Results for 'Ontological reduction'

989 found
Order:
  1. Ontological reduction and the world of numbers.W. V. Quine - 1964 - Journal of Philosophy 61 (7):209-216.
  2. Ontological Reduction and the Wave Function Ontology.Alyssa Ney - 2013 - In Alyssa Ney & David Z. Albert (eds.), The Wave Function: Essays on the Metaphysics of Quantum Mechanics. Oxford University Press. pp. 168-183.
  3. Ontological reduction: A comment on Lombardi and labarca.Paul Needham - 2006 - Foundations of Chemistry 8 (1):73-80.
    In a recent article in this journal (Foundations of Chemistry, 7 (2005), 125–148) Lombardi and Labarca call into question a thesis of ontological reduction to which several writers on reduction subscribe despite rejecting a thesis of epistemological reduction. Lombardi and Labarca advocate instead a pluralistic ontology inspired by Putnam’s internal realism. I suggest that it is not necessary to go so far, and that a more critical view of the ontological reduction espoused by the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  4. Ontological reduction and molecular structure.Robin Findlay Hendry - 2010 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 41 (2):183-191.
  5. Ontology, reduction, emergence: A general frame.C. Ulises Moulines - 2006 - Synthese 151 (3):313-323.
    In a scientific context, ontological commitments should be considered as supervenient over accepted scientific theories. This implies that the primarily ontological notions of reduction and emergence of entities of different kinds should be reformulated in terms of relations between existing empirical theories. For this, in turn, it is most convenient to employ a model-theoretic view of scientific theories: the identity criterion of a scientific theory is essentially given by a class of models. Accordingly, reduction and emergence (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  6.  32
    Ontological reduction.Reinhardt Grossmann - 1973 - Bloomington,: Indiana University Press.
  7. Ontology, Reduction, and the Unity of Science.C. Ulises Moulines - 2001 - The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 10:19-27.
    Ontology should be conceived as supervenient on scientific theories. They tell us what categories of things there really are. Thus, we would have a unique system of ontology if we would attain the unity of science through a reductionist program. For this, it should be clear how a relation of intertheoretical reduction (with ontological implications) is to be conceived. A formal proposal is laid out in this paper. This allows us also to define the notion of a fundamental (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  8.  64
    Ontological reduction.Dale Gottlieb - 1976 - Journal of Philosophy 73 (3):57-76.
  9.  27
    Ontological Reduction by Logical Analysis and the Primitive Vocabulary of Mentalese.Gyula Klima - 2012 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 86 (3):403-414.
    This paper confronts a certain modern view of the relation between semantics and ontology with that of the late-medieval nominalist philosophers, William Ockham and John Buridan. The modern view in question is characterized in terms of what is called here “the thesis of onto-semantic parallelism,” which states that the primitive (indefinable) categorematic concepts of our semantics mark out the primary entities in reality. The paper argues that, despite some apparently plausible misinterpretations to the contrary, the late-medieval nominalist program of “ (...) reduction” was not driven by considerations that try to “read off” ontology from semantic analysis or those that try to identify semantic primitives in their search for ontological primitives. The medieval authors presented a much more flexible, dynamic view of “Aristotelian naturalism,” which challenges both of the unappealing modern alternatives of “conceptual tribalism” and “conceptual imperialism.”. (shrink)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Ontological Reduction.Reinhardt Grossman - 1977 - Mind 86 (344):624-627.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  11.  61
    Ontological reduction.Leslie H. Tharp - 1971 - Journal of Philosophy 68 (6):151-164.
  12.  18
    Ontological Reduction.Eric B. Dayton - 1975 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 35 (4):582-583.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. Ontological Reductions in Mathematics. Part II: Argumentational Strategies for Realism.Krzysztof Wojtowicz - 2011 - Filozofia Nauki 19 (2):29.
  14. Ontological Reductions in Mathematics. Part III: On Reconstruction of Some Parts of Mathematics.Krzysztof Wojtowicz - 2011 - Filozofia Nauki 19 (3):49.
  15.  50
    Against ontological reduction.Frederick W. Kroon - 1992 - Erkenntnis 36 (1):53 - 81.
  16. Ontology, reduction, emergence: A general frame. Authors' reply.C. Ulises Moulines & Stéphanie Ruphy - 2006 - Synthese 151 (3):313-334.
  17. Neo-logicism? An ontological reduction of mathematics to metaphysics.Edward N. Zalta - 2000 - Erkenntnis 53 (1-2):219-265.
