Results for 'Pregnant Women'

995 found
Order:
  1.  44
    Pregnant women should not be categorised as a ‘vulnerable population’ in biomedical research studies: ending a vicious cycle of ‘vulnerability’.Carleigh B. Krubiner & Ruth R. Faden - 2017 - Journal of Medical Ethics 43 (10):664-665.
    A new study published in Journal of Medical Ethics by van der Zande et al 1 further highlights why classifying pregnant women as a ‘vulnerable population’ in the context of research is deeply problematic. Because the designation of ‘vulnerable’ is otherwise applied to populations whose decision-making capacity about research participation is somehow compromised—such as children and adults of limited cognitive ability—many of us have been arguing for some time that using this designation for pregnant women is (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  2.  40
    Should pregnant women be charged for non-invasive prenatal screening? Implications for reproductive autonomy and equal access.Eline M. Bunnik, Adriana Kater-Kuipers, Robert-Jan H. Galjaard & Inez D. de Beaufort - 2020 - Journal of Medical Ethics 46 (3):194-198.
    The introduction of non-invasive prenatal testing in healthcare systems around the world offers an opportunity to reconsider funding policies for prenatal screening. In some countries with universal access healthcare systems, pregnant women and their partners are asked to pay for NIPT. In this paper, we discuss two important rationales for charging women for NIPT: to prevent increased uptake of NIPT and to promote informed choice. First, given the aim of prenatal screening, high or low uptake rates are (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  3.  13
    Pregnant Women Can Finally Expect Better.Angela Ballantyne - 2019 - Hastings Center Report 49 (1):10-11.
    A decade of advocacy for the inclusion of pregnant women in the clinical research agenda is starting to pay off. In September, the United States Task Force on Research Specific to Pregnant Women and Lactating Women issued its advice to the secretary of Health and Human Services on addressing gaps in knowledge and research on safe and effective therapies for pregnant women and lactating women. The task force is pushing for major reforms. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Are pregnant women fetal containers?Laura M. Purdy - 1990 - Bioethics 4 (4):273–291.
  5.  38
    Shackling Pregnant Women: US Prisons, Anti-Blackness, and the Unfinished Project of American Abolition.Brady Heiner - 2022 - philoSOPHIA: A Journal of Continental Feminism 12 (1):1-35.
    Abstract:This article analyzes the pervasive practice in US carceral institutions of shackling incarcerated pregnant women during childbirth and postpartum. After a review of bioethical, civil, and human rights norms, which widely condemn the practice, I advance an interpretation of the social meaning of shackling imprisoned pregnant women and its persistence despite widespread normative consensus in favor of its abolition. Two arguments regarding the persistence of the practice are considered: (1) that it stems from the unthinking exportation (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  33
    Shackling Pregnant Women.Brady Heiner - 2022 - philoSOPHIA: A Journal of Continental Feminism 12 (1-2):1-35.
    This article analyzes the pervasive practice in US carceral institutions of shackling incarcerated pregnant women during childbirth and postpartum. After a review of bioethical, civil, and human rights norms, which widely condemn the practice, I advance an interpretation of the social meaning of shackling imprisoned pregnant women and its persistence despite widespread normative consensus in favor of its abolition. Two arguments regarding the persistence of the practice are considered: that it stems from the unthinking exportation of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  36
    Are Pregnant Women Fetal Containers?Laura M. Purdy - 1990 - Bioethics 4 (4):273-291.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  8.  96
    How are pregnant women vulnerable research participants?Verina Wild - 2012 - International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 5 (2):82-104.
    Despite the attempts to promote the inclusion of pregnant women into clinical research, this group is still widely excluded. An analysis of the “vulnerability of pregnant women” that questions deeply internalized stereotypes is necessary for finding the right balance in the protection of pregnant women as research participants. Criticism of the traditional account of vulnerability will lead to an alternative that focuses on situations rather than groups and on the obligations of responsible parties. The (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  9.  16
    The experiences of pregnant women in an interventional clinical trial: Research In Pregnancy Ethics study.Angela Ballantyne, Susan Pullon, Lindsay Macdonald, Christine Barthow, Kristen Wickens & Julian Crane - 2017 - Bioethics 31 (6):476-483.
