Results for 'Alfred Goodwin'

(not author) ( search as author name )
1000+ found
Order:
  1.  22
    Critical notices.Alfred Goodwin - 1886 - Mind (41):117-119.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  5
    Verrall's ion of Euripides. [REVIEW]Alfred Goodwin - 1891 - The Classical Review 5 (3):97-98.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  28
    Prophetic Evangelicals: Envisioning a Just and Peaceable Kingdom ed. by Bruce Ellis Benson, Malinga Elizabeth Berry, and Peter Goodwin Heltzel, and: Bearing True Witness: Truthfulness in Christian Practice by Craig Hovey.Guenther “Gene” Haas - 2014 - Journal of the Society of Christian Ethics 34 (2):221-224.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Prophetic Evangelicals: Envisioning a Just and Peaceable Kingdom ed. by Bruce Ellis Benson, Malinga Elizabeth Berry, and Peter Goodwin Heltzel, and: Bearing True Witness: Truthfulness in Christian Practice by Craig HoveyGuenther “Gene” HaasReview of Prophetic Evangelicals: Envisioning a Just and Peaceable Kingdom EDITED BY BRUCE ELLIS BENSON, MALINGA ELIZABETH BERRY, AND PETER GOODWIN HELTZEL Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2012. 225 pp. $35.00Review of Bearing True Witness: (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Free Will and Luck.Alfred R. Mele - 2006 - New York, US: Oxford University Press.
    Mele's ultimate purpose in this book is to help readers think more clearly about free will. He identifies and makes vivid the most important conceptual obstacles to justified belief in the existence of free will and meets them head on. Mele clarifies the central issues in the philosophical debate about free will and moral responsibility, criticizes various influential contemporary theories about free will, and develops two overlapping conceptions of free will--one for readers who are convinced that free will is incompatible (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   328 citations  
  5. Free will and luck: Reply to critics.Alfred R. Mele - 2007 - Philosophical Explorations 10 (2):153 – 155.
    Mele's ultimate purpose in this book is to help readers think more clearly about free will. He identifies and makes vivid the most important conceptual obstacles to justified belief in the existence of free will and meets them head on. Mele clarifies the central issues in the philosophical debate about free will and moral responsibility, criticizes various influential contemporary theories about free will, and develops two overlapping conceptions of free will--one for readers who are convinced that free will is incompatible (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   144 citations  
  6.  13
    Process and reality.Alfred North Whitehead - 1957 - New York,: Macmillan. Edited by David Ray Griffin & Donald W. Sherburne.
    One of the major philosophical texts of the 20th century, Process and Reality is based on Alfred North Whitehead’s influential lectures that he delivered at the University of Edinburgh in the 1920s on process philosophy. Whitehead’s master work in philsophy, Process and Reality propounds a system of speculative philosophy, known as process philosophy, in which the various elements of reality into a consistent relation to each other. It is also an exploration of some of the preeminent thinkers of the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  7. Real Self-Deception.Alfred R. Mele - 1997 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 20 (1):91-102.
    Self-deception poses tantalizing conceptual conundrums and provides fertile ground for empirical research. Recent interdisciplinary volumes on the topic feature essays by biologists, philosophers, psychiatrists, and psychologists (Lockard & Paulhus 1988, Martin 1985). Self-deception's location at the intersection of these disciplines is explained by its significance for questions of abiding interdisciplinary interest. To what extent is our mental life present--or even accessible--to consciousness? How rational are we? How is motivated irrationality to be explained? To what extent are our beliefs subject to (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   92 citations  
  8. The psychology of meta-ethics: Exploring objectivism.Geoffrey P. Goodwin & John M. Darley - 2008 - Cognition 106 (3):1339-1366.
  9.  3
    Seminar on the Dual Unity and the Phantom.Abraham Nicolas & Goodwin Tom - 2016 - Diacritics 44 (4):14-38.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10. Über den Begriff der Logischen Folgerung.Alfred Tarski - 1937 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 2 (2):83-84.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   79 citations  
  11. Kane, luck, and the significance of free will.Alfred R. Mele - 1999 - Philosophical Explorations 2 (2):96-104.
    This paper raises a pair of objections to the novel libertarian position advanced in Robert Kane's recent book, The Significance of Free Will.The first objection's target is a central element in Kane's intriguing response to what he calls the "Intelligibility" and "Existence" questions about free will. It is argued that this response is undermined by considerations of luck.The second objection is directed at a portion of Kane's answer to what he calls "The Significance Question" about free will: "Why do we, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  12.  36
    A Decision Method for Elementary Algebra and Geometry.Alfred Tarski - 1952 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 17 (3):207-207.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   76 citations  
  13. Why are some moral beliefs perceived to be more objective than others.Geoffrey Goodwin & John M. Darley - 2012 - Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 48 (1):250-256.
