Results for 'Hob–Nob sentences'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Intentional identity and descriptions.William Lanier - 2014 - Philosophical Studies 170 (2):289-302.
    What is the semantic contribution of anaphoric links in sentences like, ‘A physicist was late to the party. He brought some bongos’? A natural first thought is that the passage entails a wide-scope existential claim that there is something that both (i) was late to the party and (ii) brought some bongos. Intentional identity sentences are counter-examples to this natural thought applied to anaphora in general. Some have tried to rescue the thought and accommodate the counter-examples by positing (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  2.  20
    Hob, Nob, and Hecate: The Problem of Quantifying Out.Michael Pendlebury - 1982 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 60 (4):346 – 354.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  3. Salmon on Hob and Nob.David Friedell - 2013 - Philosophical Studies 165 (1):213-220.
    Nathan Salmon appeals to his theory of mythical objects as part of an attempt to solve Geach’s Hob–Nob puzzle. In this paper I argue that, even if Salmon’s theory of mythical objects is correct, his attempt to solve the puzzle is unsuccessful. I also refute an original variant of his proposal. The discussion indicates that it is difficult (if not impossible) to devise a genuine solution to the puzzle that relies on mythical objects.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  4. A Relationist Theory of Intentional Identity.Dilip Ninan - forthcoming - Mind.
    This essay argues for a 'relationist' treatment of intentional identity sentences like (1) "Hob believes that a witch blighted Bob's mare and Nob believes that she killed Cob's sow" (Geach 1967). According to relationism, facts of the form "a believes that p and b believes that q" are not in general reducible to facts of the form "c believes that r". We first argue that extant, non-relationist treatments of intentional identity are unsatisfactory, and then go on to motivate and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. No Identity Without an Entity.Luke Manning - 2015 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 96 (1):279-305.
    Peter Geach's puzzle of intentional identity is to explain how the claim ‘Hob thinks a witch has blighted Bob's mare, and Nob wonders whether she killed Cob's sow’ is compatible with there being no such witch. I clarify the puzzle and reduce it to the familiar problem of negative existentials. That problem is a paradox of representations that seem to include denials of commitment , to carry commitment to what they deny commitment to, and to be true. The best proposed (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  6. Intentional Identity.Walter Edelberg - 1984 - Dissertation, University of Pittsburgh
    Certain belief-ascription statements suggest that people can think about the same object, even if that object doesn't exist. Peter Geach, who in 1967 first discussed these statements, gave them the name of statements of intentional identity. In an especially puzzling form of these statements, a pronoun in one belief clause has its antecedent in another: "Hob believes a witch is F, and Nob believes she is G." In this form, the statements raise three interesting problems. They generate puzzles for a (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7. High efficiency and low specific mass mixed inert gas non-equilibrium MHD single system for space power.Nob Harada - 2005 - In Alan F. Blackwell & David MacKay (eds.), Power. Cambridge University Press. pp. 3.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. Ivano caponigro and daphna Heller.Specificational Sentences - 2007 - In Chris Barker & Pauline I. Jacobson (eds.), Direct Compositionality. Oxford University Press. pp. 14--237.
  9. John Lyons.Locative Sentences - forthcoming - Foundations of Language.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Many toys are in box.Existential Sentences - 1971 - Foundations of Language: International Journal of Language and Philosophy 7.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Philip Hugly and Charles Sayward.Null Sentences - 1999 - Iyyun 48:23.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. La boadi.Existential Sentences In Akan - 1971 - Foundations of Language 7:19.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. Lisa Green/Aspectual be–type Constructions and Coercion in African American English Yoad Winter/Distributivity and Dependency Instructions for Authors.Pauline Jacobson, Paycheck Pronouns, Bach-Peters Sentences, Inflectional Head, Thomas Ede Zimmermann, Free Choice Disjunction, Epistemic Possibility, Sigrid Beck & Uli Sauerland - 2000 - Natural Language Semantics 8 (373).
  14. Practical Moore Sentences.Matthew Mandelkern - 2019 - Noûs 55 (1):39-61.
    I discuss what I call practical Moore sentences: sentences like ‘You must close your door, but I don’t know whether you will’, which combine an order together with an avowal of agnosticism about whether the order will be obeyed. I show that practical Moore sentences are generally infelicitous. But this infelicity is surprising: it seems like there should be nothing wrong with giving someone an order while acknowledging that you do not know whether it will obeyed. I (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  15.  55
    Reduction sentences and metaphysics.Manley H. Thompson - 1941 - Philosophical Review 50 (6):610-615.
