Results for 'Jacquette Dale'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  25
    Parts: A Study in Ontology.Dale Jacquette - 1990 - Philosophy of Science 57 (3):540-542.
  2.  26
    Shakespeare's Philosophy: Discovering the Meaning Behind the Plays.Dale Jacquette - 2007 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 65 (4):421-424.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3.  47
    Alexius Meinong, The Shepherd of Non-Being.Dale Jacquette - 2015 - Cham: Imprint: Springer.
    This book explores the thought of Alexius Meinong, a philosopher known for his unconventional theory of reference and predication. The chapters cover a natural progression of topics, beginning with the origins of Gegenstandstheorie, Meinong's theory of objects, and his discovery of assumptions as a fourth category of mental states to supplement his teacher Franz Brentano's references to presentations, feelings, and judgments. The chapters explore further the meaning and metaphysics of fictional and other nonexistent intended objects, fine points in Meinongian object (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  4. Schopenhauer on Death.Dale Jacquette - 1999 - In Christopher Janaway (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Schopenhauer. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 293--317.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  5.  69
    David Hume's critique of infinity.Dale Jacquette - 2001 - Boston: Brill.
    The present work considers Hume's critique of infinity in historical context as a product of Enlightenment theory of knowledge, and assesses the prospects of ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  6.  18
    Applied Mathematics in the Sciences.Dale Jacquette - 2006 - Croatian Journal of Philosophy 6 (2):237-267.
    A complete philosophy of mathematics must address Paul Benacerraf’s dilemma. The requirements of a general semantics for the truth of mathematical theorems that coheres also with the meaning and truth conditions for non-mathematical sentences, according to Benacerraf, should ideally be coupled with an adequate epistemology for the discovery of mathematical knowledge. Standard approaches to the philosophy of mathematics are criticized against their own merits and against the background of Benacerraf’s dilemma, particularly with respect to the problem of understanding the distinction (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  69
    Is nondefectively justified true belief knowledge?Dale Jacquette - 1996 - Ratio 9 (2):115-127.
    The traditional conception of knowledge as justified true belief is refuted in two famous counterexamples by Edmund L. Gettier. Roderick M. Chisholm has attempted to rescue a version of the traditional conception by distinguishing between defective and nondefective kinds of justification, and redefining knowledge more specifically as nondefectively justified true belief. Chisholm's revised definition avoids Gettier's counterexamples, but goes too far in the opposite direction, imposing conditions that are too narrow and not jointly necessary for knowledge. Chisholm's definition excludes some (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  8. On defoliating meinong's jungle.Dale Jacquette - 1996 - Axiomathes 7 (1-2):17-42.
  9. Intentionality as a Conceptually Primitive Relation.Dale Jacquette - 2011 - Acta Analytica 26 (1):15-35.
    If conceptual analysis is possible for finite thinkers, then there must ultimately be a distinction between complex and primitive or irreducible and unanalyzable concepts, by which complex concepts are analyzed as relations among primitive concepts. This investigation considers the advantages of categorizing intentionality as a primitive rather than analyzable concept, in both a historical Brentanian context and in terms of contemporary philosophy of mind. Arguments in support of intentionality as a primitive relation are evaluated relative to objections, especially a recent (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  10. Moral dilemmas, disjunctive obligations, and Kant's principle that 'ought' implies 'can'.Dale Jacquette - 1991 - Synthese 88 (1):43 - 55.
    In moral dilemmas, where circumstances prevent two or more equally justified prima facie ethical requirements from being fulfilled, it is often maintained that, since the agent cannot do both, conjoint obligation is overridden by Kant's principle that ought implies can, but that the agent nevertheless has a disjunctive obligation to perform one of the otherwise obligatory actions or the other. Against this commonly received view, it is demonstrated that although Kant's ought-can principle may avoid logical inconsistency, the principle is incompatible (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  11.  23
    Brentano on Aristotle’s Psychology of the Active Intellect.Dale Jacquette - 2018 - In Christof Rapp, Colin G. King & Gerald Hartung (eds.), Aristotelian Studies in 19th Century Philosophy. Boston: De Gruyter. pp. 149-178.