    Recent research has investigated whether people think of their moral beliefs as objectively true facts about the world, or as subjective preferences. The present research examines variability in the perceived objectivity of different moral beliefs, with respect both to the content of moral beliefs themselves (what they are about), and to the social representation of those moral beliefs (whether other individuals are thought to hold them). It also examines the possible consequences of perceiving a moral belief as objective. With respect (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  14. Twisted Self Deception.Alfred R. Mele - 1999 - Philosophical Psychology 12 (2):117-137.
    In instances of "twisted" self-deception, people deceive themselves into believing things that they do not want to be true. In this, twisted self-deception differs markedly from the "straight" variety that has dominated the philosophical and psychological literature on self-deception. Drawing partly upon empirical literature, I develop a trio of approaches to explaining twisted self-deception: a motivation-centered approach; an emotion-centered approach; and a hybrid approach featuring both motivation and emotion. My aim is to display our resources for exploring and explaining twisted (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  15. Manipulation, Moral Responsibility, and Bullet Biting.Alfred R. Mele - 2013 - The Journal of Ethics 17 (3):167-184.
    This article’s guiding question is about bullet biting: When should compatibilists about moral responsibility bite the bullet in responding to stories used in arguments for incompatibilism about moral responsibility? Featured stories are vignettes in which agents’ systems of values are radically reversed by means of brainwashing and the story behind the zygote argument. The malady known as “intuition deficit disorder” is also discussed.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  16. A critique of Pereboom's 'four-case argument' for incompatibilism.Alfred R. Mele - 2005 - Analysis 65 (1):75-80.
    One popular style of argument for the thesis that determinism is incompatible with moral responsibility features manipulation. Its thrust is that regarding moral responsibility, there is no important difference between various cases of manipulation in which agents who A are not morally responsible for A-ing and ordinary cases of A-ing in deterministic worlds. There is a detailed argument of this kind in Derk Pereboom’s recent book (2001: 112–26). His strategy in what he calls his ‘four-case argument’ (117) is to describe (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  17.  83
    Recent work on self-deception.Alfred R. Mele - 1987 - American Philosophical Quarterly 24 (1):1-17.
    I start, in Section I, with the case for skepticism about the possibility of self-deception. In Sections II and III, I review attempts to explain how self-deception, conceived on a strict interpersonal model, is possible. Section IV addresses a variety of analyses of self-deception that involve modest departures from these strict models and canvasses associated attacks on the standard paradoxes. The emphasis there is on the static paradoxes, discussion of their dynamic coun terparts being reserved largely for Section V. Section (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  18. Self-deception.Alfred R. Mele - 1983 - Philosophical Quarterly 33 (October):366-377.
    Self-Deception, Properly understood, Is not paradoxical. Although self-Deception involves motivated false belief, It is not properly modeled after "intentional" interpersonal deception. Thus, The major source of paradox is dissolved. Moreover, Even intentional self-Deception need not be paradoxical and there is good reason to believe that a kind of self-Deception which "would" be paradoxical never occurs. Finally, In cases of self-Deception, As in instances of akratic action, There is scope for blame.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  19. Situationism and Agency.Alfred R. Mele & Joshua Shepherd - 2013 - Journal of Practical Ethics 1 (1):62-83.
    Research in psychology indicates that situations powerfully impact human behavior. Often, it seems, features of situations drive our behavior even when we remain unaware of these features or their influence. One response to this research is pessimism about human agency: human agents have little conscious control over their own behavior, and little insight into why they do what they do. In this paper we review classic and more recent studies indicating “the power of the situation,” and argue for a more (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  20.  38
    The Truth of Conditional Assertions.Geoffrey P. Goodwin & P. N. Johnson-Laird - 2018 - Cognitive Science 42 (8):2502-2533.
    Given a basic conditional of the form, If A then C, individuals usually list three cases as possible: A and C, not‐A and not‐C, not‐A and C. This result corroborates the theory of mental models. By contrast, individuals often judge that the conditional is true only in the case of A and C, and that cases of not‐A are irrelevant to its truth or falsity. This result corroborates other theories of conditionals. To resolve the discrepancy, we devised two new tasks: (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  21. Self-control, motivational strength, and exposure therapy.Alfred R. Mele - 2014 - Philosophical Studies 170 (2):359-375.
    Do people sometimes exercise self-control in such a way as to bring it about that they do not act on present-directed motivation that continues to be motivationally strongest for a significant stretch of time (even though they are able to act on that motivation at the time) and intentionally act otherwise during that stretch of time? This paper explores the relative merits of two different theories about synchronic self-control that provide different answers to this question. One is due to Sripada (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  22. BLOM Hans, John Christian Laursen and Luisa Simonutti (eds).Brennan Geoffrey, Robert Goodwin, Frank Jackson & Michael Smith - 2007 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 15 (4):833-837.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Chreods, homeorhesis and biofields: Finding the right path for science.Arran Gare - 2017 - Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology 131:61-91.