  16. Non-descriptive negation for normative sentences.Andrew Alwood - 2016 - Philosophical Quarterly 66 (262):1-25.
    Frege-Geach worries about embedding and composition have plagued metaethical theories like emotivism, prescriptivism and expressivism. The sharpened point of such criticism has come to focus on whether negation and inconsistency have to be understood in descriptivist terms. Because they reject descriptivism, these theories must offer a non-standard account of the meanings of ethical and normative sentences as well as related semantic facts, such as why certain sentences are inconsistent with each other. This paper fills out such a solution (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  17.  93
    Parsing ‘if’-sentences.V. H. Dudman - 1984 - Analysis 44 (4):145-153.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  18. Enlightened semantics for simple sentences.G. Forbes - 1999 - Analysis 59 (2):86-91.
  19.  52
    Pragmatic Strengthening in Plural Predications and Donkey Sentences.Manfred Krifka - unknown
    The classical analysis of donkey sentences like (1.a,b) in Kamp (1981) and Heim (1982) assigns them truth conditions as given in (2.a). That is, they are treated as quantifications over farmer-donkey pairs. Partee (1984) and Kadmon (1987) have pointed out that the proper reading of (1.b), and a preferred reading of (1.a), is rather a quantification over farmers, as illustrated in (2.b).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  20. Propositions, opinions, sentences, and facts.C. J. Ducasse - 1940 - Journal of Philosophy 37 (26):701-711.
  21.  40
    The∀∃ theory of Peano Σ1 sentences.Per Lindström & V. Yu Shavrukov - 2008 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 8 (2):251-280.
    We present a decision procedure for the ∀∃ theory of the lattice of Σ1 sentences of Peano Arithmetic.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  22.  65
    Memory for tacit implications of sentences.Marcia K. Johnson, John D. Bransford & Susan K. Solomon - 1973 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 98 (1):203.
  23.  79
    Craig's theorem, Ramsey-sentences, and scientific instrumentalism.James W. Cornman - 1972 - Synthese 25 (1-2):82 - 128.
  24.  7
    Propositions, Opinions, Sentences, and Facts.C. J. Ducasse - 1941 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 6 (2):68-69.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  25.  32
    Acquiring and Producing Sentences: Whether Learners Use Verb-Specific or Verb-General Information Depends on Cue Validity.Malathi Thothathiri & Michelle G. Rattinger - 2016 - Frontiers in Psychology 7.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  26. Polarity in Natural Language: Predication, Quantification and Negation in Particular and Characterizing Sentences.Sebastian Löbner - 2000 - Linguistics and Philosophy 23 (3):213-308.
    The present paper is an attempt at the investigation of the nature of polarity contrast in natural languages. Truth conditions for natural language sentences are incomplete unless they include a proper definition of the conditions under which they are false. It is argued that the tertium non datur principle of classical bivalent logical systems is empirically invalid for natural languages: falsity cannot be equated with non-truth. Lacking a direct intuition about the conditions under which a sentence is false, we (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  27.  6
    The Principle of Least Effort and Comprehension of Spoken Sentences by Younger and Older Adults.Nicolai D. Ayasse, Alana J. Hodson & Arthur Wingfield - 2021 - Frontiers in Psychology 12.
    There is considerable evidence that listeners’ understanding of a spoken sentence need not always follow from a full analysis of the words and syntax of the utterance. Rather, listeners may instead conduct a superficial analysis, sampling some words and using presumed plausibility to arrive at an understanding of the sentence meaning. Because this latter strategy occurs more often for sentences with complex syntax that place a heavier processing burden on the listener than sentences with simpler syntax, shallow processing (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  23
    Generic Terms and Generic Sentences.Greg N. Carlson - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (3):858-859.
  29. The logical form of action sentences.Donald Davidson - 1967 - In Nicholas Rescher (ed.), The Logic of Decision and Action. University of Pittsburgh Press. pp. 81--95.