  12.  11
    The Bloomsbury Companion to the Philosophy of Consciousness.Dale Jacquette (ed.) - 2017 - New York: Bloomsbury Academic.
    From Descartes and Cartesian mind-body dualism in the 17th century though to 21st-century concerns about artificial intelligence programming, The Bloomsbury Companion to the Philosophy of Consciousness presents a compelling history and up-to-date overview of this burgeoning subject area. Acknowledging that many of the original concepts of consciousness studies are found in writings of past thinkers, it begins with introductory overviews to the thought of Descartes through to Kant, covering Brentano's restoration of empiricism to philosophical psychology and the major figures of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. Philosophy of Logic.Dale Jacquette (ed.) - 2002 - Malden, Mass.: North Holland.
    The papers presented in this volume examine topics of central interest in contemporary philosophy of logic. They include reflections on the nature of logic and its relevance for philosophy today, and explore in depth developments in informal logic and the relation of informal to symbolic logic, mathematical metatheory and the limiting metatheorems, modal logic, many-valued logic, relevance and paraconsistent logic, free logics, extensional v. intensional logics, the logic of fiction, epistemic logic, formal logical and semantic paradoxes, the concept of truth, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  14.  64
    A Companion to Philosophical Logic.Dale Jacquette (ed.) - 2002 - Malden, MA, USA: Wiley-Blackwell.
    This collection of newly comissioned essays by international contributors offers a representative overview of the most important developments in contemporary philosophical logic. Presents controversies in philosophical implications and applications of formal symbolic logic. Surveys major trends and offers original insights.
  15. Damn the torpedoes.Dale Jacquette - 2003 - American Philosophical Quarterly 40 (4):249-250.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  6
    Axiom of Infinity and Plato’s Third Man.Dale Jacquette - 2010 - Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies 30 (1):5-13.
    As a contribution to the critical appreciation of a central thesis in Russell’s philosophical logic, I consider the Third Man objection to Platonic realism in the philosophy of mathematics, and argue that the Third Man infinite regress, for those who accept its assumptions, provides a worthy substitute for Whitehead and Russell’s Axiom of Infinity in positing a denumerably infinite set or series onto which other sets, series, and formal operations in the foundations of mathematics can be mapped.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  3
    How (Not) to Justify Induction.Dale Jacquette - 2011 - Kriterion - Journal of Philosophy 1 (24):1-18.
    A conceptual analysis of the problem of induction suggests that the difficulty of justifying probabilistic reasoning depends on a mistaken comparison between deductive and inductive inference. Inductive reasoning is accordingly thought to stand in need of special justification because it does not measure up to the standard of conditional absolute certainty guaranteed by deductive validity. When comparison is made, however, it appears that deductive reasoning is subject to a counterpart argument that is just as threatening to the justification of deductive (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. The blue banana trick: Dennett on Jackson's color scientist.Dale Jacquette - 1995 - Theoria 61 (3):217-30.
  19.  2
    Modality of Deductively Valid Inference.Dale Jacquette - 2002 - In A Companion to Philosophical Logic. Malden, MA, USA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 256–261.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Validity and Necessity The Validity Paradox Gödel Arithmetizing the Validity Paradox The Validity Paradox in S5 Validity, Necessity, and Deductive Inference.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  7
    Navigating Creative Inner Space on the Innocent Pleasures of Hashish.Dale Jacquette - 2010-09-24 - In Fritz Allhoff & Dale Jacquette (eds.), Cannabis Philosophy for Everyone. Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 121–136.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Creative Inner Space O True Apothecary! A Votary to Fond Desire Philosophers Gaining Altitude Insight and Delusion Life, Liberty, and the Pursuit of Cannabis.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Enhancing the Diagramming Method in Informal Logic.Dale Jacquette - 2011 - Argument: Biannual Philosophical Journal 1 (2):327-360.