    In this paper, we describe "metaphysical reductions", in which the well-defined terms and predicates of arbitrary mathematical theories are uniquely interpreted within an axiomatic, metaphysical theory of abstract objects. Once certain (constitutive) facts about a mathematical theory T have been added to the metaphysical theory of objects, theorems of the metaphysical theory yield both an analysis of the reference of the terms and predicates of T and an analysis of the truth of the sentences of T. The well-defined terms and (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  18.  43
    Intertheoretical Identity And Ontological Reductions.Ronald Loeffler - 2005 - Erkenntnis 62 (2):157-187.
    I argue that there are good reasons to assume that Quine’s theory of reference and ontology is incompatible with reductive statements – such as ‘Heat is molecular motion’ or ‘Rabbits are conglomerations of cells’. Apparently, reductive statements imply certain intertheoretical identities, yet Quine’s theory of reference and ontology seems incompatible with intertheoretical identities. I argued that treating, for the sake of reconciliation, reductive statements along the lines of Quine’s theory of an ontological reduction (which does not imply intertheoretical (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19.  45
    Quine and Whitehead on Ontological Reduction.Christine Holmgren & Leemon McHenry - 2012 - Process Studies 41 (2):261-286.
    W.V.O. Quine and A.N. Whitehead shared a dualistic ontology of concrete and abstract objects but differed sharply on the status of properties. In this essay, we explore Whitehead’s reasons for admitting properties into his ontology and Quine’s objections. In the course of examining Quine’s position we demonstrate some deficiencies in his position and conclude that in spite of his claims, neither space-time coordinate systems nor classes can do all the ontological work of properties.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20.  65
    Ontological Reduction[REVIEW]Harold Hodes - 1975 - Philosophical Review 84 (3):439.
  21. Reinhardt Grossmann's ontological reduction.T. L. S. Sprigge - 1975 - Noûs 9 (4):429-445.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  11
    Some troubles with ontological reduction.Donald Hockney - 1976 - Philosophical Books 17 (1):9-13.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Missing Elements and Missing Premises: A Combinatorial Argument for the Ontological Reduction of Chemistry.Robin Le Poidevin - 2005 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 56 (1):117-134.
    Does chemistry reduce to physics? If this means ‘Can we derive the laws of chemistry from the laws of physics?’, recent discussions suggest that the answer is ‘no’. But sup posing that kind of reduction—‘epistemological reduction’—to be impossible, the thesis of ontological reduction may still be true: that chemical properties are determined by more fundamental properties. However, even this thesis is threatened by some objections to the physicalist programme in the philosophy of mind, objections that generalize (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  24. Reinhardt Grossmann's "Ontological Reduction". [REVIEW]Eric B. Dayton - 1975 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 35 (4):582.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  56
    Conceptual reductions, truthmaker reductive explanations, and ontological reductions.Savvas Ioannou - 2022 - Synthese 200 (4):1-26.
    According to conceptual reductive accounts, if properties of one domain can be conceptually reduced to properties of another domain, then the former properties are ontologically reduced to the latter properties. I will argue that conceptual reductive accounts face problems: either they do not recognise that many higher-level properties are correlated with multiple physical properties, or they do not clarify how we can discover new truthmakers of sentences about a higher-level property. Still, there is another way to motivate ontological (...), the truthmaker reductive explanations (TRE). TRE can be given by using resources from John Heil’s truthmaker theory and the a priori entailment view or the a posteriori entailment view. I will argue that we can give these truthmaker reductive explanations if there are various less-than-perfectly similar physical properties that can be the truthmakers of sentences about higher-level properties and the physical similarity between them can explain why an irreducible higher-level property is not needed. (shrink)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  66
    An analysis of Quine's ``ontological reduction and the world of numbers''.St Iwan - 2000 - Erkenntnis 53 (1-2):195-218.
    A detailed analysis of Quine's paper on ontologicalreduction shows that the proxy-function requirement, in hischaracterization of the concept of ontological reduction,is superfluous for blocking Pythagoreism and inappropriate for a generalblockade of ontological monism.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. GROSSMAN, R. "Ontological Reduction". [REVIEW]R. Gallie - 1977 - Mind 86:624.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Pluralistic ontology and theory reduction in the physical sciences.Fritz Rohrlich - 1988 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 39 (3):295-312.
    It is demonstrated that the reduction of a physical theory S to another one, T, in the sense that S can be derived from T holds in general only for the mathematical framework. The interpretation of S and the associated central terms cannot all be derived from those of T because of the qualitative differences between the cognitive levels of S and T. Their cognitively autonomous status leads to an epistemic as well as an ontological pluralism. This pluralism (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  29. Reduction: ontological and linguistic facets.Carl Hempel - 1969 - In White Morgenbesser (ed.), Philosophy, Science, and Method: Essays in Honor of Ernest Nagel. St Martin's Press.