    There is increasing global pressure to ensure that pregnant women are responsibly and safely included in clinical research in order to improve the evidence base that underpins healthcare delivery during pregnancy. One supposed barrier to inclusion is the assumption that pregnant women will be reluctant to participate in research. There is however very little empirical research investigating the views of pregnant women. Their perspective on the benefits, burdens and risks of research is a crucial (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10.  15
    Supervaluation of pregnant women is reductive of women.Jennifer Parks & Timothy F. Murphy - 2024 - Journal of Medical Ethics 50 (1):29-30.
    Robinson argues that by certain threshold criteria, pregnant women qualify for a higher moral status by reason of their pregnancies. While her intention is to make this a status upgrade for women, we worry that it may result in a status downgrade for women as a class, by presupposing and reinforcing women’s value in relation to their reproductive labour. Historically, central to feminist analysis is resistance to reductive accounts of women in relation to their (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11. Pregnant women with fetal abnormalities: The forgotten people in the abortion debate.L. De Crespigny & Savulescu, J. - manuscript
    of (from Oxford Uehiro Centre for Practical Ethics) Medical Journal of Australia, 188 (2) 100 - 102.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  23
    Supporting Pregnant Women through Difficult Decisions: A Case of Prenatal Diagnosis of Osteogenesis Imperfecta.Marilyn E. Coors & Susan F. Townsend - 2006 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 17 (3):266-274.
  13.  5
    Clinical Research Involving Pregnant Women.Françoise Baylis & Angela Ballantyne (eds.) - 2016 - Cham: Imprint: Springer.
    This book discusses 'how' to respectfully and responsibly include pregnant women in clinical research. In sharp contrast, the existing literature predominantly focuses on the reasons 'why' the inclusion of pregnant women in clinical research is necessary - viz., to develop effective treatments for women during pregnancy, to promote fetal safety, to reduce harm to women and fetuses from suboptimal care, and to allow access to the benefits of research participation. This book supports the shift (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  48
    Vulnerability of pregnant women in clinical research.Indira S. E. Van der Zande, Rieke van der Graaf, Martijn A. Oudijk & Johannes J. M. Van Delden - 2017 - Journal of Medical Ethics 43 (10):657-663.
    Background Notwithstanding the need to produce evidence-based knowledge on medications for pregnant women, they remain underrepresented in clinical research. Sometimes they are excluded because of their supposed vulnerability, but there are no universally accepted criteria for considering pregnant women as vulnerable. Our aim was to explore whether and if so to what extent pregnant women are vulnerable as research subjects. Method We performed a conceptual and empirical analysis of vulnerability applied to pregnant (...). Analysis A conceptual analysis supports Hurst's definition of vulnerability. Consequently, we argue that pregnant women are vulnerable if they encounter an identifiably increased likelihood of incurring additional or greater wrong. According to the literature, this increased likelihood could exist of four alleged features for pregnant women's vulnerability: informed consent, susceptibility to coercion, higher exposure to risk due to lack of knowledge, vulnerability of the fetus. Discussion Testing the features against Hurst's definition demonstrates that they all concern the same issue: pregnant women are only vulnerable because a higher exposure to risk due to lack of scientific knowledge comprises an increased wrong. Research Ethics Committees have a responsibility to protect the vulnerable, but a higher exposure to risk due to lack of scientific knowledge is a much broader issue and also needs to be addressed by other stakeholders. Conclusions The only reason why pregnant women are potentially vulnerable is to the extent that they are increasingly exposed to higher risks due to a lack of scientific knowledge. Accordingly, the discussion can advance to the development of practical strategies to promote fair inclusion of pregnant women in clinical research. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  15.  12
    Anomalous cerebral morphology of pregnant women with cleft fetuses.Zhen Li, Chunlin Li, Yuting Liang, Keyang Wang, Li Wang, Xu Zhang & Qingqing Wu - 2022 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 16:959710.
    ObjectivePregnancy leads to long-lasting changes in brain structure for healthy women; however, little is known regarding alterations in the cortical features of pregnant women with malformed fetuses. Isolated clefts of the lip and/or palate (ICL/P) are the most common congenital anomaly in the craniofacial region, which is highly gene-associated. We speculated that pregnant women carrying fetuses with ICL/P may have associated risk genes and specific brain changes during pregnancy.MethodsIn this study, we investigated T1-weighted brain magnetic (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  25
    Involving Pregnant Women in Research: What Should We Recommend When the Regulations Seem Ethically Problematic?Holly A. Taylor & Christian Morales - 2018 - American Journal of Bioethics 18 (4):91-92.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  55
    Research with Pregnant Women: New Insights on Legal Decision‐Making.Anna C. Mastroianni, Leslie Meltzer Henry, David Robinson, Theodore Bailey, Ruth R. Faden, Margaret O. Little & Anne Drapkin Lyerly - 2017 - Hastings Center Report 47 (3):38-45.