    The argument diagramming method developed by Monroe C. Beardsley in his (1950) book Practical Logic, which has since become the gold standard for diagramming arguments in informal logic, makes it possible to map the relation between premises and conclusions of a chain of reasoning in relatively complex ways. The method has since been adapted and developed in a number of directions by many contemporary informal logicians and argumentation theorists. It has proved useful in practical applications and especially pedagogically in teaching (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  22.  35
    A Turing test conversation.Dale Jacquette - 1993 - Philosophy 68 (264):231-33.
  23. Schopenhauer on the ethics of suicide.Dale Jacquette - 2000 - Continental Philosophy Review 33 (1):43-58.
    The concept of death is of special importance in Schopenhauer''s metaphysics of appearance and Will. Death for Schopenhauer is the aim and purpose of life, that toward which life is directed, and the denial of the individual will to life. Despite his profound pessimism, Schopenhauer vehemently rejects suicide as an unworthy affirmation of the will to life by those who seek to escape rather than seek nondiscursive knowledge of Will in suffering. The only manner of self-destruction Schopenhauer finds philosophically acceptable (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  24.  14
    On the Relation of Informal to Symbolic Logic.Dale Jacquette - 2002 - In Philosophy of Logic. Malden, Mass.: North Holland. pp. 131.
  25. Aristotle on the value of friendship as a motivation for morality.Dale Jacquette - 2001 - Journal of Value Inquiry 35 (3):371-389.
    In Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle offers a solution to the problem of motivating morality based on his distinction between three types of friendship. I consider Aristotle's argument in detail, placing it in a context of similar concerns about the question of why we ought to be moral that ranges from Socrates' discussion of the ring of Gyges in Plato's Republic to Wittgenstein's distinction between internal and external rewards and punishments for action in Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Contrary to J.O. Urmson's conclusion that Aristotle's (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  26.  33
    Philosophy of mathematics: an anthology.Dale Jacquette (ed.) - 2002 - Malden, Mass.: Blackwell.
    This volume explores the central problems and exposes intriguing new directions in the philosophy of mathematics, making it an essential teaching resource, ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  27.  55
    The Cambridge companion to Brentano.Dale Jacquette (ed.) - 2004 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Franz Brentano (1838-1917) led an intellectual revolution that sought to revitalize German-language philosophy and to reverse its post-Kantian direction. His philosophy laid the groundwork for philosophy of science as it came to fruition in the Vienna Circle, and for phenomenology in the work of such figures as his student Edmund Husserl. This volume brings together newly commissioned chapters on his important work in theory of judgement, the reform of syllogistic logic, theory of intentionality, empirical descriptive psychology and phenomenology, theory of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  28. Frege on Identity as a Relation of Names.Dale Jacquette - 2011 - Metaphysica 12 (1):51-72.
    This essay offers a detailed philosophical criticism of Frege’s popular thesis that identity is a relation of names. I consider Frege’s position as articulated both in ‘On Sense and Reference’, and in the Grundgesetze, where he appears to take an objectual view of identity, arguing that in both cases Frege is clearly committed to the proposition that identity is a relation holding between names, on the grounds that two different things can never be identical. A counterexample to Frege’s thesis is (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  29.  22
    Wittgenstein's Manometer and the Private Language Argument.Dale Jacquette - 1998 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 15 (1):99 - 126.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  30. Metamathematical criteria for minds and machines.Dale Jacquette - 1987 - Erkenntnis 27 (1):1-16.
  31. Algebra of Theoretical Term Reductions in the Sciences.Dale Jacquette - 2014 - Symposion: Theoretical and Applied Inquiries in Philosophy and Social Sciences 1 (1): 51-67.