    C.H. Waddington’s concepts of ‘chreods’ (canalized paths of development) and ‘homeorhesis’ (the tendency to return to a path), each associated with ‘morphogenetic fields’, were conceived by him as a contribution to complexity theory. Subsequent developments in complexity theory have largely ignored Waddington’s work and efforts to advance it. Waddington explained the development of the concept of chreod as the influence on his work of Alfred North Whitehead’s process philosophy, notably, the concept of concrescence as a self-causing process. Processes were (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Emotion and Desire in Self-Deception.Alfred R. Mele - 2003 - In Anthony Hatzimoysis (ed.), Philosophy and the Emotions. Cambridge University Press. pp. 163-179.
    According to a traditional view of self-deception, the phenomenon is an intrapersonal analogue of stereotypical interpersonal deception. In the latter case, deceivers intentionally deceive others into believing something, p , and there is a time at which the deceivers believe that p is false while their victims falsely believe that p is true. If self-deception is properly understood on this model, self-deceivers intentionally deceive themselves into believing something, p , and there is a time at which they believe that p (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  25. Decisions, intentions, and free will.Alfred R. Mele - 2005 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 29 (1):146-162.
    I will argue that close attention to deciding casts doubt on the simple view and the single phenomena view of intentional action. That is my thesis. My aim is much broader—to improve our understanding of deciding and of the bearing of the phenomenon of deciding on free will and moral responsibility.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  26.  67
    Autonomy, self-control and weakness of will.Alfred R. Mele - 2001 - In Robert Kane (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Free Will. New York: Oxford University Press.
    This article defends a nonstandard position on free will that is based on three topics linked to contemporary debates about free will: autonomy, self-control, and weakness of will. It argues that autonomy, and hence also free will, requires more than self-control, including ideal self-control. It considers the additional conditions required, showing how contemporary discussions of autonomy are intertwined with debates about free will. These additional conditions for genuine autonomy do not require us to choose between compatibilist and incompatibilist accounts of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  27. Self-deception and emotion.Alfred R. Mele - 2000 - Consciousness and Emotion 1 (1):115-137.
    Drawing on recent empirical work, this philosophical paper explores some possible contributions of emotion to self-deception. Three hypotheses are considered: (1) the anxiety reduction hypothesis: the function of self-deception is to reduce present anxiety; (2) the solo emotion hypothesis: emotions sometimes contribute to instances of self-deception that have no desires among their significant causes; (3) the direct emotion hypothesis: emotions sometimes contribute directly to self-deception, in the sense that they make contributions that, at the time, are neither made by desires (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  28. Evidence, Hypothesis, and Grue.Alfred Schramm - 2014 - Erkenntnis 79 (3):571-591.
    Extant literature on Goodman’s ‘New Riddle of Induction’ deals mainly with two versions. I consider both of them, starting from the (‘epistemic’) version of Goodman’s classic of 1954. It turns out that it belongs to the realm of applications of inductive logic, and that it can be resolved by admitting only significant evidence (as I call it) for confirmations of hypotheses. Sect. 1 prepares some ground for the argument. As much of it depends on the notion of evidential significance, this (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  29. The folk concept of intentional action: A commentary.Alfred Mele - 2006 - Journal of Cognition and Culture 6 (1-2):277-290.
    In this commentary, I discuss the three main articles in this volume that present survey data relevant to a search for something that might merit the label “the folk concept of intentional action” – the articles by Joshua Knobe and Arudra Burra, Bertram Malle, and Thomas Nadelhoffer. My guiding question is this: What shape might we find in an analysis of intentional action that takes at face value the results of all of the relevant surveys about vignettes discussed in these (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  30. Justice by Lottery.Barbara Goodwin - 1997 - Utopian Studies 8 (1):175-176.
  31.  36
    Gestures as a resource for the organization of mutual orientation.Charles Goodwin - 1986 - Semiotica 62 (1-2):29-50.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  32.  19
    Revisiting Death: Implicit Bias and the Case of Jahi McMath.Michele Goodwin - 2018 - Hastings Center Report 48 (S4):77-80.
    For nearly five years, bioethicists and neurologists debated whether Jahi McMath, an African American teenager, was alive or dead. While Jahi's condition provides a compelling study for analyzing brain death, circumscribing her life status to a question of brain death fails to acknowledge and respond to a chronic, if uncomfortable, bioethics problem in American health care—namely, racial bias and unequal treatment, both real and perceived. Bioethicists should examine the underlying, arguably broader social implications of what Jahi's medical treatment and experience (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  33.  57
    Structural formulas and explanation in organic chemistry.W. M. Goodwin - 2008 - Foundations of Chemistry 10 (2):117-127.