    U.S. researchers and scholars often point to two legal factors as significant obstacles to the inclusion of pregnant women in clinical research: the Department of Health and Human Services’ regulatory limitations specific to pregnant women's research participation and the fear of liability for potential harm to children born following a pregnant woman's research participation. This article offers a more nuanced view of the potential legal complexities that can impede research with pregnant women than (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18.  44
    Hiv testing of pregnant women: An ethical analysis.Kjell Arne Johansson, Kirsten Bjerkreim Pedersen & Anna-Karin Andersson - 2011 - Developing World Bioethics 11 (3):109-119.
    Recent global advances in available technology to prevent mother-to-child HIV transmission necessitate a rethinking of contemporary and previous ethical debates on HIV testing as a means to preventing vertical transmission. In this paper, we will provide an ethical analysis of HIV-testing strategies of pregnant women. First, we argue that provider-initiated opt-out HIV testing seems to be the most effective HIV test strategy. The flip-side of an opt-out strategy is that it may end up as involuntary testing in a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19.  17
    A New Threat to Pregnant Women's Autonomy.Dawn Johnsen - 1987 - Hastings Center Report 17 (4):33-40.
    Courts and legislatures are increasingly being called upon to restrict the autonomy of pregnant women by requiring them to behave in ways that others determine are best for the fetuses they carry. The state should not attempt to transform pregnant women into ideal baby‐making machines. Pregnant women make decisions about their behavior in the context of the rest of their lives, with all the attendant complexities and pressures. Our interest in helping future children by (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  20.  31
    At Law: Pregnant Women as Fetal Containers.George J. Annas - 1986 - Hastings Center Report 16 (6):13.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  21.  11
    Pregnant Women and Equitable Access to Emergency Medical Care.Michael R. Ulrich - 2018 - American Journal of Bioethics 18 (7):57-59.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  32
    How should risks and benefits be balanced in research involving pregnant women and fetuses?C. Strong - 2011 - IRB: Ethics & Human Research 33 (6):1-5.
    In research involving pregnant women and fetuses, a number of questions arise concerning the balancing of risks and benefits. In research that holds out a prospect of direct benefit for the woman, how much risk to the fetus is permissible? How should the principle of minimizing risks be applied when there are two subjects—pregnant woman and fetus? Should risks for each of them be minimized? What if minimizing risks for one increases risks for the other? These and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  23
    How the CIOMS guidelines contribute to fair inclusion of pregnant women in research.Rieke van der Graaf, Indira S. E. Van der Zande & Johannes J. M. Van Delden - 2018 - Bioethics 33 (3):377-383.
    As early as 2002, CIOMS stated that pregnant women should be presumed eligible for participation in research. Despite this position and calls of other well‐recognized organizations, the health needs of pregnant women in research remain grossly under‐researched. Although the presumption of eligibility remains unchanged, the revision of the 2002 CIOMS International ethical guidelines for biomedical research involving human subjects involved a substantive rewrite of the guidance on research with pregnant women and related guidelines, such (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  24.  9
    Are We Justified in Introducing Carbon Monoxide Testing to Encourage Smoking Cessation in Pregnant Women?Catherine Bowden - 2019 - Health Care Analysis 27 (2):128-145.
    Smoking is frequently presented as being particularly problematic when the smoker is a pregnant woman because of the potential harm to the future child. This premise is used to justify targeting pregnant women with a unique approach to smoking cessation including policies such as the routine testing of all pregnant women for carbon monoxide at every antenatal appointment. This paper examines the evidence that such policies are justified by the aim of harm prevention and argues (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  25.  10
    Are We Justified in Introducing Carbon Monoxide Testing to Encourage Smoking Cessation in Pregnant Women?Catherine Bowden - 2019 - Health Care Analysis 27 (2):128-145.