  30. Physicalism: Ontology, determination and reduction.Geoffrey Paul Hellman & Frank Wilson Thompson - 1975 - Journal of Philosophy 72 (October):551-64.
  31. Emergence and reduction in chemistry: Ontological or epistemological concepts?Lee McIntyre - 2007 - Synthese 155 (3):337-343.
    In this paper I argue that the ontological interpretation of the concepts of reduction and emergence is often misleading in the philosophy of science and should nearly always be eschewed in favor of an epistemological interpretation. As a paradigm case, an example is drawn from the philosophy of chemistry to illustrate the drawbacks of “ontological reduction” and “ontological emergence,” and the virtues of an epistemological interpretation of these concepts.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  32.  56
    Reduction and ontological unification: Reply to McCauley.Robert L. Causey - 1981 - Philosophy of Science 48 (2):228-231.
  33.  25
    An Ontological Sketch for Robust Non-Reductive Realists.Bruno Niederbacher - 2018 - Topoi 37 (4):549-559.
    The aim of this article is to draw a sketch of an ontology for Realist Non-Naturalist Cognitivists. A distinction is made between moral property-universals and moral property-particulars. It is argued, first, that moral property-universals have the same ontological status as non-moral property-universals; second, that moral property-universals have many instances in the spatio-temporal world; third that these moral property-instances or -particulars have the same ontological status as non-moral property-particulars.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34.  18
    Ontology and Reduction.Richard E. Grandy - 1978 - Southwestern Journal of Philosophy 9 (2):69-78.
  35.  17
    Ontology and Madness: The Question of Clinical and "Eidetic" Reduction.Jacques Garelli & Lois Oppenheim - 1983 - Substance 12 (2):21.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  9
    Ontology and Reduction.Richard E. Grandy - 1978 - Southwestern Journal of Philosophy 9 (2):69-78.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  12
    Reduction in Sartre’s Ontology.Imad Shouery - 1971 - Southwestern Journal of Philosophy 2 (1-2):47-53.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  5
    Reduction in Sartre’s Ontology.Imad Shouery - 1971 - Southwestern Journal of Philosophy 2 (1-2):47-53.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  86
    Incommensurability, Comparability, and Non-reductive Ontological Relations.José L. Falguera & Xavier Donato-Rodríguez - 2016 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 47 (1):37-58.
    We begin by highlighting some points related to Kuhn’s later thoughts on the incommensurability thesis and then show to what extent the standard version of the thesis given by the structuralist metatheory allows us to capture Kuhn’s ideas. Our main aim is to establish what constitutes the basis of comparability between incommensurable theories, even in cases of incommensurability with respect to theoretical and non-theoretical terms. We propose that comparability between incommensurable theories requires some connection between their respective ontologies that can (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  55
    Science and Ontology: From Merleau-Ponty's “Reduction” to Simondon's “Transduction”.Miguel de Beistegui - 2005 - Angelaki 10 (2):109 – 122.
    (2005). Science and Ontology. Angelaki: Vol. 10, continental philosophy and the sciences the french tradition issue editor: andrew aitken, pp. 109-122.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  41. How to minimize ontological commitments: a grounding-reductive approach.Reuben Sass - 2022 - Synthese 200 (4):1-22.
    Some revisionary ontologies are highly parsimonious: they posit far fewer entities than what we quantify over in ordinary discourse. The most radical examples are minimal ontologies, on which physical simples are the only things that exist. Highly parsimonious ontologies, and especially minimal ones, face the challenge of either accounting for the truth of our ordinary quantificational discourse, or paraphrasing such discourse away. Common strategies for addressing this challenge include classical reduction, paraphrase nihilism, and a distinction between ontological and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  14
    On Contextual and Ontological Aspects of Emergence and Reduction.Esteban Céspedes - 2020 - Eidos: Revista de Filosofía de la Universidad Del Norte 32:40-73.
    Although the interest about emergence has grown during the last years, there does not seem to be consensus on whether it is a non-trivial and interesting notion and whether the concept of reduction is relevant to its characterization. Another key issue is whether emergence should be understood as an epistemic notion or if there is a plausible ontological concept of emergence. The aim of this work is to propose an epistemic notion of contextual emergence on the basis of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. Non-reductive realization and the powers-based subset strategy.Jessica Wilson - 2011 - The Monist (Issue on Powers) 94 (1):121-154.