    Organic chemists have been able to develop a robust, theoretical understanding of the phenomena they study; however, the primary theoretical devices employed in this field are not mathematical equations or laws, as is the case in most other physical sciences. Instead it is diagrams, and in particular structural formulas and potential energy diagrams, that carry the explanatory weight in the discipline. To understand how this is so, it is necessary to investigate both the nature of the diagrams employed in organic (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  34.  21
    The Pragmatic Force of Making an Argument.Jean Goodwin & Beth Innocenti - 2019 - Topoi 38 (4):669-680.
    Making arguments makes reasons apparent. Sometimes those reasons may affect audiences’ relationships to claims. But an over-emphasis on audience effects encouraged by functionalist theories of argumentation distracts attention from other things that making arguments can accomplish. We advance the normative pragmatic program on argumentation through two case studies of how early advocates for women’s suffrage in the U.S. made reasons apparent in order to show that what they were doing wasn’t ridiculous. While it might be possible to identify this as (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  35.  15
    Should Climate Scientists Fly?Jean Goodwin - 2020 - Informal Logic 40 (2):157-203.
    I inquire into argument at the system level, exploring the controversy over whether climate scientists should fly. I document participants’ knowledge of a skeptical argument that because scientists fly, they cannot testify credibly about the climate emergency. I show how this argument has been managed by pro-climate action arguers, and how some climate scientists have developed parallel reasoning, articulating a sophisticated case why they will be more effective in the controversy if they fly less. Finally, I review some strategies arguers (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  36.  48
    Strength of motivation and being in control - learning from Libet.Alfred R. Mele - 1997 - American Philosophical Quarterly 34 (3):319-32.
    It is sometimes suggested that if, whenever we act intentionally, we do, or try to do, what we are most strongly motivated to do at the time, then we are at the mercy of whatever desire happens to be strongest at the time. I have argued elsewhere that this is false (Mele 1987, ch. 5; 1992, ch. 4; 1995, ch. 3; 1996). This essay provides another route to that conclusion, but that is not my primary aim. The goal of this (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  37.  34
    Cicero's authority.Jean Goodwin - 1999 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 34 (1):38-60.
    In this paper I propose to continue the analysis of the appeal to authority begun at the last OSSA conference. I proceed by examining the well-documented use of the appeal made by the ancient Roman advocate, Cicero. The fact that Cicero expressed his opinion was expectably sufficient to give his auditors--responsible citizens all--reason to do as he desired. But why? The resolution of this puzzle points to a strong sense in which arguments can be called rhetorical , for the rational (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  38.  93
    Motivated irrationality.Alfred R. Mele - 2004 - In Alfred R. Mele & Piers Rawling (eds.), The Oxford handbook of rationality. New York: Oxford University Press.
    The literature on motivated irrationality has two primary foci: action and belief. This article explores two of the central topics falling under this rubric: akratic action (action exhibiting so-called weakness of will or deficient self-control) and motivationally biased belief (including self-deception). Among other matters, this article offers a resolution of Donald Davidson's worry about the explanation of irrationality. When agents act akratically, they act for reasons, and in central cases, they make rational judgments about what it is best to do. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  39.  15
    Cardinal Algebras.Alfred Tarski & Bjarni Jonsson - 1949 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 14 (3):188-189.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  40. Contributions to the Theory of Models.Alfred Tarski - 1956 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 21 (4):405-406.
  41.  93
    The acquisition of Boolean concepts.Geoffrey P. Goodwin & Philip N. Johnson-Laird - 2013 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 17 (3):128-133.
  42. The Theatre, Diplomacy And Censorship In The Reign Of Henri Iv.Alfred Soman - 1973 - Bibliothèque d'Humanisme Et Renaissance 35 (2):273-288.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  3
    Die Atomistik in römischer Zeit: Rezeption und Verdrängung.Alfred Stückelberger - 1987 - In Wolfgang Haase (ed.), Philosophie, Wissenschaften, Technik. Philosophie. De Gruyter. pp. 2561-2581.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  7
    A Philosopher Looks at Science.Alfred Stern - 1969 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 7 (2):127-137.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  8
    Fiktionen und Mythen in der Geschichte.Alfred Stern - 1979 - Kant Studien 70 (1-4):52-65.
  46. Geschichtsphilosophie und Wertproblem.Alfred Stern - 1970 - Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 24 (1):145-151.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Historicism and Basic Existential Ethics.Alfred Stern - 1962 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 43 (3):313.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Husserl's Phenomenology and the Scope of Philosophy.Alfred Stern - 1954 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 35 (3):267.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49. Le problème de l'absolutisme et du relativisme axiologique et la philosophie allemande.Alfred Stern - 1939 - Revue Internationale de Philosophie 1 (4):703-742.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Mathematics and the Good.Alfred North Whitehead - 1942 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 7 (2):101-101.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000