    Smoking is frequently presented as being particularly problematic when the smoker is a pregnant woman because of the potential harm to the future child. This premise is used to justify targeting pregnant women with a unique approach to smoking cessation including policies such as the routine testing of all pregnant women for carbon monoxide at every antenatal appointment. This paper examines the evidence that such policies are justified by the aim of harm prevention and argues (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  26.  32
    Psychological readiness of pregnant women to parenthood.S. I. Galjautdinova, R. R. Kutusheva & R. B. Gumerova - 2016 - Liberal Arts in Russiaроссийский Гуманитарный Журналrossijskij Gumanitarnyj Žurnalrossijskij Gumanitarnyj Zhurnalrossiiskii Gumanitarnyi Zhurnal 5 (2):243.
    In this article the results of a study of psychological readiness of pregnant women to parenthood are presented. Psychological readiness is defined as a structure consisting of three components: the cognitive, emotional, and behavioral, which is consistent with the single theory of psychological processes L. M. Vekkera. It was found that the main component that determines the high level of psychological readiness for motherhood is a cognitive component. The content of the cognitive component includes an understanding of the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  24
    Vulnerability of pregnant women in clinical research.Indira S. E. van der Zande, Rieke van der Graaf, Martijn A. Oudijk & Johannes J. M. van Delden - 2017 - Journal of Medical Ethics 43 (10):657-663.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  28.  63
    Harms of Excluding Pregnant Women from Clinical Research: The Case of HIV-Infected Pregnant Women.Nancy E. Kass, Holly A. Taylor & Patricia A. King - 1996 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 24 (1):36-46.
    Since the beginning of the AIDS epidemic, the proportion of AIDS cases among women has continued to rise. Women constituted 23 percent of the AIDS cases reported to the Centers for Disease Control and Prevention in 1995, and 81 percent of these women were of childbearing age. It was not until 1991, however, that epidemiological studies of women were initiated. By comparison, the representation of HIV-infected women in clinical trials gradually has grown. Undoubtedly, a consequence (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  29.  20
    Harms of excluding Pregnant Women from Clinical Research: The Case of HIV-Infected Pregnant Women.Nancy E. Kass, Holly A. Taylor & Patricia A. King - 1996 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 24 (1):36-46.
    Since the beginning of the AIDS epidemic, the proportion of AIDS cases among women has continued to rise. Women constituted 23 percent of the AIDS cases reported to the Centers for Disease Control and Prevention in 1995, and 81 percent of these women were of childbearing age. It was not until 1991, however, that epidemiological studies of women were initiated. By comparison, the representation of HIV-infected women in clinical trials gradually has grown. Undoubtedly, a consequence (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  30. HIV-Infected Pregnant Women in Developing Countries. Ethical Imperialism or Unethical Exploitation.Randomised Placebo-Controlled Trials - 2001 - Bioethics 15 (4):289-311.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Should we Routinely Test Pregnant Women for HIV?Rebecca Bennett - 2001 - In Rebecca Bennett & Charles A. Erin (eds.), Hiv and Aids, Testing, Screening, and Confidentiality. Clarendon Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  67
    The second wave: Toward responsible inclusion of pregnant women in research.Anne Drapkin Lyerly, Margaret Olivia Little & Ruth Faden - 2008 - International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 1 (2):5-22.
    Though much progress has been made on inclusion of non-pregnant women in research, thoughtful discussion about including pregnant women has lagged behind. We outline resulting knowledge gaps and their costs and then highlight four reasons why ethically we are obliged to confront the challenges of including pregnant women in clinical research. These are: the need for effective treatment for women during pregnancy, fetal safety, harm from the reticence to prescribe potentially beneficial medication, and (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  33.  14
    Why the nuclear option? Supporting pregnant women without new categories of moral status.J. Burke Rea - 2024 - Journal of Medical Ethics 50 (1):20-21.
    Recourse to a being’s moral status is the ‘nuclear option’ of moral theorising—it tells us not only what obligations we have and to what degree, but whether we have obligations to them in the first place and whether their moral concern trumps concern for other beings simply in virtue of the kind of being they are. As such, we should only explain obligations in terms of a being’s moral status if doing so is principled and necessary to defend that obligation. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34.  97
    Power Difference and Risk Perception: Mapping Vulnerability within the Decision Process of Pregnant Women towards Clinical Trial Participation in an Urban Middle‐Income Setting.C. den Hollander Geerte, lBrowne Joyce, Arhinful Daniel, Graaf Rieke & Klipstein-Grobusch Kerstin - 2016 - Developing World Bioethics:68-75.