  30.  42
    DeepRhole: deep learning for rhetorical role labeling of sentences in legal case documents.Paheli Bhattacharya, Shounak Paul, Kripabandhu Ghosh, Saptarshi Ghosh & Adam Wyner - 2021 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 31 (1):53-90.
    The task of rhetorical role labeling is to assign labels (such as Fact, Argument, Final Judgement, etc.) to sentences of a court case document. Rhetorical role labeling is an important problem in the field of Legal Analytics, since it can aid in various downstream tasks as well as enhances the readability of lengthy case documents. The task is challenging as case documents are highly various in structure and the rhetorical labels are often subjective. Previous works for automatic rhetorical role (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  31. On the presuppositions of number sentences.Katharina Felka - 2015 - Synthese 192 (5):1393-1412.
    This paper is concerned with an intuitive contrast that arises when we consider sentences containing empty definite descriptions. A sentence like ‘The king of France is bald’ appears neither true nor false, while a sentence like ‘My friend was visited by the king of France’ appears false. Recently, Stephen Yablo has suggested an account of this intuitive contrast. Yablo’s account is particularly interesting, since it has important consequences for the ontological commitments of number sentences like ‘The number of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  32.  14
    A remark on equivalent Rosser sentences.Christopher von Bülow - 2008 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 151 (1):62-67.
    An oversight in Guaspari and Solovay’s “Rosser sentences” [D. Guaspari, R.M. Solovay, Rosser sentences, Annals of Mathematical Logic 16 81–99] is pointed out and emended. It concerns the premisses of their proof that there are standard proof predicates all of whose Rosser sentences are provably equivalent. The result holds up, but the premisses mentioned in the paper have to be strengthened somewhat.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  33.  31
    The comprehension of anomalous sentences: Evidence from structural priming.Iva Ivanova, Martin J. Pickering, Holly P. Branigan, Janet F. McLean & Albert Costa - 2012 - Cognition 122 (2):193-209.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  34.  18
    Generalizations of enumeration reducibility using recursive infinitary propositional sentences.C. J. Ash - 1992 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 58 (3):173-184.
    Ash, C.J., Generalizations of enumeration reducibility using recursive infinitary propositional sentences, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 58 173–184. We consider the relation between sets A and B that for every set S if A is Σ0α in S then B is Σ0β in S. We show that this is equivalent to the condition that B is definable from A in a particular way involving recursive infinitary propositional sentences. When α = β = 1, this condition is that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  35.  20
    On the probability of sentences.A. I. Dale - 1978 - Philosophical Papers 7 (2):69-72.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  41
    Can indexical sentences stand in logical relations?Yehoshua Bar-Hillel - 1963 - Philosophical Studies 14 (6):87 - 90.
  37.  5
    The logical status of "God" and the function of theological sentences.Michael Durrant - 1973 - [New York]: St. Martins Press.
  38.  72
    A Comparative Taxonomy of Medieval and Modern Approaches to Liar Sentences.C. Dutilh Novaes - 2008 - History and Philosophy of Logic 29 (3):227-261.
    Two periods in the history of logic and philosophy are characterized notably by vivid interest in self-referential paradoxical sentences in general, and Liar sentences in particular: the later medieval period (roughly from the 12th to the 15th century) and the last 100 years. In this paper, I undertake a comparative taxonomy of these two traditions. I outline and discuss eight main approaches to Liar sentences in the medieval tradition, and compare them to the most influential modern approaches (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  39. On the logic of perception sentences.Esa Saarinen - 1982 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 11 (1-2):72-76.
    In this paper I discuss perception sentences of the following there syn- tactic types: John saw Mary John saw Mary run John saw that Mary run Our aim is to present an interpretation of Hintikka's logic of perception, extend it to case and dened the approach against the cirticism levelled against it by Jon Barwise.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  40. Motivating Wittgenstein's Perspective on Mathematical Sentences as Norms.Simon Friederich - 2011 - Philosophia Mathematica 19 (1):1-19.
    The later Wittgenstein’s perspective on mathematical sentences as norms is motivated for sentences belonging to Hilbertian axiomatic systems where the axioms are treated as implicit definitions. It is shown that in this approach the axioms are employed as norms in that they function as standards of what counts as using the concepts involved. This normative dimension of their mode of use, it is argued, is inherited by the theorems derived from them. Having been motivated along these lines, Wittgenstein’s (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  41.  25
    Comprehension of reversible sentences in “agrammatism”: a meta-analysis.Rita Sloan Berndt, Charlotte C. Mitchum & Anne N. Haendiges - 1996 - Cognition 58 (3):289-308.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  42. Looking for structure in all the wrong places: Ramsey sentences, multiple realisability, and structure.Angelo Cei & Steven French - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 37 (4):633-655.