    I argue that an adequate account of non-reductive realization must guarantee satisfaction of a certain condition on the token causal powers associated with (instances of) realized and realizing entities---namely, what I call the 'Subset Condition on Causal Powers' (first introduced in Wilson 1999). In terms of states, the condition requires that the token powers had by a realized state on a given occasion be a proper subset of the token powers had by the state that realizes it on that occasion. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   103 citations  
  44. Reduction and Revelation in Aristotle's Science of Sensible Qualities.Robert Howton - manuscript
    I attribute to Aristotle a theory of sensible qualities that straddles the modern debate between reductive physicalist and primitivist theories of color. On the interpretation I defend, Aristotle identifies sensible qualities with the physical properties of sensibly qualified bodies in virtue of which they move and affect perceivers and sense media. Nevertheless, I argue, Aristotle thinks that the essential nature of these qualities is revealed in ordinary sense experience. From a modern perspective, the resulting picture of sensible qualities as simultaneously (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Non-reductive physicalism and degrees of freedom.Jessica Wilson - 2010 - British Journal for Philosophy of Science 61 (2):279-311.
    Some claim that Non- reductive Physicalism is an unstable position, on grounds that NRP either collapses into reductive physicalism, or expands into emergentism of a robust or ‘strong’ variety. I argue that this claim is unfounded, by attention to the notion of a degree of freedom—roughly, an independent parameter needed to characterize an entity as being in a state functionally relevant to its law-governed properties and behavior. I start by distinguishing three relations that may hold between the degrees of freedom (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  46.  55
    The Ambiguity of Reduction.Eric R. Scerri - 2007 - Hyle 13 (2):67 - 81.
    I claim that the question of whether chemistry is reduced to quantum mechanics is more ambiguous and multi-faceted than generally supposed. For example, chemistry appears to be both reduced and not reduced at the same time depending on the perspective that one adopts. Similarly, I argue that some conceptual issues in quantum mechanics are ambiguous and can only be laid to rest by embracing paradox and ambiguity rather than regarding them as obstacles to be overcome. Recent work in the (...) of chemistry is also reviewed, including discussions of the ontological reduction of chemistry and the question of the emergence of chemistry from physics. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  47. Approaches to reduction.Kenneth F. Schaffner - 1967 - Philosophy of Science 34 (2):137-147.
    Four current accounts of theory reduction are presented, first informally and then formally: (1) an account of direct theory reduction that is based on the contributions of Nagel, Woodger, and Quine, (2) an indirect reduction paradigm due to Kemeny and Oppenheim, (3) an "isomorphic model" schema traceable to Suppes, and (4) a theory of reduction that is based on the work of Popper, Feyerabend, and Kuhn. Reference is made, in an attempt to choose between these schemas, (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   228 citations  
  48. The Concept of Reduction.Raphael van Riel - 2014 - Heidelberg: Springer.
    This volume investigates the notion of reduction. Building on the idea that philosophers employ the term ‘reduction’ to reconcile diversity and directionality with unity, without relying on elimination, the book offers a powerful explication of an “ontological” notion of reduction the extension of which is (primarily) formed by properties, kinds, individuals, or processes. It argues that related notions of reduction, such as theory-reduction and functional reduction, should be defined in terms of this explication. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  49. The Limitations of Kim’s Reductive Physicalism in Accounting for Living Systems and an Alternative Nonreductionist Ontology.Slobodan Perovic - 2007 - Acta Biotheoretica 55 (3):243-267.
    Jaegwon Kim’s exclusion argument is a general ontological argument, applicable to any properties deemed supervenient on a microproperty basis, including biological properties. It implies that the causal power of any higher-level property must be reducible to the subset of the causal powers of its lower-level properties. Moreover, as Kim’s recent version of the argument indicates, a higher-level property can be causally efficient only to the extent of the efficiency of its micro-basis. In response, I argue that the ontology that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  12
    Ontological Indifference of Theories and Semantic Primacy of Sentences.Dirk Greimann - 2021 - Kriterion - Journal of Philosophy 35 (2):167-190.
    In his late philosophy, Quine generalized the structuralist view in the philosophy of mathematics that mathematical theories are indifferent to the ontology we choose for them. According to his ‘global structuralism’, the choice of objects does not matter to any scientific theory. In the literature, this doctrine is mainly understood as an epistemological thesis claiming that the empirical evidence for a theory does not depend on the choice of its objects. The present paper proposes a new interpretation suggested by Quine’s (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 989