    To address the burden of maternal morbidity and mortality in low‐ and middle‐income countries (LMICs), research with pregnant women in these settings is increasingly common. Pregnant women in LMIC‐context may experience vulnerability related to giving consent to participate in a clinical trial. To recognize possible layers of vulnerability this study aims to identify factors that influence the decision process towards clinical trial participation of pregnant women in an urban middle‐income setting. This qualitative research used (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  18
    "Confucius and Pregnant Women: An Investigation into the Intertextuality of the" Lunyu".Oliver Weingarten - 2009 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 129 (4):597-618.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  36.  48
    Routine antenatal HIV testing: the responses and perceptions of pregnant women and the viability of informed consent. A qualitative study.P. de Zulueta & M. Boulton - 2007 - Journal of Medical Ethics 33 (6):329-336.
    This qualitative cross-sectional survey, undertaken in the antenatal booking clinics of a hospital in central London, explores pregnant women’s responses to routine HIV testing, examines their reasons for declining or accepting the test, and assesses how far their responses fulfil standard criteria for informed consent. Of the 32 women interviewed, only 10 participants were prepared for HIV testing at their booking interview. None of the women viewed themselves as being particularly at risk for HIV infection. The (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  37.  32
    Clinical Research Involving Pregnant Women ed. by Françoise Baylis and Angela Ballantyne. [REVIEW]Elizabeth Victor - 2019 - International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 12 (1):175-179.
    As a feminist bioethicist, I have frequently wondered why the exclusion of pregnant women has been the default position for most clinical research and how social values have influenced this decision. Relatedly, I wonder what responsible research involving pregnant women would look like. As a theorist who conducts research on the concept of vulnerability, I have often wanted to know why there has been so little research into the harmful effects of the routine exclusion of (...) women, including questions such as: What do pregnant women actually think about participating in research? How should we treat pregnant women and their fetuses for the purposes of consent (are they two separable persons or one complex... (shrink)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  9
    Responsibilities of Pregnant Women.Tracey Phelan - 2001 - Chisholm Health Ethics Bulletin 7 (1):1.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  28
    Informed choice of pregnant women in prenatal screening tests for Down's syndrome.Hsien-Hsien Chiang, Y. M. Yu Chao & Y. S. Yuh - 2006 - Journal of Medical Ethics 32 (5):273-277.
  40.  40
    A qualitative study on acceptable levels of risk for pregnant women in clinical research.Indira S. E. Van der Zande, Rieke van der Graaf, Martijn A. Oudijk & Johannes J. M. van Delden - 2017 - BMC Medical Ethics 18 (1):35.
    There is ambiguity with regard to what counts as an acceptable level of risk in clinical research in pregnant women and there is no input from stakeholders relative to such research risks. The aim of our paper was to explore what stakeholders who are actively involved in the conduct of clinical research in pregnant women deem an acceptable level of risk for pregnant women in clinical research. Accordingly, we used the APOSTEL VI study, a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  45
    Noninvasive Prenatal Testing: Views of Canadian Pregnant Women and Their Partners Regarding Pressure and Societal Concerns.Vardit Ravitsky, Stanislav Birko, Jessica Le Clerc-Blain, Hazar Haidar, Aliya O. Affdal, Marie-Ève Lemoine, Charles Dupras & Anne-Marie Laberge - 2021 - AJOB Empirical Bioethics 12 (1):53-62.
    Background Noninvasive prenatal testing (NIPT) provides important benefits yet raises ethical concerns. We surveyed Canadian pregnant women and their partners to explore their views regarding pressure to test and terminate a pregnancy, as well as other societal impacts that may result from the routinization of NIPT.Methods A questionnaire was offered (March 2015 to July 2016) to pregnant women and their partners at five healthcare facilities in four Canadian provinces.Results 882 pregnant women and 395 partners (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  42.  11
    Association of Sleep Duration and Screen Time With Anxiety of Pregnant Women During the COVID-19 Pandemic.Yuan Zhang, Yuge Zhang, Renli Deng, Min Chen, Rong Cao, Shijiu Chen, Kuntao Chen, Zhiheng Jin, Xue Bai, Jingyan Tian, Baofeng Zhou & Kunming Tian - 2021 - Frontiers in Psychology 12.