    ‘Epistemic structural realism’ (ESR) insists that all that we know of the world is its structure, and that the ‘nature’ of the underlying elements remains hidden. With structure represented via Ramsey sentences, the question arises as to how ‘hidden natures’ might also be represented. If the Ramsey sentence describes a class of realisers for the relevant theory, one way of answering this question is through the notion of multiple realisability. We explore this answer in the context of the work (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  43.  21
    The Interpretation of Classically Quantified Sentences: A Set-Theoretic Approach.Guy Politzer, Jean-Baptiste Van der Henst, Claire Delle Luche & Ira A. Noveck - 2006 - Cognitive Science 30 (4):691-723.
    We present a set-theoretic model of the mental representation of classically quantified sentences (All P are Q, Some P are Q, Some P are not Q, and No P are Q). We take inclusion, exclusion, and their negations to be primitive concepts. We show that although these sentences are known to have a diagrammatic expres- sion (in the form of the Gergonne circles) that constitutes a semantic representation, these concepts can also be expressed syntactically in the form of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44.  11
    Computable Scott sentences and the weak Whitehead problem for finitely presented groups.Gianluca Paolini - 2024 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 175 (7):103441.
  45. The Interpretation of Classically Quantified Sentences: A set-theoretic approach.Guy Politzer, Jean-Baptiste Van Der Henst, Claire Delle Luche & Ira Noveck - 2006 - Cognitive Science 30 (4):691-723.
    We present a set-theoretic model of the mental representation of classically quantified sentences (All P are Q, Some P are Q, Some P are not Q, and No P are Q). We take inclusion, exclusion, and their negations to be primitive concepts. It is shown that, although these sentences are known to have a diagrammatic expression (in the form of the Gergonne circles) which constitute a semantic representation, these concepts can also be expressed syntactically in the form of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  80
    Simple Trinitarianism and Feature-Placing Sentences.Shieva Kleinschmidt - 2016 - Faith and Philosophy 33 (3):257-277.
    Some Trinitarians, such as Thomas Aquinas, wish to claim that God is mereologically simple; that is, God has no parts distinct from Himself. In this paper, I present Simple Trinitarianism, a view that takes God to be simple but, diverging from Aquinas, does not identify the Father, Son, and Holy Spirit with anything in our ontology. Nonetheless, Simple Trinitarians would like Trinitarian sentences to be true; thus, they must give a non-standard semantics for those sentences. I will focus (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  47.  54
    The date-analysis of tensed sentences.Clifford Williams - 1992 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 70 (2):198 – 203.
    Advocates of the A-Theory of time argue that pastness, presentness and futurity are mind-independent properties of events on the grounds that tensed and tenseless sentences are not semantically equivalent. However, their arguments for semantic nonequivalence do not entail state of affairs nonequivalence, and this latter nonequivalence must also obtain in order for the A-Theory to be true. The situation is like arguing that hereness and thisness are extra, mind-independent properties of places and objects on the grounds that sentences (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48.  66
    Believing in sentences.John Bigelow - 1980 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 58 (1):11 – 18.
  49.  30
    Motivating Wittgenstein’s Perspective on Mathematical Sentences as Norms†.Simon Friederich - 2010 - Philosophia Mathematica 18 (3):1-19.
    The later Wittgenstein’s perspective on mathematical sentences as norms is motivated for sentences belonging to Hilbertian axiomatic systems where the axioms are treated as implicit definitions. It is shown that in this approach the axioms are employed as norms in that they function as standards of what counts as using the concepts involved. This normative dimension of their mode of use, it is argued, is inherited by the theorems derived from them. Having been motivated along these lines, Wittgenstein’s (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  50.  41
    The ∀∃ theory of peano σ1 sentences.Per Lindström & V. Yu Shavrukov - 2008 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 8 (2):251-280.
    We present a decision procedure for the ∀∃ theory of the lattice of Σ1 sentences of Peano Arithmetic.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000