of Boyle's diffident (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  46.  11
    Reid's anti-sensationalism and his realism.Keith DeRose - 1989 - Philosophical Review 98 (3):313-348.
  47.  11
    Time, Truth and Modalities.Keith Lehrer & Richard Taylor - 1967 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 32 (3):401-402.
  48.  4
    The fallibility paradox.Keith Lehrer & Kihyeon Kim - 1990 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50:99-107.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  49.  1
    Met aknowledge: Undefeated justification.Keith Lehrer - 1988 - Synthese 74 (3):329 - 347.
    Internalism and externalism are both false. What is needed to convert true belief into knowledge is the appropriate blend of subjective and objective factors to yield the appropriate sort of connection between mind and the world. The sort of knowledge explicated is calledmetaknowledge and is knowledge that involves the evaluation of incoming information in terms of a background system. It is proposed that knowledge is equivalent to undefeated justification which is justification on the basis of every system that eliminates or (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  50.  63
    Freedom of Preference: A Defense of Compatiblism.Keith Lehrer - 2016 - The Journal of Ethics 20 (1-3):35-46.
    Harry G. Frankfurt has presented a case of a counterfactual intervener CI with knowledge and power to control an agent so he will do A. He concludes that if the agent prefers to do A and there is no intervention by CI, the agent has acted of his own free will and is morally responsible for doing A, though he lacked an alternative possibility. I consider the consequences for freedom and moral responsibility of CI having a complete plan P for (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000