    An elementary algebra identifies conceptual and corresponding applicational limitations in John Kemeny and Paul Oppenheim’s (K-O) 1956 model of theoretical reduction in the sciences. The K-O model was once widely accepted, at least in spirit, but seems afterward to have been discredited, or in any event superceeded. Today, the K-O reduction model is seldom mentioned, except to clarify when a reduction in the Kemeny-Oppenheim sense is not intended. The present essay takes a fresh look at the basic mathematics of K-O (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32.  33
    Essay Review.Dale Jacquette & Volker Peckhaus - 1997 - History and Philosophy of Logic 18 (2):109-114.
    P. M. S. Hacker, Wittgenstein’s place in twentieth-century analytic philosophy:Oxford Blackwell, 1996. xviii + 346 pp. £50.00 $54.00 (cloth); £14.99 $21.95 (paper) Jarmo Pulkkinen, The threat of logical mathematism. A study on the critique of mathematical logic in Germany at the turn of the 20th century. Frankfurt a.M:Peter Lang, 1994. Scandinavian University Studies in the Humanities and Social Sciences; 7). 186 pp. 24 DM. ISBN 3-631-47409-1.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Anselm’s Metaphysics of Nonbeing.Dale Jacquette - 2012 - European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 4 (4):27--48.
    In his eleventh century dialogue De Casu Diaboli, Anselm seeks to avoid the problem of evil for theodicy and explain the fall of Satan as attributable to Satan’s own self-creating wrongful will. It is something, as such, for which God as Satan’s divine Creator cannot be held causally or morally responsible. The distinctions on which Anselm relies presuppose an interesting metaphysics of nonbeing, and of the nonbeing of evil in particular as a privation of good, worthy of critical philosophical investigation (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34. Conundrums of conditionals in contraposition.Dale Jacquette - 1999 - Nordic Journal of Philosophical Logic 4:117-126.
  35. Meditations on meinong's golden mountain.Dale Jacquette - 2008 - In Nicholas Griffin & Dale Jacquette (eds.), Russell Vs. Meinong: The Legacy of "on Denoting". London and New York: Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  36. Schopenhauer's proof that thing-in-itself is will.Dale Jacquette - 2007 - Kantian Review 12 (2):76-108.
    In a bold series of pronouncements, Arthur Schopenhauer maintains that the Kantian thing-in-itself is Will. The division between the world as Will and representation, with its impressive array of implications, is Schopenhauer's most important and distinctive contribution to metaphysics. To understand what Schopenhauer means by ‘Will’ as opposed to the empirical ‘will’, and his reasons for identifying thing-in-itself with Will, we must look in detail at two related arguments by which Schopenhauer proposes to link these concepts. The arguments appear in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  37.  29
    Subalternation and existence presuppositions in an unconventionally formalized canonical square of opposition.Dale Jacquette - 2016 - Logica Universalis 10 (2-3):191-213.
    An unconventional formalization of the canonical square of opposition in the notation of classical symbolic logic secures all but one of the canonical square’s grid of logical interrelations between four A-E-I-O categorical sentence types. The canonical square is first formalized in the functional calculus in Frege’s Begriffsschrift, from which it can be directly transcribed into the syntax of contemporary symbolic logic. Difficulties in received formalizations of the canonical square motivate translating I categoricals, ‘Some S is P’, into symbolic logical notation, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  38.  58
    Schopenhauer, Philosophy and the Arts.Dale Jacquette (ed.) - 1996 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This collection brings together thirteen essays by some of the most respected contemporary scholars of Schopenhauer's aesthetics from a wide spectrum of philosophical perspectives. The dynamics of the empirical will and Will as a thing-in-itself in the interplay of Schopenhauer's metaphysics and philosophy of fine art has important implications for the freedom, salvation and tragic suffering of the artist, the representation of Platonic Ideas in art, and the role of artistic inspiration, emotion and aesthetic pleasure in the beautiful and sublime. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  39. Meinongian Logic.Dale Jacquette - 1999 - Studia Logica 63 (2):280-285.
  40.  5
    Cannabis - Philosophy for Everyone: What were we just talking about?Dale Jacquette (ed.) - 2010 - Wiley.