    The COVID-19 pandemic has dramatically changed the patterns of lifestyle and posed psychological stress on pregnant women. However, the association of sleep duration and screen time with anxiety among pregnant women under the backdrop of the COVID-19 pandemic scenario has been poorly addressed. We conducted one large-scale, multicenter cross-sectional study which recruited 1794 pregnant women across middle and west China. Self-reported demographic characteristics, lifestyle, and mental health status were collected from 6th February to 8th (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  58
    Samantha Burton and the Rights of Pregnant Women Twenty Years afterIn re A. C.Howard Minkoff & Anne Drapkin Lyerly - 2010 - Hastings Center Report 40 (6):13-15.
    In 1987, a young woman named Angela Carder, pregnant and dying from cancer, was ordered by a court of law to undergo a cesarean delivery against her and her family’s wishes. She and her baby both died. Three years later, an appeals court took an extraordinary stand: it vacated the order that ended their lives and upheld pregnant women’s rights to informed consent and bodily integrity. The “unkindest cut of all,”1 it seemed, had been condemned by the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  44.  15
    How Should the Precautionary Principle Apply to Pregnant Women in Clinical Research?Indira S. E. van der Zande, Rieke van der Graaf, Martijin A. Oudijk & Johannes J. M. van Delden - 2021 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 46 (5):516-529.
    The precautionary principle is often invoked in relation to pregnant women and may be one of the underlying reasons for their continuous underrepresentation in clinical research. The principle is appealing, because potential fetal harm as a result of research participation is considered to be serious and irreversible. In our paper, we explore through conceptual analysis whether and if so how the precautionary principle should apply to pregnant women. We argue that the principle is a decision-making strategy (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45.  20
    Brain Death in Pregnant Women.Jay E. Kantor & Iffath Abbasi Hoskins - 1993 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 4 (4):308-314.
  46.  49
    Women's views about participating in research while pregnant.A. D. Lyerly, E. E. Namey, B. Gray, G. Swamy & R. R. Faden - 2012 - IRB: Ethics & Human Research 34 (4):1-8.
    Pregnant women and their interests have been underrepresented in health research. Little is known about issues relevant to women considering research participation during pregnancy. We performed in-depth interviews with 22 women enrolled in either one of two trials sponsored by the National Institutes of Health to assess the safety and immunogenicity of the H1N1 vaccine during pregnancy. Three themes characterized women’s decisions to participate in research: they valued early access to the vaccine, they perceived a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47.  20
    How the CIOMS guidelines contribute to fair inclusion of pregnant women in research.Rieke van der Graaf, Indira S. E. van der Zande & Johannes J. M. van Delden - 2018 - Bioethics 33 (3):377-383.
    As early as 2002, CIOMS stated that pregnant women should be presumed eligible for participation in research. Despite this position and calls of other well‐recognized organizations, the health needs of pregnant women in research remain grossly under‐researched. Although the presumption of eligibility remains unchanged, the revision of the 2002 CIOMS International ethical guidelines for biomedical research involving human subjects involved a substantive rewrite of the guidance on research with pregnant women and related guidelines, such (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  48.  18
    Ethical Issues in Researching Pregnant Women: A Commentary.Shirley Jones & Paula McGee - 2007 - Research Ethics 3 (2):51-52.
    This study appeared in full in the last issue of Research Ethics Review : 18). Rowena Jones is an obstetrician working in a busy hospital for women. Her research focuses on changes in women's brains during pregnancy1. Rowena plans to use magnetic resonance imaging to record images of the brains of women in the second and third trimesters and after birth at 6 and 24 weeks. Her sample consists of two groups of healthy women with uncomplicated (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  43
    Routine HIV Testing of Hospital Patients and Pregnant Women: Informed Consent in the Real World.David J. Mayo, Frank S. Rhame & Martin Gunderson - 1996 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 6 (2):161-182.
    : The Centers for Disease Control and Prevention (CDC) has recommended that HIV testing be routinely offered to certain patients in hospitals with a high prevalence of HIV infection and on all pregnant women. The CDC does not, however, offer implementation level guidelines for obtaining informed consent. We provide a moral justification for requiring informed consent for HIV testing and propose guidelines for securing such consent. In particular we argue that genuine informed consent can be secured without elaborate (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  37
    The Common Rule, Pregnant Women, and Research: No Need to “Rescue” That Which Should Be Revised.Chris Kaposy & Françoise Baylis - 2011 - American Journal of Bioethics 11 (5):60-62.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
1 — 50 / 995