    The debate on the status and legality of cannabis continues to gain momentum. Here, personal anecdotes combined with academic and scientific reports combine to sharpen some of the fascinating philosophical issues associated with cannabis use. A frank, professionally informed and playful discussion of cannabis usage in relation to philosophical inquiry Considers the meaning of a ‘high’, the morality of smoking marijuana for pleasure, the slippery slope to more dangerous drugs, and the human drive to alter our consciousness Not only incorporates (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  61
    Adventures in the chinese room.Dale Jacquette - 1989 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 49 (June):605-23.
  42.  23
    Intentionality and Stich's theory of brain sentence syntax.Dale Jacquette - 1990 - Philosophical Quarterly 40 (159):169-82.
  43.  52
    Who's afraid of the Turing test?Dale Jacquette - 1993 - Behavior and Philosophy 20 (2):63-74.
    The Turing Test is a verbal-behavioral operational criterion of artificial intelligence. If a machine can participate in question–and–answer conversation adequately enough to deceive an intelligent interlocutor, then it has intelligent information processing abilities. Robert M. French has argued that recent discoveries in cognitive science about subcognitive processes involving associational primings prove that the Turing Test cannot provide a satisfactory criterion of machine intelligence, that Turing's prediction concerning the feasibility of building machines to play the imitation game successfully is false, and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44.  28
    The Hidden Logic of Slippery Slope Arguments.Dale Jacquette - 1989 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 22 (1):59 - 70.
    The argument from incremental differences among objects with indefinite property-Complement demarcations arranged along a continuum is known classically as the sorites or slippery slope fallacy. The inferences are typically unsound, And may contain structural logical defects, Though the precise source of error is the subject of wide-Ranging philosophical dispute. In this treatment, Slippery slopes are reduced to a single category of logically valid (but sometimes unsound) conditional chains of hypothetical syllogism. The analysis provides a framework for distinguishing between unsound slippery (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  45.  12
    Philosophy, Psychology, and Psychologism: Critical and Historical Readings on the Psychological Turn in Philosophy.Dale Jacquette (ed.) - 2003 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer Verlag.
    This book presents a remarkable diversity of contemporary opinions on the prospects of addressing philosophical topics from a psychological perspective. It considers the history and philosophical merits of psychologism, and looks systematically at psychologism in phenomenology, cognitive science, epistemology, logic, philosophy of language, philosophical semantics, and artificial intelligence.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  46.  63
    Brentano's Concept of Intentionality.Dale Jacquette - 2004 - In The Cambridge companion to Brentano. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 98--130.
  47.  5
    Logic and How It Gets That Way.Dale Jacquette - 2008 - Routledge.
    In this challenging and provocative analysis, Dale Jacquette argues that contemporary philosophy labours under a number of historically inherited delusions about the nature of logic and the philosophical significance of certain formal properties of specific types of logical constructions. Exposing some of the key misconceptions about formal symbolic logic and its relation to thought, language and the world, Jacquette clears the ground of some very well-entrenched philosophical doctrines about the nature of logic, including some of the most (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  48.  30
    Demonstratives and the logic of the self.Dale Jacquette - 1999 - Philosophical Papers 28 (1):1-23.
  49.  7
    Explanatory limitations of sociobiology.Dale Jacquette - 1988 - Journal of Social Philosophy 19 (2):56-62.
  50.  30
    Justification and Truth Conditions in the Concept of Knowledge.Dale Jacquette - 2012 - Logos and Episteme 3 (3):429-447.
    The traditional concept of propositional knowledge as justified true belief (JTB), even when modified, typically in its justification condition, to avoid Gettier-typecounterexamples, remains subject to a variety of criticisms. The redefinition proposed here puts pressure more specifically on the concept of truth as redundant in light of and inaccessible beyond the most robust requirements of best justification. Best-J is defined as justification for believing in a proposition’s truth where there is no better countermanding justification for believing instead the proposition’s negation. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 1000